“The Book of Why”的版本间的差异
(建立内容为“待建立”的新页面) |
|||
第1行: | 第1行: | ||
− | + | 此词条由因果科学读书会词条梳理志愿者雨轩翻译审校,未经专家审核,带来阅读不便,请见谅。 | |
+ | |||
+ | 第一段英文为原维基百科的内容,第二段英文为摘除多余格式的英文原文,方便大家审校,以及第三段为机器翻译的中文。 | ||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | The Book of Why: The New Science of Cause and Effect is a 2018 nonfiction book by computer scientist Judea Pearl and writer Dana Mackenzie. The book explores the subject of causality and causal inference from statistical and philosophical points of view for a general audience. | ||
+ | [[文件:The Book of Why.jpg|缩略图]] | ||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | Contents | ||
+ | |||
+ | 1Summary | ||
+ | |||
+ | 1.1Introduction: Mind over Data | ||
+ | |||
+ | 1.2Chapter 1: The Ladder of Causation | ||
+ | |||
+ | 1.3Chapter 2: From Buccaneers to Guinea Pigs: The Genesis of Causal Inference | ||
+ | |||
+ | 1.4Chapter 3: From Evidence to Causes: Reverend [Thomas Bayes|Bayes] meets Mr Holmes | ||
+ | |||
+ | 1.5Chapter 4: Confounding and Deconfounding, or, Slaying the Lurking Variable | ||
+ | |||
+ | 1.6Chapter 5: The Smoke-filled Debate: Clearing the Air | ||
+ | |||
+ | 1.7Chapter 6: Paradoxes Galore! | ||
+ | |||
+ | 1.8Chapter 7: Beyond Adjustment: The Conquest of Mount Intervention | ||
+ | |||
+ | 1.9Chapter 8: Counterfactuals: Mining worlds that could have been | ||
+ | |||
+ | 1.10Chapter 9: Mediation: The Search for Mechanism | ||
+ | |||
+ | 1.11Chapter 10: Big Data, Artificial Intelligence and the Big Questions | ||
+ | |||
+ | 2Reviews | ||
+ | |||
+ | 3References | ||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | The book consists of ten chapters and an introduction. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Introduction: Mind over Data | ||
+ | |||
+ | The introduction describes the inadequacy of early 20th century statistical methods at making statements about causal relationships between variables. The authors then describe what they term 'The Causal Revolution', which started in the middle of the 20th century, and provided new conceptual and mathematical tools for describing causal relationships. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Chapter 1: The Ladder of Causation | ||
+ | |||
+ | Chapter 1 introduces the 'ladder of causation' - a diagram used to illustrate the three levels of causal reasoning. The first level is named 'Association', which discusses associations between variables. Questions such as 'is variable X associated with variable Y?' can be answered at this level. However, crucially, causality is not invoked. An example of reasoning on this first level is the observation that a crowing rooster is associated with the sunrise. However, this kind of reasoning cannot describe causal relations, for example, we cannot say whether the sunrise causes the rooster to crow, or whether the rooster causes the sun to rise. Many of the early 20th century statistical tools, such as correlation and regression operate on this level. | ||
+ | |||
+ | The second level (or 'rung') on the ladder of causation is labelled 'Intervention'. Reasoning on this level answers questions of the form 'if I make the intervention X, how will this affect the probability of the outcome Y?'. For example, the question 'does smoking increase my chance of lung cancer?' exists on the second level of the ladder of causation. This kind of reasoning invokes causality and can be used to investigate more questions than the reasoning of the first rung. | ||
+ | |||
+ | The third rung of the ladder of causation is labelled 'Counterfactuals' and involves answering questions which ask what might have been, had circumstances been different. Such reasoning invokes causality to a greater degree than the previous level. An example counterfactual question given in the book is 'Would Kennedy be alive if Oswald had not killed him?' | ||
+ | |||
+ | Chapter 2: From Buccaneers to Guinea Pigs: The Genesis of Causal Inference | ||
+ | |||
+ | Chapter 2 starts with a brief summary of the contributions of Francis Galton and Karl Pearson to the development of statistics in the late 19th Century and early 20th Centuries. The authors blame Galton for keeping the study of statistics on the first rung of the ladder of causation and discouraging any discussion of causality in statistics. Causal analysis using path diagrams is then introduced through the explanations of the work of Sewall Wright. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Chapter 3: From Evidence to Causes: Reverend [Thomas Bayes|Bayes] meets Mr Holmes[edit] | ||
+ | |||
+ | Chapter 3 provides an introduction to Bayes Theorem. Then Bayesian Networks are introduced. Finally, the links between Baysian networks and causal diagrams are discussed. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Chapter 4: Confounding and Deconfounding, or, Slaying the Lurking Variable[edit] | ||
+ | |||
+ | This chapter introduces the idea of confounding and describes how causal diagrams can be used to identify confounding variables and determine their effect. Pearl explains that randomized controlled trials (RCTs) can be used to nullify the effect of confounders, but shows that, provided one has a causal model of confounding, an RCT does not necessarily have to be performed to get results. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Chapter 5: The Smoke-filled Debate: Clearing the Air[edit] | ||
+ | |||
+ | This chapter takes a historical approach to the question 'does smoking cause lung cancer?', focusing on the arguments made by Abraham Lilienfeld, Jacob Yerushalmy, Ronald Fisher and Jerome Cornfield. The authors explain that, though cigarette smoking was clearly correlated with lung cancer, some, such as Fisher and Yerushalmy, believed that the two variables were confounded and argued against the hypothesis that cigarettes caused the cancer. The authors then explain how causal reasoning (as developed in the rest of the book) can be used to argue that cigarettes do indeed cause cancer. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Chapter 6: Paradoxes Galore![edit] | ||
