更改

删除12,044字节 、 2021年6月5日 (六) 19:40
无编辑摘要
第2行: 第2行:  
由CecileLi初步审校
 
由CecileLi初步审校
   −
{{short description|Classical Greek philosopher and polymath, founder of the Peripatetic School}}
+
'''Aristotle''' ({{IPAc-en|ær|ɪ|s|ˈ|t|ɒ|t|əl}};{{sfn|Collins English Dictionary}} {{lang-grc-gre|Ἀριστοτέλης}} ''Aristotélēs'', {{IPA-grc|aristotélɛːs|pron}}; 384–322 BC) was a Greek [[philosopher]] and [[polymath]] during the [[Classical Greece|Classical period]] in [[Ancient Greece]]. Taught by [[Plato]], he was the founder of the [[Lyceum (Classical)|Lyceum]], the [[Peripatetic school]] of philosophy, and the [[Aristotelianism|Aristotelian]] tradition. His writings cover many subjects including [[Physics (Aristotle)|physics]], [[biology]], [[zoology]], [[metaphysics]], [[logic]], [[ethics]], [[aesthetics]], [[Poetics (Aristotle)|poetry]], [[theatre]], [[music]], [[rhetoric]], [[psychology]], [[linguistics]], [[economics]], [[politics]], and government. Aristotle provided a complex synthesis of the various philosophies existing prior to him. It was above all from his teachings that the West inherited its intellectual [[lexicon]], as well as problems and methods of inquiry. As a result, his philosophy has exerted a unique influence on almost every form of knowledge in the West and it continues to be a subject of contemporary philosophical discussion.
   −
{{other uses}}
+
Aristotle (/ærɪsˈtɒtəl/;Greek: Ἀριστοτέλης Aristotélēs, pronounced [aristotélɛːs]; 384–322 BC) was a Greek philosopher and polymath during the Classical period in Ancient Greece. Taught by Plato, he was the founder of the Lyceum, the Peripatetic school of philosophy, and the Aristotelian tradition. His writings cover many subjects including physics, biology, zoology, metaphysics, logic, ethics, aesthetics, poetry, theatre, music, rhetoric, psychology, linguistics, economics, politics, and government. Aristotle provided a complex synthesis of the various philosophies existing prior to him. It was above all from his teachings that the West inherited its intellectual lexicon, as well as problems and methods of inquiry. As a result, his philosophy has exerted a unique influence on almost every form of knowledge in the West and it continues to be a subject of contemporary philosophical discussion.
   −
{{pp-protected|small=yes}}
+
亚里士多德(Aristotle)是古希腊古典时期的希腊哲学家和博学家。在’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> </font>’’’柏拉图(Plato)的指导下,他创立了吕克昂学院、哲学逍遥学派和亚里士多德传统。他的著作涉及许多学科,包括’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 物理学 physics </font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 生物学 biology </font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 动物学 zoology</font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 形而上学 metaphysics</font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 逻辑学 logic</font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 伦理学 ethics</font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 美学 aesthetics</font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 诗歌 poetry</font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 戏剧 theatre</font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 音乐music </font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 修辞学 rhetoric</font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 心理学 psychology</font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 语言学 linguistics</font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 经济学 economics</font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 政治学 politics</font>’’’和政府。Aristotle对在他之前存在的各种哲学进行了复杂的综合。最重要的是,正是从他的教诲中,西方继承了其知识词汇,以及问题和探究方法。因此,他的哲学对西方几乎所有的知识形式都产生了独特的影响,并且继续成为当代哲学讨论的主题。
   −
{{Use British English Oxford spelling|date=March 2020}}
+
Little is known about his life. Aristotle was born in the city of [[Stagira (ancient city)|Stagira]] in [[Northern Greece]]. His father, [[Nicomachus (father of Aristotle)|Nicomachus]], died when Aristotle was a child, and he was brought up by a guardian. At seventeen or eighteen years of age he joined [[Plato's Academy]] in [[Athens]] and remained there until the age of thirty-seven ([[Circa|c.]] 347 BC).{{sfn|Aristotle (384–322 B.C.E.)}} Shortly after Plato died, Aristotle left Athens and, at the request of [[Philip II of Macedon]], tutored [[Alexander the Great]] beginning in 343 BC.{{sfn|Russell| 1972}} He established a library in the [[Lyceum (Classical)|Lyceum]] which helped him to produce many of his hundreds of books on [[papyrus]] [[scrolls]]. Though Aristotle wrote many elegant treatises and dialogues for publication, only around a third of his original output has survived, none of it intended for publication.{{sfn|Barnes|1995|p=9}}
   −
{{good article}}
+
Little is known about his life. Aristotle was born in the city of Stagira in Northern Greece. His father, Nicomachus, died when Aristotle was a child, and he was brought up by a guardian. At seventeen or eighteen years of age he joined Plato's Academy in Athens and remained there until the age of thirty-seven (c. 347 BC). Shortly after Plato died, Aristotle left Athens and, at the request of Philip II of Macedon, tutored Alexander the Great beginning in 343 BC. He established a library in the Lyceum which helped him to produce many of his hundreds of books on papyrus scrolls. Though Aristotle wrote many elegant treatises and dialogues for publication, only around a third of his original output has survived, none of it intended for publication.
   −
{{Use dmy dates|date=March 2020}}
+
关于他的生平我们知之甚少。Aristotle出生于希腊北部的 斯塔基拉市。他的父亲尼科马修斯(Nicomachus),在Aristotle还是个孩子的时候就去世了,他是由一位监护人抚养长大的。十七岁的时候,他加入了雅典的柏拉图学院,一直呆到37岁(约公元前347年)。在柏拉图死后不久,Aristotle离开了雅典,在腓力二世的要求下,他从公元前343年开始辅导亚历山大大帝。他在吕克昂里建立了一个图书馆,帮助他制作了数百本纸莎草卷轴的书籍。尽管亚里士多德写了许多优美的论文和对话录供出版,但是只有三分之一的原著保存下来,没有一本打算出版。
   −
{{Infobox philosopher
     −
{{Infobox philosopher
     −
{ Infobox 哲学家
+
Aristotle's views on [[Aristotelian physics|physical science]] profoundly shaped medieval scholarship. Their influence extended from [[Late Antiquity]] and the [[Early Middle Ages]] into the [[Renaissance]], and were not replaced systematically until [[Age of Enlightenment|the Enlightenment]] and theories such as [[classical mechanics]] were developed. Some of Aristotle's zoological observations found in [[Aristotle's biology|his biology]], such as on the [[Hectocotylus|hectocotyl (reproductive) arm]] of the [[octopus]], were disbelieved until the 19th century. His works contain the earliest known formal study of logic, studied by medieval scholars such as [[Peter Abelard]] and [[John Buridan]]. Aristotle's influence on logic also continued well into the 19th century.
   −
| name=Aristotle
+
Aristotle's views on physical science profoundly shaped medieval scholarship. Their influence extended from Late Antiquity and the Early Middle Ages into the Renaissance, and were not replaced systematically until the Enlightenment and theories such as classical mechanics were developed. ’’’<font color=’’#32CD32’’> Some of Aristotle's zoological observations found in his biology, such as on the hectocotyl (reproductive) arm of the octopus, were disbelieved until the 19th century. </font>’’’ His works contain the earliest known formal study of logic, studied by medieval scholars such as Peter Abelard and John Buridan. Aristotle's influence on logic also continued well into the 19th century.
   −
| name=Aristotle
+
Aristotle关于物理学的观点深刻地影响了中世纪的学术研究。他们的影响从古代晚期和中世纪早期一直延伸到文艺复兴时期,直到启蒙运动和经典力学等理论的发展才被系统地取代。’’’<font color=’’#32CD32’’> Aristotle在他的生物学中发现的一些动物学观察,例如章鱼的八轴臂(繁殖臂),直到19世纪才被人们所相信。</font>’’’他的著作包含了已知最早的逻辑学研究,中世纪学者如彼得 · 阿伯拉尔Peter Abelard和约翰 · 布里丹John Buridan研究过。Aristotle对逻辑学的影响一直延续到19世纪。
   −
姓名 = 亚里士多德
     −
| image=Aristotle Altemps Inv8575.jpg
     −
| image=Aristotle Altemps Inv8575.jpg
+
He influenced [[Judeo-Islamic philosophies (800–1400)]] during the [[Middle Ages]], as well as [[Christian theology]], especially the [[Neoplatonism]] of the [[Early Church]] and the [[Scholasticism|scholastic]] tradition of the [[Catholic Church]]. Aristotle was revered among medieval Muslim scholars as "The First Teacher" and among medieval Christians like [[Thomas Aquinas]] as simply "The Philosopher". His ethics, though always influential, gained renewed interest with the modern advent of [[virtue ethics]], such as in the thinking of  [[Alasdair MacIntyre]] and [[Philippa Foot]].
   −
8575. jpg
+
He influenced Judeo-Islamic philosophies (800–1400) during the Middle Ages, as well as Christian theology, especially the Neoplatonism of the Early Church and the scholastic tradition of the Catholic Church. Aristotle was revered among medieval Muslim scholars as "The First Teacher" and among medieval Christians like Thomas Aquinas as simply "The Philosopher". His ethics, though always influential, gained renewed interest with the modern advent of virtue ethics, such as in the thinking of  Alasdair MacIntyre and Philippa Foot.
