第27行: |
第27行: |
| | | |
| 第16页: “正是在这种情况下……他分析了堂吉诃德Don Quixote的两难处境:走武装之路(praxis,行动)还是走文字之路(poiesis,创造,生产)。我第一次理解了‘poiesis’这个词的力量,并发明了我们需要的词:autopoiesis。这是一个前所未有的词,一个可以直接表达‘在生命系统特有的自主性的动态中发生了什么’的词。” | | 第16页: “正是在这种情况下……他分析了堂吉诃德Don Quixote的两难处境:走武装之路(praxis,行动)还是走文字之路(poiesis,创造,生产)。我第一次理解了‘poiesis’这个词的力量,并发明了我们需要的词:autopoiesis。这是一个前所未有的词,一个可以直接表达‘在生命系统特有的自主性的动态中发生了什么’的词。” |
| + | |
| Page 78: An autopoietic machine is a machine organized (defined as a unity) as a network of processes of production (transformation and destruction) of components which: (i) through their interactions and transformations continuously regenerate and realize the network of processes (relations) that produced them; and (ii) constitute it (the machine) as a concrete unity in space in which they (the components) exist by specifying the topological domain of its realization as such a network. | | Page 78: An autopoietic machine is a machine organized (defined as a unity) as a network of processes of production (transformation and destruction) of components which: (i) through their interactions and transformations continuously regenerate and realize the network of processes (relations) that produced them; and (ii) constitute it (the machine) as a concrete unity in space in which they (the components) exist by specifying the topological domain of its realization as such a network. |
| | | |
第75行: |
第76行: |
| Though others have often used the term as a synonym for self-organization, Maturana himself stated he would "[n]ever use the notion of self-organization ... Operationally it is impossible. That is, if the organization of a thing changes, the thing changes". Moreover, an autopoietic system is autonomous and operationally closed, in the sense that there are sufficient processes within it to maintain the whole. Autopoietic systems are "structurally coupled" with their medium, embedded in a dynamic of changes that can be recalled as sensory-motor coupling. This continuous dynamic is considered as a rudimentary form of knowledge or cognition and can be observed throughout life-forms. | | Though others have often used the term as a synonym for self-organization, Maturana himself stated he would "[n]ever use the notion of self-organization ... Operationally it is impossible. That is, if the organization of a thing changes, the thing changes". Moreover, an autopoietic system is autonomous and operationally closed, in the sense that there are sufficient processes within it to maintain the whole. Autopoietic systems are "structurally coupled" with their medium, embedded in a dynamic of changes that can be recalled as sensory-motor coupling. This continuous dynamic is considered as a rudimentary form of knowledge or cognition and can be observed throughout life-forms. |
| | | |
− | 尽管其他人经常使用该术语来作为自组织self-organization的同义词,Maturana本人表示他“永远不会使自组织的概念……在操作上它是不可能的。换句话说,如果一个事物的组织发生了变化,这个事物也就发生了变化。”。此外,自创生系统是资助的,并且在操作上是封闭的。也就是说,它内部有足够的过程,来维持整个系统。自创生系统和它们的媒介“在结构上是耦合的”,嵌入在一种变化的动态中,可以被称为感知-运动的耦合。这种连续的动态被认为是知识或认知的初级形式,可以在整个生命形式中观察到。 | + | 尽管其他人经常使用该术语来作为自组织self-organization的同义词,Maturana本人表示他“永远不会使自组织的概念……在操作上它是不可能的。换句话说,如果一个事物的组织发生了变化,这个事物也就发生了变化。”。此外,自创生系统是自主的,并且在操作上是封闭的。也就是说,它内部有足够的过程,来维持整个系统。自创生系统和它们的媒介“在结构上是耦合的”,嵌入在一种变化的动态中,可以被称为感知-运动的耦合。这种连续的动态被认为是知识或认知的初级形式,可以在整个生命形式中观察到。 |
| | | |
| | | |
第104行: |
第105行: |
| | | |
| ==Relation to complexity== | | ==Relation to complexity== |
| + | |
| + | |
| + | 与复杂性的关系 |
| + | |
| | | |
| Autopoiesis can be defined as the ratio between the complexity of a system and the complexity of its environment.<ref name="Fernández"> | | Autopoiesis can be defined as the ratio between the complexity of a system and the complexity of its environment.<ref name="Fernández"> |
第119行: |
第124行: |