+ | |||
+ | This chapter examines several paradoxes, including the Monty Hall Problem, Simpson's paradox, Berkson's paradox and Lord's paradox. The authors show how these paradoxes can be resolved using causal reasoning. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Chapter 7: Beyond Adjustment: The Conquest of Mount Intervention[edit] | ||
+ | |||
+ | This chapter looks at the 'second rung' of the ladder of causation introduced in chapter 1. The authors describe how to use causal diagrams to ascertain the causal effect of performing interventions (eg. smoking) on outcomes (such as lung cancer). The 'front-door criterion' and the 'do-calculus' are introduced as tools for doing this. The chapter finishes with two examples, used to introduce the use of instrumental variables to estimate causal relationships. The first is John Snow's discovery that cholera is caused by unsanitary water supplies. The second is the relationship between cholesterol levels and likelihood of a heart attack. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Chapter 8: Counterfactuals: Mining worlds that could have been[edit] | ||
+ | |||
+ | This chapter examines the third rung of the ladder of causation: counterfactuals. The chapter introduces 'structural causal models', which allow reasoning about counterfactuals in a way that traditional (non-causal) statistics does not. Then, the applications of counterfactual reasoning are explored in the areas of climate science and the law. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Chapter 9: Mediation: The Search for Mechanism[edit] | ||
+ | |||
+ | This chapter discusses mediation: the mechanism by which a cause leads to an effect. The authors discuss the work of Barbara Stoddard Burks on the causes of intelligence of children, the 'algebra for all' policy by Chicago public schools, and the use of tourniquets to treat combat wounds. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Chapter 10: Big Data, Artificial Intelligence and the Big Questions[edit] | ||
+ | |||
+ | The final chapter discusses the use of causal reasoning in big data and artificial intelligence (AI) and the philosophical problem that AI would have to reflect on its own actions, which requires counterfactual (and therefore causal) reasoning. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Reviews[edit] | ||
+ | |||
+ | Scientific Background, excerpts, errata, and a list of 37 reviews of The Book of Why is provided on Judea Pearl's web page | ||
+ | |||
+ | The Book of Why was reviewed by Jonathan Knee in The New York Times. The review was positive, with Knee calling the book "illuminating". However, he describes some parts of the book as "challenging", stating that the book is "not always fully accessible to readers who do not share the author's fondness for equations". | ||
+ | |||
+ | Tim Maudlin gave the book a mixed review in The Boston Review, calling it a "splendid overview of the state of the art in causal analysis". However, Maudlin criticizes the inclusion of "counterfactuals" as separate rung on the "ladder of causation", stating counterfactuals are so closely entwined with causal claims that it is not possible to think causally but not counterfactually". Maudlin also criticizes the section on free will for its "imprecision and lack of familiarity with the philosophical literature". Finally he points to the work of several scientists (including Clark Glymour) who developed similar ideas to Pearl, and claims that Pearl "could have saved himself literally years of effort had he been apprised of this work". | ||
+ | |||
+ | In a rebuttal, Pearl notes that, not only was he apprised of these scientists' work, but he actively collaborated in its creation. Additionally, the key developments described in The Book of Why, among them (1) identification analysis, (2) the algorithmization of counterfactuals, (3) mediation analysis, and (4) external validity, far surpass the narrow philosophical literature of the pre-2000 era. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Zoe Hackett, writing in Chemistry World, gave The Book of Why a positive review, with the caveat that "[i]t requires concentration, and a studious effort to work through the mind-bending statistical problems posited in the text". The review concludes by stating that "[t]his book is a must for any serious student of philosophy of science, and should be required reading for any first-year undergraduate statistics class". | ||
+ | |||
+ | Lisa R. Goldberg wrote a detailed, technical review in Notices of the American Mathematical Society. | ||
+ | |||
+ | References[edit] | ||
+ | |||
+ | Judea Pearl's information page for The Book of Why, <nowiki>http://bayes.cs.ucla.edu/WHY/</nowiki> | ||
+ | |||
+ | "Review: The Book of Why Examines the Science of Cause and Effect". The New York Times. 1 June 2018. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Tim Maudlin (4 September 2019). "The Why of the World". The Boston Review. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Zoe Hackett (18 January 2019). "The Book of Why: The New Science of Cause and Effect". Chemistry World. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Lisa R. Goldberg (August 2019). "The Book of Why" (PDF). Notices of the American Mathematical Society. |
2022年5月4日 (三) 17:00的版本
此词条由因果科学读书会词条梳理志愿者雨轩翻译审校,未经专家审核,带来阅读不便,请见谅。
第一段英文为原维基百科的内容,第二段英文为摘除多余格式的英文原文,方便大家审校,以及第三段为机器翻译的中文。
The Book of Why: The New Science of Cause and Effect is a 2018 nonfiction book by computer scientist Judea Pearl and writer Dana Mackenzie. The book explores the subject of causality and causal inference from statistical and philosophical points of view for a general audience.