   −
| caption=Roman copy in marble of a Greek bronze [[Bust (sculpture)|bust]] of Aristotle by [[Lysippos]], [[Circa|c.]] 330 BC, with modern [[alabaster]] [[mantle (clothing)|mantle]]
+
他影响了中世纪的犹太-伊斯兰哲学(800-1400),也影响了基督教神学,特别是早起教会的新柏拉图主义和天主教会的经院传统。亚里士多德在中世纪的穆斯林学者中被尊为“第一导师” ,在托马斯 · 阿奎那Thomas Aquinas等中世纪基督徒中被尊为“哲学家”。他的伦理学虽然一直很有影响力,但随着现代美德伦理学的出现,例如阿拉斯代尔·麦金泰尔Alasdair MacIntyre 和菲利帕 · 福特Philippa Foot的思想,他的伦理学又重新引起了人们的兴趣。
   −
| caption=Roman copy in marble of a Greek bronze bust of Aristotle by Lysippos, c. 330 BC, with modern alabaster mantle
     −
公元前330年,利西波斯用现代雪花石膏做的希腊亚里士多德半身铜像的罗马仿品
     −
| birth_date=384 BC{{efn-ua|That these dates (the first half of the Olympiad year 384/383 BC, and in 322 shortly before the death of Demosthenes) are correct was shown by [[August Boeckh]] (''Kleine Schriften'' VI 195); for further discussion, see [[Felix Jacoby]] on ''[[FGrHist]]'' 244 F 38. Ingemar Düring, ''Aristotle in the Ancient Biographical Tradition'', Göteborg, 1957,{{p.|253}}}}
+
==Life==
 +
生平
   −
| birth_date=384 BC}}
     −
出生日期 公元前384年
+
[[File:20160518 092 mieza nympheum.jpg | thumb | left | School of Aristotle in [[Mieza, Macedonia|Mieza]], [[Macedonia (Greece)|Macedonia, Greece]]]]
   −
| birth_place=[[Stagira (ancient city)|Stagira]], [[Chalcidian League]]
+
School of Aristotle in Mieza, Macedonia, Greece
   −
| birth_place=Stagira, Chalcidian League
+
Aristotle的学校,在米萨,马其顿,希腊
   −
出生地: 开尔基狄安联盟的斯塔吉拉
     −
| death_date={{nowrap|322 BC (aged 61–62)}}
+
In general, the details of Aristotle's life are not well-established. The biographies written in ancient times are often speculative and historians only agree on a few salient points.{{efn-ua | See {{harvnb|Shields|2012|pp=3–16}}; {{harvnb|Düring|1957}} covers ancient biographies of Aristotle.}}
   −
| death_date=
+
In general, the details of Aristotle's life are not well-established. The biographies written in ancient times are often speculative and historians only agree on a few salient points.
   −
逝世日期 公元前322年(61-62岁)
+
总的来说,关于Aristotle生活的细节并不完整。古代的传记往往是臆测性的,历史学家们只在几个要点上达成一致。
   −
| death_place=[[Euboea]], [[Macedonia (ancient kingdom)#Empire|Macedonian Empire]]
+
Aristotle, whose name means "the best purpose" in Ancient Greek,{{sfn|Campbell}}<!--better source desirable--> was born in 384&nbsp;BC in [[Stagira (ancient city)|Stagira]], [[Chalcidice]], about 55&nbsp;km (34 miles) east of modern-day [[Thessaloniki]].{{sfn|McLeisch|1999|p=5}}{{sfn|Aristoteles-Park in Stagira}} His father [[Nicomachus (father of Aristotle)|Nicomachus]] was the personal physician to [[Amyntas III of Macedon|King Amyntas of Macedon]]. Both of Aristotle's parents died when he was about thirteen, and [[Proxenus of Atarneus]] became his guardian.{{sfn|Hall|2018|p=14}} Although little information about Aristotle's childhood has survived, he probably spent some time within the Macedonian palace, making his first connections with the [[Macedonia (ancient kingdom)#Kingship and the royal court|Macedonian monarchy]].{{sfn|Anagnostopoulos|2013|page=4}}
   −
| death_place=Euboea, Macedonian Empire
+
Aristotle, whose name means "the best purpose" in Ancient Greek,was born in 384 BC in Stagira, Chalcidice, about 55 km (34 miles) east of modern-day Thessaloniki.His father Nicomachus was the personal physician to King Amyntas of Macedon. Both of Aristotle's parents died when he was about thirteen, and Proxenus of Atarneus became his guardian.Although little information about Aristotle's childhood has survived, he probably spent some time within the Macedonian palace, making his first connections with the Macedonian monarchy.
   −
逝世地点 = 埃维厄岛,马其顿王国
     −
| predecessor=[[Plato]]
+
Aristotle的名字在古希腊语中意为“最好的目的”,他出生于公元前384年,位于查尔基迪斯的斯塔吉拉,距现代塞萨洛尼基东约55公里(34英里)。他的父亲Nicomachus是马其顿国王阿米尼塔斯Amyntas的私人医生。Aristotle的父母均在他十三岁时去世,而来自阿塔尼厄斯的普罗齐诺斯Proxenus成为了他的监护人。尽管关于亚里士多德童年的信息很少,但他可能在马其顿宫殿里呆过一段时间,与马其顿君主政体初次接触。
   −
| predecessor=Plato
     −
前辈 = 柏拉图
     −
| spouse=[[Pythias]]
+
At the age of seventeen or eighteen, Aristotle moved to Athens to continue his education at [[Platonic Academy|Plato's Academy]].{{sfn|Blits|1999|pp=58–63}} He probably experienced the [[Eleusinian Mysteries]] as he wrote when describing the sights one viewed at the Eleusinian Mysteries, "to experience is to learn" [παθείν μαθεĩν].{{sfn|Evans|2006}} Aristotle remained in Athens for nearly twenty years before leaving in 348/47&nbsp;BC. The traditional story about his departure records that he was disappointed with the Academy's direction after control passed to Plato's nephew [[Speusippus]], although it is possible that he feared the anti-Macedonian sentiments in Athens at that time and left before Plato died.{{sfn|Aristotle|1984|pp=Introduction}} Aristotle then accompanied [[Xenocrates]] to the court of his friend [[Hermias of Atarneus]] in [[Asia Minor]]. After the death of Hermias, Aristotle travelled with his pupil [[Theophrastus]] to the island of [[Lesbos]], where together they researched the [[botany]] and zoology of the island and its sheltered lagoon. While in Lesbos, Aristotle married [[Pythias]], either Hermias's adoptive daughter or niece. She bore him a daughter, whom they also named Pythias. In 343 BC, Aristotle was invited by [[Philip II of Macedon]] to become the tutor to his son [[Alexander the Great|Alexander]].{{sfn|Shields|2016}}{{sfn|Russell|1972}}
   −
| spouse=Pythias
+
At the age of seventeen or eighteen, Aristotle moved to Athens to continue his education at Plato's Academy.He probably experienced the Eleusinian Mysteries as he wrote when describing the sights one viewed at the Eleusinian Mysteries, "to experience is to learn" [παθείν μαθεĩν].Aristotle remained in Athens for nearly twenty years before leaving in 348/47 BC. The traditional story about his departure records that he was disappointed with the Academy's direction after control passed to Plato's nephew Speusippus, although it is possible that he feared the anti-Macedonian sentiments in Athens at that time and left before Plato died.Aristotle then accompanied Xenocrates to the court of his friend Hermias of Atarneus in Asia Minor. After the death of Hermias, Aristotle travelled with his pupil Theophrastus to the island of Lesbos, where together they researched the botany and zoology of the island and its sheltered lagoon. While in Lesbos, Aristotle married Pythias, either Hermias's adoptive daughter or niece. She bore him a daughter, whom they also named Pythias. In 343 BC, Aristotle was invited by Philip II of Macedon to become the tutor to his son Alexander.