| {{quote|This generalized view of autopoiesis considers systems as self-producing not in terms of their physical components, but in terms of its organization, which can be measured in terms of information and complexity. In other words, we can describe autopoietic systems as those producing more of their own complexity than the one produced by their environment.<ref name=Gershenson>{{cite arXiv |title=Requisite Variety, Autopoiesis, and Self-organization | first = Carlos | last = Gershenson | name-list-style = vanc | author-link = Carlos Gershenson|date=26 Sep 2014 |eprint= 1409.7475| class = nlin.AO }}</ref>}} | | {{quote|This generalized view of autopoiesis considers systems as self-producing not in terms of their physical components, but in terms of its organization, which can be measured in terms of information and complexity. In other words, we can describe autopoietic systems as those producing more of their own complexity than the one produced by their environment.<ref name=Gershenson>{{cite arXiv |title=Requisite Variety, Autopoiesis, and Self-organization | first = Carlos | last = Gershenson | name-list-style = vanc | author-link = Carlos Gershenson|date=26 Sep 2014 |eprint= 1409.7475| class = nlin.AO }}</ref>}} |
| | | |
| + | 这种关于自创生的笼统观点认为:系统的自我生产指的不是其物理成分,而是其组织,可以用信息和复杂度来衡量。换句话说,我们可以把自创生系统描述为那些自己产生的复杂性多于环境产生的复杂性的系统。 |
| + | |
| + | ——Carlos Gershenson,“必要的多样性、自创生与自组织” 。 |
| | | |
| | | |
| An extensive discussion of the connection of autopoiesis to cognition is provided by Thompson. The basic notion of autopoiesis as involving constructive interaction with the environment is extended to include cognition. Initially, Maturana defined cognition as behavior of an organism "with relevance to the maintenance of itself". However, computer models that are self-maintaining but non-cognitive have been devised, so some additional restrictions are needed, and the suggestion is that the maintenance process, to be cognitive, involves readjustment of the internal workings of the system in some metabolic process. On this basis it is claimed that autopoiesis is a necessary but not a sufficient condition for cognition. Thompson (p. 127) takes the view that this distinction may or may not be fruitful, but what matters is that living systems involve autopoiesis and (if it is necessary to add this point) cognition as well. It can be noted that this definition of 'cognition' is restricted, and does not necessarily entail any awareness or consciousness by the living system. | | An extensive discussion of the connection of autopoiesis to cognition is provided by Thompson. The basic notion of autopoiesis as involving constructive interaction with the environment is extended to include cognition. Initially, Maturana defined cognition as behavior of an organism "with relevance to the maintenance of itself". However, computer models that are self-maintaining but non-cognitive have been devised, so some additional restrictions are needed, and the suggestion is that the maintenance process, to be cognitive, involves readjustment of the internal workings of the system in some metabolic process. On this basis it is claimed that autopoiesis is a necessary but not a sufficient condition for cognition. Thompson (p. 127) takes the view that this distinction may or may not be fruitful, but what matters is that living systems involve autopoiesis and (if it is necessary to add this point) cognition as well. It can be noted that this definition of 'cognition' is restricted, and does not necessarily entail any awareness or consciousness by the living system. |
| | | |
− | 汤普森对自创生与认知之间的联系进行了广泛的讨论。自创生的基本概念涉及与环境的建设性互动,这一概念被扩展到包括认知。最初,Maturana 将认知定义为有机体“与维持自身相关”的行为。然而,人们已经设计出了可以自我维持但不具有认知能力的计算机模型,因此还需要一些额外的限制,这个建议认为,维护过程需要在某些代谢重新调整系统的内部工作。在此基础上,认为自创生是认知的一个必要条件,但不是充分条件。汤普森(第127页)认为,这种区分可能是有益的,也可能没有,但重要的是,生命系统涉及自创生和(如果有必要增加这一点)认知。可以注意到,这个“认知”的定义是有限的,并不一定要求生命系统有任何意识或觉知。
| + | Evan Thompson在其2007年出版的《生命中的心智》(Mind in Life)中,对自创生与认知的联系进行了广泛的讨论。自创生的基本概念——涉及与环境的建构性互动——被扩展到能够包括认知。最初,Maturana将认知定义为有机体“与维持自身有关”的行为。然而,人们已经设计出了能自我维持但不具有认知性的计算机模型,因此,“认知”需要一些额外的限制。维持过程要具有认知性,最好涉及某些代谢过程中对系统内部运作的重新调整。在此基础上,可以宣称自创生是认知的必要不充分条件。Thompson写道:这种区分可能有结果,也可能没结果;但重要的是,生命系统涉及自创生,认知也涉及(如果有必要加上这点的话)。可以注意到,这种对“认知”的定义是有限制的,不一定需要生命系统的任何意识或觉察。 |
| | | |
| ==Relation to cognition== | | ==Relation to cognition== |
| + | |
| + | 与意识的关系 |
| + | |
| | | |