Contents
1Summary
1.1Introduction: Mind over Data
1.2Chapter 1: The Ladder of Causation
1.3Chapter 2: From Buccaneers to Guinea Pigs: The Genesis of Causal Inference
1.4Chapter 3: From Evidence to Causes: Reverend [Thomas Bayes|Bayes] meets Mr Holmes
1.5Chapter 4: Confounding and Deconfounding, or, Slaying the Lurking Variable
1.6Chapter 5: The Smoke-filled Debate: Clearing the Air
1.7Chapter 6: Paradoxes Galore!
1.8Chapter 7: Beyond Adjustment: The Conquest of Mount Intervention
1.9Chapter 8: Counterfactuals: Mining worlds that could have been
1.10Chapter 9: Mediation: The Search for Mechanism
1.11Chapter 10: Big Data, Artificial Intelligence and the Big Questions
2Reviews
3References
The book consists of ten chapters and an introduction.
Introduction: Mind over Data
The introduction describes the inadequacy of early 20th century statistical methods at making statements about causal relationships between variables. The authors then describe what they term 'The Causal Revolution', which started in the middle of the 20th century, and provided new conceptual and mathematical tools for describing causal relationships.
Chapter 1: The Ladder of Causation
Chapter 1 introduces the 'ladder of causation' - a diagram used to illustrate the three levels of causal reasoning. The first level is named 'Association', which discusses associations between variables. Questions such as 'is variable X associated with variable Y?' can be answered at this level. However, crucially, causality is not invoked. An example of reasoning on this first level is the observation that a crowing rooster is associated with the sunrise. However, this kind of reasoning cannot describe causal relations, for example, we cannot say whether the sunrise causes the rooster to crow, or whether the rooster causes the sun to rise. Many of the early 20th century statistical tools, such as correlation and regression operate on this level.
The second level (or 'rung') on the ladder of causation is labelled 'Intervention'. Reasoning on this level answers questions of the form 'if I make the intervention X, how will this affect the probability of the outcome Y?'. For example, the question 'does smoking increase my chance of lung cancer?' exists on the second level of the ladder of causation. This kind of reasoning invokes causality and can be used to investigate more questions than the reasoning of the first rung.
The third rung of the ladder of causation is labelled 'Counterfactuals' and involves answering questions which ask what might have been, had circumstances been different. Such reasoning invokes causality to a greater degree than the previous level. An example counterfactual question given in the book is 'Would Kennedy be alive if Oswald had not killed him?'
Chapter 2: From Buccaneers to Guinea Pigs: The Genesis of Causal Inference
Chapter 2 starts with a brief summary of the contributions of Francis Galton and Karl Pearson to the development of statistics in the late 19th Century and early 20th Centuries. The authors blame Galton for keeping the study of statistics on the first rung of the ladder of causation and discouraging any discussion of causality in statistics. Causal analysis using path diagrams is then introduced through the explanations of the work of Sewall Wright.
Chapter 3: From Evidence to Causes: Reverend [Thomas Bayes|Bayes] meets Mr Holmes[edit]
Chapter 3 provides an introduction to Bayes Theorem. Then Bayesian Networks are introduced. Finally, the links between Baysian networks and causal diagrams are discussed.
Chapter 4: Confounding and Deconfounding, or, Slaying the Lurking Variable[edit]
This chapter introduces the idea of confounding and describes how causal diagrams can be used to identify confounding variables and determine their effect. Pearl explains that randomized controlled trials (RCTs) can be used to nullify the effect of confounders, but shows that, provided one has a causal model of confounding, an RCT does not necessarily have to be performed to get results.