配偶 皮提亚斯
  −
     −
| era=[[Ancient Greek philosophy]]
+
在十七八岁时,Aristotle移居雅典,在柏拉图学院继续他的学业。他可能经历过厄琉息斯秘仪,正如他在描述在厄琉息斯秘仪观察到的景象时所写的,“经历就是学习”[ παεθν αθν μθν ]。Aristotle在公元前348/47年离开之前,在雅典呆了将近20年。关于他离开的传统故事记载,在Plato的侄子斯皮普斯 Speusippus掌管学院后,他对学院发展方向感到失望,尽管他可能害怕当时雅典的反马其顿情绪,并在柏拉图去世之前离开了。随后,Aristotle陪同齐诺克利特Xenocrates来到小亚细亚的他的朋友阿塔尼厄斯的赫米亚Hermias的宫廷。Hermias死后,Aristotle和他的学生泰奥弗拉斯特斯Theophrastus前往莱斯博斯岛,在那里他们一起研究了岛上及其环礁湖的植物学和动物学。在莱斯博斯岛的时候,Aristotle与Hermias的养女或侄女皮提亚斯Pythias结婚。她为他生了一个女儿,他们也给她起名叫Pythias。公元前343年,腓力二世邀请Aristotle成为他儿子亚历山大Alexander的家庭教师。
   −
| era=Ancient Greek philosophy
     −
哲学时代 古希腊哲学
     −
| region=[[Western philosophy]]
+
[[File:Aristoteles Louvre.jpg | thumb | upright | [[Bust (sculpture)|Portrait bust]] of Aristotle; an [[Roman Empire|Imperial Roman]] (1st or 2nd century AD) copy of a lost [[bronze sculpture]] made by [[Lysippos]]]]
   −
| region=Western philosophy
+
Portrait bust of Aristotle; an Imperial Roman (1st or 2nd century AD) copy of a lost bronze sculpture made by Lysippos
   −
| 哲学属地 = 西方哲学
+
Aristotle的肖像半身像; 罗马帝国时期(公元1世纪或2世纪)利西波斯仿制的失落青铜雕像
   −
| school_tradition={{Flatlist}}
     −
| school_tradition=
     −
学派
+
Aristotle was appointed as the head of the royal academy of [[Macedon]]. During Aristotle's time in the Macedonian court, he gave lessons not only to Alexander, but also to two other future kings: [[Ptolemy I Soter|Ptolemy]] and [[Cassander]].{{sfn|Green|1991|pp=58–59}} Aristotle encouraged Alexander toward eastern conquest, and Aristotle's own attitude towards [[Persia]] was unabashedly [[Ethnocentricism|ethnocentric]]. In one famous example, he counsels Alexander to be "a leader to the Greeks and a despot to the barbarians, to look after the former as after friends and relatives, and to deal with the latter as with beasts or plants".{{sfn|Green|1991|pp=58–59}} By 335&nbsp;BC, Aristotle had returned to Athens, establishing his own school there known as the [[Lyceum (Classical)|Lyceum]]. Aristotle conducted courses at the school for the next twelve years. While in Athens, his wife Pythias died and Aristotle became involved with [[Herpyllis]] of Stagira, who bore him a son whom he named after his father, [[Nicomachus (son of Aristotle)|Nicomachus]]. If we believed the ''[[Suda]]'' (an uncritical compilation from the Middle Ages) he may also had an ''[[eromenos|erômenos]]'', [[Palaephatus | Palaephatus of Abydus]].{{sfn|Smith|2007|p=88}}
   −
* [[Peripatetic school]]
+
Aristotle was appointed as the head of the royal academy of Macedon. During Aristotle's time in the Macedonian court, he gave lessons not only to Alexander, but also to two other future kings: Ptolemy and Cassander. Aristotle encouraged Alexander toward eastern conquest, and Aristotle's own attitude towards Persia was unabashedly ethnocentric. In one famous example, he counsels Alexander to be "a leader to the Greeks and a despot to the barbarians, to look after the former as after friends and relatives, and to deal with the latter as with beasts or plants". By 335&nbsp;BC, Aristotle had returned to Athens, establishing his own school there known as the Lyceum. Aristotle conducted courses at the school for the next twelve years. While in Athens, his wife Pythias died and Aristotle became involved with Herpyllis of Stagira, who bore him a son whom he named after his father, Nicomachus. If we believed the Suda (an uncritical compilation from the Middle Ages) ’’’<font color=’’#32CD32’’> he may also had an erômenos,  Palaephatus of Abydus.</font>’’’
逍遥学派
+
Aristotle被任命为马其顿皇家学院院长。Aristotle在马其顿宫廷的时候,他不仅向亚历山大授课,还向未来的另外两位国王授课: 托勒密Ptolemy和卡山德Cassander。Aristotle鼓励Alexander去征服东方,而Aristotle本人对波斯的态度是毫不掩饰的种族中心主义。在一个著名的例子中,他建议Alexander成为“希腊人的领袖,野蛮人的暴君,像对待亲友一样对待前者,像对待动物或植物一样对待后者”。到公元前335年,Aristotle回到雅典,在那里建立了他自己的学校,被称为吕克昂。在接下来的十二年里,Aristotle在学校里开设课程。在雅典期间,他的妻子Pythias去世,Aristotle与斯塔吉拉的赫皮利斯Herpyllis有染,Herpyllis为他生了一个儿子,Aristotle以他父亲Nicomachus的名字给他取名。如果我们相信苏达(中世纪的一个不严谨的汇编) ,’’’<font color=’’#32CD32’’>他可能也有一个 erômenos,Palaephatus of Abydus。 </font>’’’
   −
* [[Aristotelianism]]
  −
亚里士多德哲学
     −
* [[Classical republicanism]]
+
This period in Athens, between 335 and 323 BC, is when Aristotle is believed to have composed many of his works.{{sfn|Russell|1972}} He wrote many dialogues, of which only fragments have survived. Those works that have survived are in [[treatise]] form and were not, for the most part, intended for widespread publication; they are generally thought to be lecture aids for his students. His most important treatises include ''[[Physics (Aristotle)|Physics]]'', ''[[Metaphysics (Aristotle)|Metaphysics]]'', ''[[Nicomachean Ethics]]'', ''[[Politics (Aristotle)|Politics]]'', ''[[On the Soul]]'' and ''[[Poetics (Aristotle)|Poetics]]''. Aristotle studied and made significant contributions to "logic, metaphysics, mathematics, physics, biology, botany, ethics, politics, agriculture, medicine, dance and theatre."{{sfn|Aristotle (384–322 B.C.E.)}}
古典共和主义
     −
{{Endflatlist}}
+
This period in Athens, between 335 and 323 BC, is when Aristotle is believed to have composed many of his works. He wrote many dialogues, of which only fragments have survived. Those works that have survived are in treatise form and were not, for the most part, intended for widespread publication; they are generally thought to be lecture aids for his students. His most important treatises include Physics, Metaphysics, Nicomachean Ethics, Politics, On the Soul and Poetics. Aristotle studied and made significant contributions to "logic, metaphysics, mathematics, physics, biology, botany, ethics, politics, agriculture, medicine, dance and theatre."
   −
| notable_students  = [[Alexander the Great]], [[Theophrastus]]
+
公元前335年至公元前323年的雅典时期,被认为是Aristotle创作许多作品的时期。他写了许多对话录,其中只有一些片段留存了下来。那些留存下来的作品都是论文形式的,而且大部分并不打算广泛出版; 它们通常被认为是他的学生的讲课辅助工具。他最重要的论著包括《物理学》、《形而上学》、《尼各马可伦理学》、《政治学》、《论灵魂》和《诗学》。Aristotle对j逻辑学、形而上学、数学、物理学、生物学、植物学、伦理学、政治学、农业、医学、舞蹈和戏剧学”都有研究,并作出了重大贡献
   −
| notable_students  = Alexander the Great, Theophrastus
     −
著名学生 = 亚历山大大帝,泰奥弗拉斯托斯
     −
| main_interests={{Flatlist}}
+
Near the end of his life, Alexander and Aristotle became estranged over Alexander's relationship with Persia and Persians. A widespread tradition in antiquity suspected Aristotle of playing a role in Alexander's death, but the only evidence of this is an [[Hagnothemis|unlikely claim]] made some six years after the death.{{sfn|Green|1991|p=460}} Following Alexander's death, anti-Macedonian sentiment in Athens was rekindled. In 322&nbsp;BC, Demophilus and [[Eurymedon the Hierophant]] reportedly denounced Aristotle for impiety,{{sfn|Filonik|2013|pp=72–73}} prompting him to flee to his mother's family estate in [[Chalcis | Chalcis, on Euboea]], at which occasion he was said to have stated: "I will not allow the Athenians to sin twice against philosophy"{{sfn|Jones|1980|p=216}}{{sfn|Gigon|2017|p=41}}{{sfn|Düring|1957|p=T44a-e}} – a reference to Athens's [[Trial of Socrates|trial and execution of Socrates]]. He died on Euboea of natural causes later that same year, having named his student [[Antipater]] as his chief [[executor]] and leaving a [[Will (law)|will]] in which he asked to be buried next to his wife.{{sfn|Haase|1992|p=3862}}
   −
  | main_interests=
+
Near the end of his life, Alexander and Aristotle became estranged over Alexander's relationship with Persia and Persians. A widespread tradition in antiquity suspected Aristotle of playing a role in Alexander's death, but the only evidence of this is an unlikely claim made some six years after the death. Following Alexander's death, anti-Macedonian sentiment in Athens was rekindled. In 322&nbsp;BC, Demophilus and Eurymedon the Hierophant reportedly denounced Aristotle for impiety, prompting him to flee to his mother's family estate in Chalcis, on Euboea, at which occasion he was said to have stated: "I will not allow the Athenians to sin twice against philosophy" – a reference to Athens's trial and execution of Socrates. He died on Euboea of natural causes later that same year, having named his student Antipater as his chief executor and leaving a will in which he asked to be buried next to his wife.