| An extensive discussion of the connection of autopoiesis to [[cognition]] is provided by Thompson.<ref name=Thompson> | | An extensive discussion of the connection of autopoiesis to [[cognition]] is provided by Thompson.<ref name=Thompson> |
第133行: |
第144行: |
| The connection of autopoiesis to cognition, or if necessary, of living systems to cognition, is an objective assessment ascertainable by observation of a living system. | | The connection of autopoiesis to cognition, or if necessary, of living systems to cognition, is an objective assessment ascertainable by observation of a living system. |
| | | |
− | 自创生与认知的联系,或者如果必要的话,生命系统与认知的联系,是一个可以通过观察生命系统来确定的客观评估。
| + | 自创生(如果有必要的话,特指生命系统的自创生)与认知的关系,是一种可以通过观察生命系统来确定的客观评估。 |
| | | |
| </ref> The basic notion of autopoiesis as involving constructive interaction with the environment is extended to include cognition. Initially, Maturana defined cognition as behavior of an organism "with relevance to the maintenance of itself".<ref name=Maturana> | | </ref> The basic notion of autopoiesis as involving constructive interaction with the environment is extended to include cognition. Initially, Maturana defined cognition as behavior of an organism "with relevance to the maintenance of itself".<ref name=Maturana> |
第141行: |
第152行: |
| One question that arises is about the connection between cognition seen in this manner and consciousness. The separation of cognition and consciousness recognizes that the organism may be unaware of the substratum where decisions are made. What is the connection between these realms? Thompson refers to this issue as the "explanatory gap", and one aspect of it is the hard problem of consciousness, how and why we have qualia. | | One question that arises is about the connection between cognition seen in this manner and consciousness. The separation of cognition and consciousness recognizes that the organism may be unaware of the substratum where decisions are made. What is the connection between these realms? Thompson refers to this issue as the "explanatory gap", and one aspect of it is the hard problem of consciousness, how and why we have qualia. |
| | | |
− | 出现的一个问题是关于以这种方式看到的认知和意识之间的联系。认知和意识的分离意识到有机体可能不知道作出决定的底层。这些领域之间的联系是什么?汤普森把这个问题称为“解释缺口” ,其中一个方面就是意识这个难题,我们如何以及为什么有感受。
| + | 由此出现的一个问题是意识与用这种方式看待的认知之间的联系。认知与意识的分离让我们意识到,有机体可能并不能意识到做出决定的底层机制。这两个领域的联系是什么?Thompson把这个问题称为“解释的鸿沟”explanatory gap,其中的一个方面是“意识的难题”the hard problem of consciousness,即我们如何以及为什么会有“感质”qualia的问题。 |
| | | |
| </ref> However, computer models that are self-maintaining but non-cognitive have been devised, so some additional restrictions are needed, and the suggestion is that the maintenance process, to be cognitive, involves readjustment of the internal workings of the system in some [[Metabolism|metabolic process]]. On this basis it is claimed that autopoiesis is a necessary but not a sufficient condition for cognition.<ref name=Bitbol> | | </ref> However, computer models that are self-maintaining but non-cognitive have been devised, so some additional restrictions are needed, and the suggestion is that the maintenance process, to be cognitive, involves readjustment of the internal workings of the system in some [[Metabolism|metabolic process]]. On this basis it is claimed that autopoiesis is a necessary but not a sufficient condition for cognition.<ref name=Bitbol> |
第149行: |
第160行: |
| A second question is whether autopoiesis can provide a bridge between these concepts. Thompson discusses this issue from the standpoint of enactivism. An autopoietic cell actively relates to its environment. Its sensory responses trigger motor behavior governed by autopoiesis, and this behavior (it is claimed) is a simplified version of a nervous system behavior. The further claim is that real-time interactions like this require attention, and an implication of attention is awareness. | | A second question is whether autopoiesis can provide a bridge between these concepts. Thompson discusses this issue from the standpoint of enactivism. An autopoietic cell actively relates to its environment. Its sensory responses trigger motor behavior governed by autopoiesis, and this behavior (it is claimed) is a simplified version of a nervous system behavior. The further claim is that real-time interactions like this require attention, and an implication of attention is awareness. |