Chapter 5: The Smoke-filled Debate: Clearing the Air[edit]
This chapter takes a historical approach to the question 'does smoking cause lung cancer?', focusing on the arguments made by Abraham Lilienfeld, Jacob Yerushalmy, Ronald Fisher and Jerome Cornfield. The authors explain that, though cigarette smoking was clearly correlated with lung cancer, some, such as Fisher and Yerushalmy, believed that the two variables were confounded and argued against the hypothesis that cigarettes caused the cancer. The authors then explain how causal reasoning (as developed in the rest of the book) can be used to argue that cigarettes do indeed cause cancer.
Chapter 6: Paradoxes Galore![edit]
This chapter examines several paradoxes, including the Monty Hall Problem, Simpson's paradox, Berkson's paradox and Lord's paradox. The authors show how these paradoxes can be resolved using causal reasoning.
Chapter 7: Beyond Adjustment: The Conquest of Mount Intervention[edit]
This chapter looks at the 'second rung' of the ladder of causation introduced in chapter 1. The authors describe how to use causal diagrams to ascertain the causal effect of performing interventions (eg. smoking) on outcomes (such as lung cancer). The 'front-door criterion' and the 'do-calculus' are introduced as tools for doing this. The chapter finishes with two examples, used to introduce the use of instrumental variables to estimate causal relationships. The first is John Snow's discovery that cholera is caused by unsanitary water supplies. The second is the relationship between cholesterol levels and likelihood of a heart attack.
Chapter 8: Counterfactuals: Mining worlds that could have been[edit]
This chapter examines the third rung of the ladder of causation: counterfactuals. The chapter introduces 'structural causal models', which allow reasoning about counterfactuals in a way that traditional (non-causal) statistics does not. Then, the applications of counterfactual reasoning are explored in the areas of climate science and the law.
Chapter 9: Mediation: The Search for Mechanism[edit]
This chapter discusses mediation: the mechanism by which a cause leads to an effect. The authors discuss the work of Barbara Stoddard Burks on the causes of intelligence of children, the 'algebra for all' policy by Chicago public schools, and the use of tourniquets to treat combat wounds.
Chapter 10: Big Data, Artificial Intelligence and the Big Questions[edit]
The final chapter discusses the use of causal reasoning in big data and artificial intelligence (AI) and the philosophical problem that AI would have to reflect on its own actions, which requires counterfactual (and therefore causal) reasoning.
Reviews[edit]
Scientific Background, excerpts, errata, and a list of 37 reviews of The Book of Why is provided on Judea Pearl's web page
The Book of Why was reviewed by Jonathan Knee in The New York Times. The review was positive, with Knee calling the book "illuminating". However, he describes some parts of the book as "challenging", stating that the book is "not always fully accessible to readers who do not share the author's fondness for equations".
Tim Maudlin gave the book a mixed review in The Boston Review, calling it a "splendid overview of the state of the art in causal analysis". However, Maudlin criticizes the inclusion of "counterfactuals" as separate rung on the "ladder of causation", stating counterfactuals are so closely entwined with causal claims that it is not possible to think causally but not counterfactually". Maudlin also criticizes the section on free will for its "imprecision and lack of familiarity with the philosophical literature". Finally he points to the work of several scientists (including Clark Glymour) who developed similar ideas to Pearl, and claims that Pearl "could have saved himself literally years of effort had he been apprised of this work".
In a rebuttal, Pearl notes that, not only was he apprised of these scientists' work, but he actively collaborated in its creation. Additionally, the key developments described in The Book of Why, among them (1) identification analysis, (2) the algorithmization of counterfactuals, (3) mediation analysis, and (4) external validity, far surpass the narrow philosophical literature of the pre-2000 era.
Zoe Hackett, writing in Chemistry World, gave The Book of Why a positive review, with the caveat that "[i]t requires concentration, and a studious effort to work through the mind-bending statistical problems posited in the text". The review concludes by stating that "[t]his book is a must for any serious student of philosophy of science, and should be required reading for any first-year undergraduate statistics class".
Lisa R. Goldberg wrote a detailed, technical review in Notices of the American Mathematical Society.
References[edit]
Judea Pearl's information page for The Book of Why, http://bayes.cs.ucla.edu/WHY/
"Review: The Book of Why Examines the Science of Cause and Effect". The New York Times. 1 June 2018.
Tim Maudlin (4 September 2019). "The Why of the World". The Boston Review.
Zoe Hackett (18 January 2019). "The Book of Why: The New Science of Cause and Effect". Chemistry World.
Lisa R. Goldberg (August 2019). "The Book of Why" (PDF). Notices of the American Mathematical Society.