   −
主要兴趣
+
在他生命的最后阶段,Alexander和Aristotle因为Alexander与波斯和波斯人的关系而变得疏远。古代有一个广泛流传的传说,怀疑Aristotle在Alexander的死亡中扮演了一个角色,但是唯一的证据是在Alexander死后大约六年提出的一个不太可能的断言。Alexander死后,雅典的反马其顿情绪重新燃起。公元前322年,据说 德摩菲勒斯 Demophilus 和赫拉菲顿Eurymedon 谴责Aristotle不敬神,促使他逃往他母亲在埃维厄岛哈尔基斯的家族庄园,据说当时他说: “我不允许雅典人两次违背哲学”——指的是雅典对苏格拉底的审判和处决。同年晚些时候,他因自然原因在埃维厄岛去世,指定他的学生安提帕特Antipater为他的首席遗嘱执行人,并留下一份遗嘱,要求与妻子葬在一起。
   −
* [[Biology]]
  −
生物学
  −
* [[Zoology]]
  −
动物学
  −
* [[Psychology]]{{sfn|Kantor|1963|page=116}}{{sfn|On the Soul}}
  −
心理学
  −
* [[Physics]]
  −
物理
  −
* [[Metaphysics]]
  −
形而上学
  −
* [[Logic]]
  −
逻辑学
  −
* [[Ethics]]
  −
伦理学
  −
* [[Rhetoric]]
  −
修辞学
  −
* [[Aesthetics]]
  −
美学
  −
* [[Music]]
  −
音乐
  −
* [[Poetry]]
  −
诗歌
  −
* [[Economics]]
  −
经济学
  −
* [[Politics]]
  −
政治学
  −
* [[Government]]
  −
政府
  −
{{Endflatlist}}
     −
| notable_ideas={{Flatlist}}
     −
| notable_ideas=
+
==Speculative philosophy==
 +
思辨哲学
   −
重要思想
     −
* [[:Template:Aristotelianism|Aristotelian philosophy]]
+
===Logic===
亚里士多德哲学
+
逻辑学
   −
* [[Syllogism]]
+
{{main | Term logic}}
三段论
+
主条目:术语逻辑学
   −
* [[On the Soul|Theory of the soul]]
+
{{details | Non-Aristotelian logic}}
灵理论
+
更多信息:非亚里士多德逻辑学
   −
* [[Virtue ethics]]
  −
德性伦理
     −
| influences={{Flatlist}}
     −
| influences=
+
With the ''[[Prior Analytics]]'', Aristotle is credited with the earliest study of formal logic,{{sfn| Degnan | 1994 | pp=81–89}} and his conception of it was the dominant form of Western logic until 19th-century advances in [[mathematical logic]].{{sfn| Corcoran | 2009 | pp=1–20}} [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]] stated in the ''[[Critique of Pure Reason]]'' that with Aristotle logic reached its completion.{{sfn| Kant | 1787 | pages=Preface}}
   −
受影响于
+
With the Prior Analytics, Aristotle is credited with the earliest study of formal logic, and his conception of it was the dominant form of Western logic until 19th-century advances in mathematical logic. Kant stated in the Critique of Pure Reason that with Aristotle logic reached its completion.
   −
* [[Plato]]
+
在《先验分析学》一书中,Aristotle被认为是最早研究形式逻辑的人,并且他对形式逻辑的构想是19世纪数学逻辑发展之前西方逻辑的主导形式。康德Kant在《纯粹理性批判》中指出,有了Aristotle逻辑学才得以完善。
柏拉图
     −
* [[Socrates]]
  −
苏格拉底
  −
* [[Heraclitus]]
  −
赫拉克利特
  −
* [[Parmenides]]
  −
巴门尼德
  −
* [[Empedocles]]
  −
恩培多克勒
  −
* [[Phaleas of Chalcedon|Phaleas]]
  −
菲利司
  −
* [[Hippodamus of Miletus|Hippodamus]]
  −
希波丹姆斯
  −
* [[Hippias]]
  −
希庇亚斯
  −
{{Endflatlist}}
     −
| influenced={{longitem|Virtually all subsequent [[Western philosophy]], especially [[Aristotelianism]]  e. g. [[Averroes]], [[Thomas Aquinas|Aquinas]]. Also pre-[[Age of Enlightenment|Enlightenment]] science (see [[List of writers influenced by Aristotle]])}}
     −
| influenced=
+
====''Organon''====
 +
工具论
   −
施影响于= 几乎所有后来的西方哲学,特别是亚里士多德哲学,如阿威罗伊Averroes、阿奎那Aquinas。还有启蒙运动前的科学(见受亚里士多德影响的作家名单)
+
{{main | Organon}}
   −
{{Endflatlist}}
+
{| class="wikitable floatright"
   −
}}
+
{| class="wikitable floatright"
   −
}}
+
{ | class = “ wikitable floatright”
   −
}}
+
|+ One of Aristotle's [[Syllogism#Types|types of syllogism]]{{efn-ua|This [[Syllogism#Types|type of syllogism]], with all three terms in 'a', is known by the traditional (medieval) [[mnemonic]] [[Baralipton|B'''a'''rb'''a'''r'''a''']].{{sfn|Lagerlund|2016}}}}
    +
|+ One of Aristotle's types of syllogism}}
    +
| + Aristotle的三段论中的一种}
   −
'''Aristotle''' ({{IPAc-en|ær|ɪ|s|ˈ|t|ɒ|t|əl}};{{sfn|Collins English Dictionary}} {{lang-grc-gre|Ἀριστοτέλης}} ''Aristotélēs'', {{IPA-grc|aristotélɛːs|pron}}; 384–322&nbsp;BC) was a Greek [[philosopher]] and [[polymath]] during the [[Classical Greece|Classical period]] in [[Ancient Greece]]. Taught by [[Plato]], he was the founder of the [[Lyceum (Classical)|Lyceum]], the [[Peripatetic school]] of philosophy, and the [[Aristotelianism|Aristotelian]] tradition. His writings cover many subjects including [[Physics (Aristotle)|physics]], [[biology]], [[zoology]], [[metaphysics]], [[logic]], [[ethics]], [[aesthetics]], [[Poetics (Aristotle)|poetry]], [[theatre]], [[music]], [[rhetoric]], [[psychology]], [[linguistics]], [[economics]], [[politics]], and government. Aristotle provided a complex synthesis of the various philosophies existing prior to him. It was above all from his teachings that the West inherited its intellectual [[lexicon]], as well as problems and methods of inquiry. As a result, his philosophy has exerted a unique influence on almost every form of knowledge in the West and it continues to be a subject of contemporary philosophical discussion.
+
! In words !! In terms{{efn-ua|M is the Middle (here, Men), S is the Subject (Greeks), P is the Predicate (mortal).{{sfn|Lagerlund|2016}}}} !! In equations{{efn-ua|The first equation can be read as 'It is not true that there exists an x such that x is a man and that x is not mortal.'{{sfn|Predicate Logic}}}}
   −
Aristotle (/ærɪsˈtɒtəl/;Greek: Ἀριστοτέλης Aristotélēs, pronounced [aristotélɛːs]; 384–322 BC) was a Greek philosopher and polymath during the Classical period in Ancient Greece. Taught by Plato, he was the founder of the Lyceum, the Peripatetic school of philosophy, and the Aristotelian tradition. His writings cover many subjects including physics, biology, zoology, metaphysics, logic, ethics, aesthetics, poetry, theatre, music, rhetoric, psychology, linguistics, economics, politics, and government. Aristotle provided a complex synthesis of the various philosophies existing prior to him. It was above all from his teachings that the West inherited its intellectual lexicon, as well as problems and methods of inquiry. As a result, his philosophy has exerted a unique influence on almost every form of knowledge in the West and it continues to be a subject of contemporary philosophical discussion.
+
! In words !! In terms}} !! In equations}}
   −
亚里士多德(Aristotle)是古希腊古典时期的希腊哲学家和博学家。在’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> </font>’’’柏拉图(Plato)的指导下,他创立了吕克昂学院、哲学逍遥学派和亚里士多德传统。他的著作涉及许多学科,包括’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 物理学 physics </font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 生物学 biology </font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 动物学 zoology</font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 形而上学 metaphysics</font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 逻辑学 logic</font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 伦理学 ethics</font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 美学 aesthetics</font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 诗歌 poetry</font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 戏剧 theatre</font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 音乐music </font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 修辞学 rhetoric</font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 心理学 psychology</font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 语言学 linguistics</font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 经济学 economics</font>’’’、’’’<font color=’’#ff8000’’> 政治学 politics</font>’’’和政府。Aristotle对在他之前存在的各种哲学进行了复杂的综合。最重要的是,正是从他的教诲中,西方继承了其知识词汇,以及问题和探究方法。因此,他的哲学对西方几乎所有的知识形式都产生了独特的影响,并且继续成为当代哲学讨论的主题。
+
!用文字! !用术语} !在方程式中}
   −
Little is known about his life. Aristotle was born in the city of [[Stagira (ancient city)|Stagira]] in [[Northern Greece]]. His father, [[Nicomachus (father of Aristotle)|Nicomachus]], died when Aristotle was a child, and he was brought up by a guardian. At seventeen or eighteen years of age he joined [[Plato's Academy]] in [[Athens]] and remained there until the age of thirty-seven ([[Circa|c.]] 347 BC).{{sfn|Aristotle (384–322 B.C.E.)}} Shortly after Plato died, Aristotle left Athens and, at the request of [[Philip II of Macedon]], tutored [[Alexander the Great]] beginning in 343 BC.{{sfn|Russell| 1972}} He established a library in the [[Lyceum (Classical)|Lyceum]] which helped him to produce many of his hundreds of books on [[papyrus]] [[scrolls]]. Though Aristotle wrote many elegant treatises and dialogues for publication, only around a third of his original output has survived, none of it intended for publication.{{sfn|Barnes|1995|p=9}}
+
|-
   −
Little is known about his life. Aristotle was born in the city of Stagira in Northern Greece. His father, Nicomachus, died when Aristotle was a child, and he was brought up by a guardian. At seventeen or eighteen years of age he joined Plato's Academy in Athens and remained there until the age of thirty-seven (c. 347 BC). Shortly after Plato died, Aristotle left Athens and, at the request of Philip II of Macedon, tutored Alexander the Great beginning in 343 BC. He established a library in the Lyceum which helped him to produce many of his hundreds of books on papyrus scrolls. Though Aristotle wrote many elegant treatises and dialogues for publication, only around a third of his original output has survived, none of it intended for publication.