| | | |
− | 第二个问题是,自创生能否在这些概念之间架起一座桥梁。汤普森从能动主义的角度讨论了这个问题。自创生细胞与周围环境密切相关。它的感觉反应触发由自创生控制的运动行为,这种行为(据称)是神经系统行为的简化版本。进一步的说法是,像这样的实时互动需要注意力,而注意力的含义就是意识。
| + | 第二个问题是自创生能否在这些概念之间提供一个桥梁。Tompson从交互理论enactivism的角度讨论了这个问题。一个自创生的细胞积极地与它的环境发生联系。它的感觉反应触发了由自创生支配的运动行为,而这种行为(据说)是神经网络行为的简化版。进一步说,像这样的实时互动需要注意力,而注意力的一个含义就是意识。 |
| | | |
| </ref> Thompson (p. 127) takes the view that this distinction may or may not be fruitful, but what matters is that living systems involve autopoiesis and (if it is necessary to add this point) cognition as well. It can be noted that this definition of 'cognition' is restricted, and does not necessarily entail any awareness or [[consciousness]] by the living system. | | </ref> Thompson (p. 127) takes the view that this distinction may or may not be fruitful, but what matters is that living systems involve autopoiesis and (if it is necessary to add this point) cognition as well. It can be noted that this definition of 'cognition' is restricted, and does not necessarily entail any awareness or [[consciousness]] by the living system. |
第161行: |
第172行: |
| There are multiple criticisms of the use of the term in both its original context, as an attempt to define and explain the living, and its various expanded usages, such as applying it to self-organizing systems in general or social systems in particular. Critics have argued that the concept and its theory fail to define or explain living systems and that, because of the extreme language of self-referentiality it uses without any external reference, it is really an attempt to give substantiation to Maturana's radical constructivist or solipsistic epistemology, or what Danilo Zolo has called instead a "desolate theology". An example is the assertion by Maturana and Varela that "We do not see what we do not see and what we do not see does not exist". The autopoietic model, said Rod Swenson, is "miraculously decoupled from the physical world by its progenitors ... (and thus) grounded on a solipsistic foundation that flies in the face of both common sense and scientific knowledge". | | There are multiple criticisms of the use of the term in both its original context, as an attempt to define and explain the living, and its various expanded usages, such as applying it to self-organizing systems in general or social systems in particular. Critics have argued that the concept and its theory fail to define or explain living systems and that, because of the extreme language of self-referentiality it uses without any external reference, it is really an attempt to give substantiation to Maturana's radical constructivist or solipsistic epistemology, or what Danilo Zolo has called instead a "desolate theology". An example is the assertion by Maturana and Varela that "We do not see what we do not see and what we do not see does not exist". The autopoietic model, said Rod Swenson, is "miraculously decoupled from the physical world by its progenitors ... (and thus) grounded on a solipsistic foundation that flies in the face of both common sense and scientific knowledge". |
| | | |
− | 对于在其原始上下文中使用这一术语,试图界定和解释生活及其各种扩大的用法,例如将其应用于一般的自组织系统或具体的社会系统,有多种批评意见。批评家们认为,这一概念及其理论未能界定或解释生命系统,而且由于它在没有任何外部参照的情况下使用的自指向性的极端语言,它实际上是试图为马图拉纳激进的建构主义或唯我认识论或达尼洛 · 佐罗所称的“荒凉神学”提供实证。一个例子是 Maturana 和 Varela 的断言,即”我们看不到我们看不到的东西,我们看不到的东西不存在”。罗德•斯文森说,自创生模型“奇迹般地与物质世界分离... ... (因此)建立在唯我论的基础上,与常识和科学知识背道而驰”。
| + | 对于该术语的应用,无论是在其最初的语境中(即试图定义和解释生命体),还是在其各种扩展的使用中(如将其应用到一半的自组织系统,特别是社会系统),都有多种批评意见[37]。批评者认为,该概念及其理论未能定义或解释神明系统。而且,由于其使用的极端的自我指涉语言没有任何外部参照,它实际上是在为Maturana的激进建构主义constructivist或唯我论solipsistic的认识论epistemology[38](又被Danilo Zolo称为“荒凉神学”[39][40])提供证据。自我指涉的一个例子是Maturana和Varela的断言:“我们看不到我们没有看到的东西,我们没有看到的东西也不存在。”Rod Swenson说,自创生模型“奇迹般地与物质世界分离... ... (因此)建立在唯我论的基础上,与常识和科学知识背道而驰。” |
| | | |
| | | |