+
|-
   −
关于他的生平我们知之甚少。Aristotle出生于希腊北部的 斯塔基拉市。他的父亲尼科马修斯(Nicomachus),在Aristotle还是个孩子的时候就去世了,他是由一位监护人抚养长大的。十七岁的时候,他加入了雅典的柏拉图学院,一直呆到37岁(约公元前347年)。在柏拉图死后不久,Aristotle离开了雅典,在腓力二世的要求下,他从公元前343年开始辅导亚历山大大帝。他在吕克昂里建立了一个图书馆,帮助他制作了数百本纸莎草卷轴的书籍。尽管亚里士多德写了许多优美的论文和对话录供出版,但是只有三分之一的原著保存下来,没有一本打算出版。
+
|-
    +
|&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;All men are mortal.<br><br>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;All Greeks are men.<br><br>[[Therefore sign|∴]] All Greeks are mortal.||M a P<br><br>S a M<br><br>S a P||[[File:Modus Barbara Equations.svg|180px]]
    +
|&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;All men are mortal.<br><br>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;All Greeks are men.<br><br>∴ All Greeks are mortal.||M a P<br><br>S a M<br><br>S a P||180px
   −
Aristotle's views on [[Aristotelian physics|physical science]] profoundly shaped medieval scholarship. Their influence extended from [[Late Antiquity]] and the [[Early Middle Ages]] into the [[Renaissance]], and were not replaced systematically until [[Age of Enlightenment|the Enlightenment]] and theories such as [[classical mechanics]] were developed. Some of Aristotle's zoological observations found in [[Aristotle's biology|his biology]], such as on the [[Hectocotylus|hectocotyl (reproductive) arm]] of the [[octopus]], were disbelieved until the 19th century. His works contain the earliest known formal study of logic, studied by medieval scholars such as [[Peter Abelard]] and [[John Buridan]]. Aristotle's influence on logic also continued well into the 19th century.
+
所有的人都是凡人。所有的希腊人都是人。所有希腊人都是凡人。
   −
Aristotle's views on physical science profoundly shaped medieval scholarship. Their influence extended from Late Antiquity and the Early Middle Ages into the Renaissance, and were not replaced systematically until the Enlightenment and theories such as classical mechanics were developed. ’’’<font color=’’#32CD32’’> Some of Aristotle's zoological observations found in his biology, such as on the hectocotyl (reproductive) arm of the octopus, were disbelieved until the 19th century. </font>’’’ His works contain the earliest known formal study of logic, studied by medieval scholars such as Peter Abelard and John Buridan. Aristotle's influence on logic also continued well into the 19th century.
+
|}
   −
Aristotle关于物理学的观点深刻地影响了中世纪的学术研究。他们的影响从古代晚期和中世纪早期一直延伸到文艺复兴时期,直到启蒙运动和经典力学等理论的发展才被系统地取代。’’’<font color=’’#32CD32’’> Aristotle在他的生物学中发现的一些动物学观察,例如章鱼的八轴臂(繁殖臂),直到19世纪才被人们所相信。</font>’’’他的著作包含了已知最早的逻辑学研究,中世纪学者如彼得 · 阿伯拉尔Peter Abelard和约翰 · 布里丹John Buridan研究过。Aristotle对逻辑学的影响一直延续到19世纪。
+
|}
    +
|}
      −
He influenced [[Judeo-Islamic philosophies (800–1400)]] during the [[Middle Ages]], as well as [[Christian theology]], especially the [[Neoplatonism]] of the [[Early Church]] and the [[Scholasticism|scholastic]] tradition of the [[Catholic Church]]. Aristotle was revered among medieval Muslim scholars as "The First Teacher" and among medieval Christians like [[Thomas Aquinas]] as simply "The Philosopher". His ethics, though always influential, gained renewed interest with the modern advent of [[virtue ethics]], such as in the thinking of  [[Alasdair MacIntyre]] and [[Philippa Foot]].
     −
He influenced Judeo-Islamic philosophies (800–1400) during the Middle Ages, as well as Christian theology, especially the Neoplatonism of the Early Church and the scholastic tradition of the Catholic Church. Aristotle was revered among medieval Muslim scholars as "The First Teacher" and among medieval Christians like Thomas Aquinas as simply "The Philosopher". His ethics, though always influential, gained renewed interest with the modern advent of virtue ethics, such as in the thinking of Alasdair MacIntyre and Philippa Foot.
+
What we today call ''Aristotelian logic'' with its [[Syllogism#Types|types of syllogism]] (methods of logical argument),{{sfn| Lagerlund | 2016}} Aristotle himself would have labelled "analytics". The term "logic" he reserved to mean ''dialectics''. Most of Aristotle's work is probably not in its original form, because it was most likely edited by students and later lecturers. The logical works of Aristotle were compiled into a set of six books called the ''[[Organon]]'' around 40 BC by [[Andronicus of Rhodes]] or others among his followers.{{sfn| Pickover | 2009 | page=52}} The books are:
   −
他影响了中世纪的犹太-伊斯兰哲学(800-1400),也影响了基督教神学,特别是早起教会的新柏拉图主义和天主教会的经院传统。亚里士多德在中世纪的穆斯林学者中被尊为“第一导师” ,在托马斯 · 阿奎那Thomas Aquinas等中世纪基督徒中被尊为“哲学家”。他的伦理学虽然一直很有影响力,但随着现代美德伦理学的出现,例如阿拉斯代尔·麦金泰尔Alasdair MacIntyre 和菲利帕 · 福特Philippa Foot的思想,他的伦理学又重新引起了人们的兴趣。
+
What we today call Aristotelian logic with its types of syllogism (methods of logical argument), Aristotle himself would have labelled "analytics". The term "logic" he reserved to mean dialectics. Most of Aristotle's work is probably not in its original form, because it was most likely edited by students and later lecturers. The logical works of Aristotle were compiled into a set of six books called the Organon around 40 BC by Andronicus of Rhodes or others among his followers. The books are:
    +
今天我们所称的亚里士多德逻辑学及其三段论(逻辑论证的方法)的类型 ,Aristotle本人将其称为“分析学”。他把“逻辑”一词保留为辩证法的意思。Aristotle的大部分著作可能都不是原貌,因为它很可能是由学生和后来的讲师编辑的。大约在公元前40年左右,Aristotle的逻辑学著作被罗德岛的安东尼库斯Andronicus及其追随者中的其他人汇编成了一套6本书,名为《工具论》。这些书是:
    +
# ''[[Categories (Aristotle)|Categories]]''
   −
==Life==
+
Categories
生平
      +
范畴篇
   −
[[File:20160518 092 mieza nympheum.jpg | thumb | left | School of Aristotle in [[Mieza, Macedonia|Mieza]], [[Macedonia (Greece)|Macedonia, Greece]]]]
+
# ''[[On Interpretation]]''
   −
School of Aristotle in Mieza, Macedonia, Greece
+
On Interpretation
 +
解释篇
   −
Aristotle的学校,在米萨,马其顿,希腊
+
# ''[[Prior Analytics]]''
    +
Prior Analytics
   −
In general, the details of Aristotle's life are not well-established. The biographies written in ancient times are often speculative and historians only agree on a few salient points.{{efn-ua | See {{harvnb|Shields|2012|pp=3–16}}; {{harvnb|Düring|1957}} covers ancient biographies of Aristotle.}}
+
前分析篇
   −
In general, the details of Aristotle's life are not well-established. The biographies written in ancient times are often speculative and historians only agree on a few salient points.
+
# ''[[Posterior Analytics]]''
   −
总的来说,关于Aristotle生活的细节并不完整。古代的传记往往是臆测性的,历史学家们只在几个要点上达成一致。
+
Posterior Analytics
   −
Aristotle, whose name means "the best purpose" in Ancient Greek,{{sfn|Campbell}}<!--better source desirable--> was born in 384&nbsp;BC in [[Stagira (ancient city)|Stagira]], [[Chalcidice]], about 55&nbsp;km (34 miles) east of modern-day [[Thessaloniki]].{{sfn|McLeisch|1999|p=5}}{{sfn|Aristoteles-Park in Stagira}} His father [[Nicomachus (father of Aristotle)|Nicomachus]] was the personal physician to [[Amyntas III of Macedon|King Amyntas of Macedon]]. Both of Aristotle's parents died when he was about thirteen, and [[Proxenus of Atarneus]] became his guardian.{{sfn|Hall|2018|p=14}} Although little information about Aristotle's childhood has survived, he probably spent some time within the Macedonian palace, making his first connections with the [[Macedonia (ancient kingdom)#Kingship and the royal court|Macedonian monarchy]].{{sfn|Anagnostopoulos|2013|page=4}}
+
后分析篇
   −
Aristotle, whose name means "the best purpose" in Ancient Greek,was born in 384 BC in Stagira, Chalcidice, about 55 km (34 miles) east of modern-day Thessaloniki.His father Nicomachus was the personal physician to King Amyntas of Macedon. Both of Aristotle's parents died when he was about thirteen, and Proxenus of Atarneus became his guardian.Although little information about Aristotle's childhood has survived, he probably spent some time within the Macedonian palace, making his first connections with the Macedonian monarchy.
+
# ''[[Topics (Aristotle)|Topics]]''
    +
Topics
   −
Aristotle的名字在古希腊语中意为“最好的目的”,他出生于公元前384年,位于查尔基迪斯的斯塔吉拉,距现代塞萨洛尼基东约55公里(34英里)。他的父亲Nicomachus是马其顿国王阿米尼塔斯Amyntas的私人医生。Aristotle的父母均在他十三岁时去世,而来自阿塔尼厄斯的普罗齐诺斯Proxenus成为了他的监护人。尽管关于亚里士多德童年的信息很少,但他可能在马其顿宫殿里呆过一段时间,与马其顿君主政体初次接触。
+
论题篇
    +
# ''[[On Sophistical Refutations]]''
    +
On Sophistical Refutations辩谬篇
   −
At the age of seventeen or eighteen, Aristotle moved to Athens to continue his education at [[Platonic Academy|Plato's Academy]].{{sfn|Blits|1999|pp=58–63}} He probably experienced the [[Eleusinian Mysteries]] as he wrote when describing the sights one viewed at the Eleusinian Mysteries, "to experience is to learn" [παθείν μαθεĩν].{{sfn|Evans|2006}} Aristotle remained in Athens for nearly twenty years before leaving in 348/47&nbsp;BC. The traditional story about his departure records that he was disappointed with the Academy's direction after control passed to Plato's nephew [[Speusippus]], although it is possible that he feared the anti-Macedonian sentiments in Athens at that time and left before Plato died.{{sfn|Aristotle|1984|pp=Introduction}} Aristotle then accompanied [[Xenocrates]] to the court of his friend [[Hermias of Atarneus]] in [[Asia Minor]]. After the death of Hermias, Aristotle travelled with his pupil [[Theophrastus]] to the island of [[Lesbos]], where together they researched the [[botany]] and zoology of the island and its sheltered lagoon. While in Lesbos, Aristotle married [[Pythias]], either Hermias's adoptive daughter or niece. She bore him a daughter, whom they also named Pythias. In 343 BC, Aristotle was invited by [[Philip II of Macedon]] to become the tutor to his son [[Alexander the Great|Alexander]].{{sfn|Shields|2016}}{{sfn|Russell|1972}}
+
[[File:Sanzio 01 Plato Aristotle.jpg | thumb | upright | [[Plato]] (left) and Aristotle in [[Raphael]]'s 1509 fresco, ''[[The School of Athens]]''. Aristotle holds his ''[[Nicomachean Ethics]]'' and gestures to the earth, representing his view in immanent realism, whilst Plato gestures to the heavens, indicating his Theory of Forms, and holds his ''[[Timaeus (dialogue)|Timaeus]]''.{{sfn| School of Athens}}{{sfn|Stewart|2019}}]]
   −
At the age of seventeen or eighteen, Aristotle moved to Athens to continue his education at Plato's Academy.He probably experienced the Eleusinian Mysteries as he wrote when describing the sights one viewed at the Eleusinian Mysteries, "to experience is to learn" [παθείν μαθεĩν].Aristotle remained in Athens for nearly twenty years before leaving in 348/47 BC. The traditional story about his departure records that he was disappointed with the Academy's direction after control passed to Plato's nephew Speusippus, although it is possible that he feared the anti-Macedonian sentiments in Athens at that time and left before Plato died.Aristotle then accompanied Xenocrates to the court of his friend Hermias of Atarneus in Asia Minor. After the death of Hermias, Aristotle travelled with his pupil Theophrastus to the island of Lesbos, where together they researched the botany and zoology of the island and its sheltered lagoon. While in Lesbos, Aristotle married Pythias, either Hermias's adoptive daughter or niece. She bore him a daughter, whom they also named Pythias. In 343 BC, Aristotle was invited by Philip II of Macedon to become the tutor to his son Alexander.
+
[[Plato (left) and Aristotle in Raphael's 1509 fresco, The School of Athens. Aristotle holds his Nicomachean Ethics and gestures to the earth, representing his view in immanent realism, whilst Plato gestures to the heavens, indicating his Theory of Forms, and holds his Timaeus.]]
   −
在十七八岁时,Aristotle移居雅典,在柏拉图学院继续他的学业。他可能经历过厄琉息斯秘仪,正如他在描述在厄琉息斯秘仪观察到的景象时所写的,“经历就是学习”[ παεθν αθν μθν ]。Aristotle在公元前348/47年离开之前,在雅典呆了将近20年。关于他离开的传统故事记载,在Plato的侄子斯皮普斯 Speusippus掌管学院后,他对学院发展方向感到失望,尽管他可能害怕当时雅典的反马其顿情绪,并在柏拉图去世之前离开了。随后,Aristotle陪同齐诺克利特Xenocrates来到小亚细亚的他的朋友阿塔尼厄斯的赫米亚Hermias的宫廷。Hermias死后,Aristotle和他的学生泰奥弗拉斯特斯Theophrastus前往莱斯博斯岛,在那里他们一起研究了岛上及其环礁湖的植物学和动物学。在莱斯博斯岛的时候,Aristotle与Hermias的养女或侄女皮提亚斯Pythias结婚。她为他生了一个女儿,他们也给她起名叫Pythias。公元前343年,腓力二世邀请Aristotle成为他儿子亚历山大Alexander的家庭教师。
+
Plato(左)和Aristotle在拉斐尔Raphael 1509年的壁画《雅典学校》中。Aristotle拿着他的《尼各马可伦理学》,对着大地做手势,代表了他的内在现实主义观点,而Plato则对着天空做手势,表示他的《形式论》,并拿着他的《提马亚斯》。
         −
[[File:Aristoteles Louvre.jpg | thumb | upright | [[Bust (sculpture)|Portrait bust]] of Aristotle; an [[Roman Empire|Imperial Roman]] (1st or 2nd century AD) copy of a lost [[bronze sculpture]] made by [[Lysippos]]]]
+
The order of the books (or the teachings from which they are composed) is not certain, but this list was derived from analysis of Aristotle's writings. It goes from the basics, the analysis of simple terms in the ''Categories,'' the analysis of propositions and their elementary relations in ''On Interpretation'', to the study of more complex forms, namely, syllogisms (in the ''Analytics''){{sfn| Prior Analytics | pp= 24b18–20}}{{sfn| Bobzien | 2015}} and dialectics (in the ''Topics'' and ''Sophistical Refutations''). The first three treatises form the core of the logical theory ''stricto sensu'': the grammar of the language of logic and the correct rules of reasoning. The ''Rhetoric'' is not conventionally included, but it states that it relies on the ''Topics''.{{sfn| Smith | 2017}}
   −
Portrait bust of Aristotle; an Imperial Roman (1st or 2nd century AD) copy of a lost bronze sculpture made by Lysippos
+
The order of the books (or the teachings from which they are composed) is not certain, but this list was derived from analysis of Aristotle's writings. It goes from the basics, the analysis of simple terms in the Categories, the analysis of propositions and their elementary relations in On Interpretation, to the study of more complex forms, namely, syllogisms (in the Analytics) and dialectics (in the Topics and Sophistical Refutations). The first three treatises form the core of the logical theory stricto sensu: the grammar of the language of logic and the correct rules of reasoning. The Rhetoric is not conventionally included, but it states that it relies on the Topics.
   −
Aristotle的肖像半身像; 罗马帝国时期(公元1世纪或2世纪)利西波斯仿制的失落青铜雕像
+
这些书的顺序(或者说它们所组成的教义)并不确定,但是这个清单是通过对亚里士多德著作的分析中得出的。它从基础知识,《范畴篇》中对简单术语的分析,《解释篇》中对命题及其基本关系的分析,到研究更复杂的形式,即三段论(在《分析篇》中)和辩证法(在《论题篇与辩谬篇》中)。前三篇论述构成了严格意义上的逻辑理论的核心: 逻辑语言的语法和正确的推理规则。《修辞学》没有按照惯例包括在内,但它指出它依赖于《论题篇》。
         −
Aristotle was appointed as the head of the royal academy of [[Macedon]]. During Aristotle's time in the Macedonian court, he gave lessons not only to Alexander, but also to two other future kings: [[Ptolemy I Soter|Ptolemy]] and [[Cassander]].{{sfn|Green|1991|pp=58–59}} Aristotle encouraged Alexander toward eastern conquest, and Aristotle's own attitude towards [[Persia]] was unabashedly [[Ethnocentricism|ethnocentric]]. In one famous example, he counsels Alexander to be "a leader to the Greeks and a despot to the barbarians, to look after the former as after friends and relatives, and to deal with the latter as with beasts or plants".{{sfn|Green|1991|pp=58–59}} By 335&nbsp;BC, Aristotle had returned to Athens, establishing his own school there known as the [[Lyceum (Classical)|Lyceum]]. Aristotle conducted courses at the school for the next twelve years. While in Athens, his wife Pythias died and Aristotle became involved with [[Herpyllis]] of Stagira, who bore him a son whom he named after his father, [[Nicomachus (son of Aristotle)|Nicomachus]]. If we believed the ''[[Suda]]'' (an uncritical compilation from the Middle Ages) he may also had an ''[[eromenos|erômenos]]'', [[Palaephatus | Palaephatus of Abydus]].{{sfn|Smith|2007|p=88}}
+
===Metaphysics===
 +
形而上学
   −
Aristotle was appointed as the head of the royal academy of Macedon. During Aristotle's time in the Macedonian court, he gave lessons not only to Alexander, but also to two other future kings: Ptolemy and Cassander. Aristotle encouraged Alexander toward eastern conquest, and Aristotle's own attitude towards Persia was unabashedly ethnocentric. In one famous example, he counsels Alexander to be "a leader to the Greeks and a despot to the barbarians, to look after the former as after friends and relatives, and to deal with the latter as with beasts or plants". By 335&nbsp;BC, Aristotle had returned to Athens, establishing his own school there known as the Lyceum. Aristotle conducted courses at the school for the next twelve years. While in Athens, his wife Pythias died and Aristotle became involved with Herpyllis of Stagira, who bore him a son whom he named after his father, Nicomachus. If we believed the Suda (an uncritical compilation from the Middle Ages) ’’’<font color=’’#32CD32’’> he may also had an erômenos,  Palaephatus of Abydus.</font>’’’
+
{{main|Metaphysics (Aristotle)}}
Aristotle被任命为马其顿皇家学院院长。Aristotle在马其顿宫廷的时候,他不仅向亚历山大授课,还向未来的另外两位国王授课: 托勒密Ptolemy和卡山德Cassander。Aristotle鼓励Alexander去征服东方,而Aristotle本人对波斯的态度是毫不掩饰的种族中心主义。在一个著名的例子中,他建议Alexander成为“希腊人的领袖,野蛮人的暴君,像对待亲友一样对待前者,像对待动物或植物一样对待后者”。到公元前335年,Aristotle回到雅典,在那里建立了他自己的学校,被称为吕克昂。在接下来的十二年里,Aristotle在学校里开设课程。在雅典期间,他的妻子Pythias去世,Aristotle与斯塔吉拉的赫皮利斯Herpyllis有染,Herpyllis为他生了一个儿子,Aristotle以他父亲Nicomachus的名字给他取名。如果我们相信苏达(中世纪的一个不严谨的汇编) ,’’’<font color=’’#32CD32’’>他可能也有一个 erômenos,Palaephatus of Abydus。 </font>’’’
      +
The word "metaphysics" appears to have been coined by the first century AD editor who assembled various small selections of Aristotle's works to the treatise we know by the name ''Metaphysics''.{{sfn| Cohen | 2000}} Aristotle called it "first philosophy", and distinguished it from mathematics and natural science (physics) as the contemplative (''theoretikē'') philosophy which is "theological" and studies the divine. He wrote in his ''Metaphysics'' (1026a16):
   −
This period in Athens, between 335 and 323 BC, is when Aristotle is believed to have composed many of his works.{{sfn|Russell|1972}} He wrote many dialogues, of which only fragments have survived. Those works that have survived are in [[treatise]] form and were not, for the most part, intended for widespread publication; they are generally thought to be lecture aids for his students. His most important treatises include ''[[Physics (Aristotle)|Physics]]'', ''[[Metaphysics (Aristotle)|Metaphysics]]'', ''[[Nicomachean Ethics]]'', ''[[Politics (Aristotle)|Politics]]'', ''[[On the Soul]]'' and ''[[Poetics (Aristotle)|Poetics]]''. Aristotle studied and made significant contributions to "logic, metaphysics, mathematics, physics, biology, botany, ethics, politics, agriculture, medicine, dance and theatre."{{sfn|Aristotle (384–322 B.C.E.)}}
+
The word "metaphysics" appears to have been coined by the first century AD editor who assembled various small selections of Aristotle's works to the treatise we know by the name Metaphysics. Aristotle called it "first philosophy", and distinguished it from mathematics and natural science (physics) as the contemplative (theoretikē) philosophy which is "theological" and studies the divine. He wrote in his Metaphysics (1026a16):
   −
This period in Athens, between 335 and 323 BC, is when Aristotle is believed to have composed many of his works. He wrote many dialogues, of which only fragments have survived. Those works that have survived are in treatise form and were not, for the most part, intended for widespread publication; they are generally thought to be lecture aids for his students. His most important treatises include Physics, Metaphysics, Nicomachean Ethics, Politics, On the Soul and Poetics. Aristotle studied and made significant contributions to "logic, metaphysics, mathematics, physics, biology, botany, ethics, politics, agriculture, medicine, dance and theatre."
+
“形而上学”一词似乎是由公元一世纪的一位广告编辑创造的,他把Aristotle的作品中的一些小片段汇编成我们所知的《形而上学》这篇论文。Aristotle称之为“第一哲学” ,并把它与数学和自然科学(物理学)区别开来,是一种沉思的(理论)哲学,即“神学”和研究神性。他在《形而上学》(1026a16)中写道:
   −
公元前335年至公元前323年的雅典时期,被认为是Aristotle创作许多作品的时期。他写了许多对话录,其中只有一些片段留存了下来。那些留存下来的作品都是论文形式的,而且大部分并不打算广泛出版; 它们通常被认为是他的学生的讲课辅助工具。他最重要的论著包括《物理学》、《形而上学》、《尼各马可伦理学》、《政治学》、《论灵魂》和《诗学》。Aristotle对j逻辑学、形而上学、数学、物理学、生物学、植物学、伦理学、政治学、农业、医学、舞蹈和戏剧学”都有研究,并作出了重大贡献
         +
{{quote | if there were no other independent things besides the composite natural ones, the study of nature would be the primary kind of knowledge; but if there is some motionless independent thing, the knowledge of this precedes it and is first philosophy, and it is universal ''in just this way'', because it is first. And it belongs to this sort of philosophy to study being as being, both what it is and what belongs to it just by virtue of being.{{sfn| Aristotle | 1999 | page=111}}}}
   −
Near the end of his life, Alexander and Aristotle became estranged over Alexander's relationship with Persia and Persians. A widespread tradition in antiquity suspected Aristotle of playing a role in Alexander's death, but the only evidence of this is an [[Hagnothemis|unlikely claim]] made some six years after the death.{{sfn|Green|1991|p=460}} Following Alexander's death, anti-Macedonian sentiment in Athens was rekindled. In 322&nbsp;BC, Demophilus and [[Eurymedon the Hierophant]] reportedly denounced Aristotle for impiety,{{sfn|Filonik|2013|pp=72–73}} prompting him to flee to his mother's family estate in [[Chalcis | Chalcis, on Euboea]], at which occasion he was said to have stated: "I will not allow the Athenians to sin twice against philosophy"{{sfn|Jones|1980|p=216}}{{sfn|Gigon|2017|p=41}}{{sfn|Düring|1957|p=T44a-e}} – a reference to Athens's [[Trial of Socrates|trial and execution of Socrates]]. He died on Euboea of natural causes later that same year, having named his student [[Antipater]] as his chief [[executor]] and leaving a [[Will (law)|will]] in which he asked to be buried next to his wife.{{sfn|Haase|1992|p=3862}}
+
如果除了复合的自然事物之外,没有其他独立的事物,那么对自然的研究将是主要的一种知识;但是,如果有不动的独立的事物,那么对于这种独立的东西的认识就先于它而成为第一哲学,因此它就具有普遍性,因为它是第一的。而这种哲学,既要研究作为存在的存在,也要研究由于存在而属于存在的存在。
   −
Near the end of his life, Alexander and Aristotle became estranged over Alexander's relationship with Persia and Persians. A widespread tradition in antiquity suspected Aristotle of playing a role in Alexander's death, but the only evidence of this is an unlikely claim made some six years after the death. Following Alexander's death, anti-Macedonian sentiment in Athens was rekindled. In 322&nbsp;BC, Demophilus and Eurymedon the Hierophant reportedly denounced Aristotle for impiety, prompting him to flee to his mother's family estate in  Chalcis, on Euboea, at which occasion he was said to have stated: "I will not allow the Athenians to sin twice against philosophy" – a reference to Athens's trial and execution of Socrates. He died on Euboea of natural causes later that same year, having named his student Antipater as his chief executor and leaving a will in which he asked to be buried next to his wife.
     −
在他生命的最后阶段,Alexander和Aristotle因为Alexander与波斯和波斯人的关系而变得疏远。古代有一个广泛流传的传说,怀疑Aristotle在Alexander的死亡中扮演了一个角色,但是唯一的证据是在Alexander死后大约六年提出的一个不太可能的断言。Alexander死后,雅典的反马其顿情绪重新燃起。公元前322年,据说 德摩菲勒斯 Demophilus 和赫拉菲顿Eurymedon 谴责Aristotle不敬神,促使他逃往他母亲在埃维厄岛哈尔基斯的家族庄园,据说当时他说: “我不允许雅典人两次违背哲学”——指的是雅典对苏格拉底的审判和处决。同年晚些时候,他因自然原因在埃维厄岛去世,指定他的学生安提帕特Antipater为他的首席遗嘱执行人,并留下一份遗嘱,要求与妻子葬在一起。
+
==== Substance ====
 +
物质
    +
{{see | Hylomorphism }}
      −
==Speculative philosophy==
  −
思辨哲学
      +
Aristotle examines the concepts of [[Substance theory|substance]] (''ousia'') and [[essence]] (''to ti ên einai'', "the what it was to be") in his ''Metaphysics'' (Book VII), and he concludes that a particular substance is a combination of both matter and form, a philosophical theory called [[hylomorphism]]. In Book VIII, he distinguishes the matter of the substance as the [[Material substratum|substratum]], or the stuff of which it is composed. For example, the matter of a house is the bricks, stones, timbers etc., or whatever constitutes the ''potential'' house, while the form of the substance is the ''actual'' house, namely 'covering for bodies and chattels' or any other [[Genus-differentia definition|differentia]] that let us define something as a house. The formula that gives the components is the account of the matter, and the formula that gives the differentia is the account of the form.{{sfn| Metaphysics | p=VIII 1043a 10–30}}{{sfn| Cohen | 2016}}
   −
===Logic===
+
Aristotle examines the concepts of substance (ousia) and essence (to ti ên einai, "the what it was to be") in his Metaphysics (Book VII), and he concludes that a particular substance is a combination of both matter and form, a philosophical theory called hylomorphism. In Book VIII, he distinguishes the matter of the substance as the substratum, or the stuff of which it is composed. For example, the matter of a house is the bricks, stones, timbers etc., or whatever constitutes the potential house, while the form of the substance is the actual house, namely 'covering for bodies and chattels' or any other differentia that let us define something as a house. The formula that gives the components is the account of the matter, and the formula that gives the differentia is the account of the form.
逻辑学
     −
{{main | Term logic}}
+
Aristotle在《形而上学》(第七卷)中研究了物质和本质的概念,他得出结论说,一种特殊的物质是物质和形式的结合体,这是一种哲学理论,称为形式质料说。在第八卷中,他将物质区分为基础,或构成物质的材料。例如,房子的物质是砖、石头、木材等,或任何构成潜在房子的物质,而实体的形式是实际的房子,即“覆盖身体和动产”或任何其他差异,让我们定义一些东西为房子。给出分量的公式是对物质的描述,给出微分的公式是对形式的描述。
主条目:术语逻辑学
     −
{{details | Non-Aristotelian logic}}
  −
更多信息:非亚里士多德逻辑学
         +
===== Immanent realism =====
 +
内在实在论
   −
With the ''[[Prior Analytics]]'', Aristotle is credited with the earliest study of formal logic,{{sfn| Degnan | 1994 | pp=81–89}} and his conception of it was the dominant form of Western logic until 19th-century advances in [[mathematical logic]].{{sfn| Corcoran | 2009 | pp=1–20}} [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]] stated in the ''[[Critique of Pure Reason]]'' that with Aristotle logic reached its completion.{{sfn| Kant | 1787 | pages=Preface}}
+
[[File:Platonic and Aristotelian Forms.svg | thumb | upright=1.6 | [[Plato]]'s [[Theory of forms|forms]] exist as [[universals]], like the ideal form of an apple. For Aristotle, both matter and form belong to the individual thing ([[hylomorphism]]).]]
   −
With the Prior Analytics, Aristotle is credited with the earliest study of formal logic, and his conception of it was the dominant form of Western logic until 19th-century advances in mathematical logic. Kant stated in the Critique of Pure Reason that with Aristotle logic reached its completion.
+
[[Plato's forms exist as universals, like the ideal form of an apple. For Aristotle, both matter and form belong to the individual thing (hylomorphism).]]
   −
在《先验分析学》一书中,Aristotle被认为是最早研究形式逻辑的人,并且他对形式逻辑的构想是19世纪数学逻辑发展之前西方逻辑的主导形式。康德Kant在《纯粹理性批判》中指出,有了Aristotle逻辑学才得以完善。
+
Plato的形式是普遍存在的,就像苹果的理想形式一样。对于Aristotle而言,物质和形式都属于单个事物(形式质料说)
    +
{{main|Aristotle's theory of universals}}
    +
Like his teacher Plato, Aristotle's philosophy aims at the [[Problem of universals|universal]]. Aristotle's [[ontology]] places the universal (''katholou'') in [[particular]]s (''kath' hekaston''), things in the world, whereas for Plato the universal is a separately existing form which actual things imitate.  For Aristotle, "form" is still what [[phenomena]] are based on, but is "instantiated" in a particular substance.{{sfn| Cohen | 2016}}
   −
====''Organon''====
+
Like his teacher Plato, Aristotle's philosophy aims at the universal. Aristotle's ontology places the universal (katholou) in particulars (kath' hekaston), things in the world, whereas for Plato the universal is a separately existing form which actual things imitate.  For Aristotle, "form" is still what phenomena are based on, but is "instantiated" in a particular substance.
工具论
     −
{{main | Organon}}
+
和他的老师Plato一样,Aristotle的哲学也着眼于普遍性。Aristotle的本体论把普遍性(天主教)至于特殊性(凯斯的希卡斯顿),即世界上的事物中,而对Plato来说,普遍性是实际事物模仿的一种单独存在的形式。对于Aristotle来说,“形式”仍然是现象的基础,但是在特定的实体中被“实例化”了。
   −
{| class="wikitable floatright"
     −
{| class="wikitable floatright"
     −
{ | class = “ wikitable floatright”
+
Plato argued that all things have a [[Theory of forms|universal form]], which could be either a property or a relation to other things. When we look at an apple, for example, we see an apple, and we can also analyse a form of an apple. In this distinction, there is a particular apple and a universal form of an apple. Moreover, we can place an apple next to a book, so that we can speak of both the book and apple as being next to each other. Plato argued that there are some universal forms that are not a part of particular things. For example, it is possible that there is no particular good in existence, but "good" is still a proper universal form. Aristotle disagreed with Plato on this point, arguing that all universals are instantiated at some period of time, and that there are no universals that are unattached to existing things. In addition, Aristotle disagreed with Plato about the location of universals. Where Plato spoke of the world of forms, a place where all universal forms subsist, Aristotle maintained that universals exist within each thing on which each universal is predicated. So, according to Aristotle, the form of apple exists within each apple, rather than in the world of the forms.{{sfn| Cohen | 2016}}{{sfn| Lloyd | 1968 | pages=43–47}}
   −
|+ One of Aristotle's [[Syllogism#Types|types of syllogism]]{{efn-ua|This [[Syllogism#Types|type of syllogism]], with all three terms in 'a', is known by the traditional (medieval) [[mnemonic]] [[Baralipton|B'''a'''rb'''a'''r'''a''']].{{sfn|Lagerlund|2016}}}}
+
Plato argued that all things have a universal form, which could be either a property or a relation to other things. When we look at an apple, for example, we see an apple, and we can also analyse a form of an apple. In this distinction, there is a particular apple and a universal form of an apple. Moreover, we can place an apple next to a book, so that we can speak of both the book and apple as being next to each other. Plato argued that there are some universal forms that are not a part of particular things. For example, it is possible that there is no particular good in existence, but "good" is still a proper universal form. Aristotle disagreed with Plato on this point, arguing that all universals are instantiated at some period of time, and that there are no universals that are unattached to existing things. In addition, Aristotle disagreed with Plato about the location of universals. Where Plato spoke of the world of forms, a place where all universal forms subsist, Aristotle maintained that universals exist within each thing on which each universal is predicated. So, according to Aristotle, the form of apple exists within each apple, rather than in the world of the forms.
   −
|+ One of Aristotle's types of syllogism}}
+
Plato认为,一切事物都有一个普遍的形式,这个形式可以是一种属性,也可以是与其他事物的关系。例如,当我们看一个苹果时,我们看到的是一个苹果,也可以分析出一个苹果的形式。在这种区分中,有一个特殊的苹果和一个苹果的普遍形式。此外,我们还可以把苹果放在一本书旁边,这样我们就可以把书和苹果都说成是相邻的。柏拉图认为,有一些普遍形式不是特定事物的一部分。例如,有可能没有特定的善存在,但 "善 "仍然是一种恰当的普遍形式。Aristotle在这一点上不同意柏拉图的观点,认为所有的普遍性都是在某个时期被实例化的,不存在不依附于现存事物的普遍性。此外,m在普遍性的位置问题上也与柏拉图意见相左。Plato所说的形式世界,是所有普遍形式都存在的地方,而m则认为,普遍性存在于每个普遍性所依托的每个事物之中。所以,根据m的观点,苹果的形式存在于每个苹果之内,而不是存在于形式世界之中。
   −
| + Aristotle的三段论中的一种}
     −
! In words !! In terms{{efn-ua|M is the Middle (here, Men), S is the Subject (Greeks), P is the Predicate (mortal).{{sfn|Lagerlund|2016}}}} !! In equations{{efn-ua|The first equation can be read as 'It is not true that there exists an x such that x is a man and that x is not mortal.'{{sfn|Predicate Logic}}}}
     −
! In words !! In terms}} !! In equations}}
+
===== Potentiality and actuality =====
 +
潜力和现实
   −
!用文字! !用术语} !在方程式中}
+
{{see | Potentiality and actuality (Aristotle)}}
   −
|-
     −
|-
     −
|-
+
With regard to the change (''[[Potentiality and actuality|kinesis]]'') and its causes now, as he defines in his ''[[Physics (Aristotle)|Physics]]'' and ''[[On Generation and Corruption]]'' 319b–320a, he distinguishes the coming to be from:
   −
|&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;All men are mortal.<br><br>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;All Greeks are men.<br><br>[[Therefore sign|∴]] All Greeks are mortal.||M a P<br><br>S a M<br><br>S a P||[[File:Modus Barbara Equations.svg|180px]]
+
With regard to the change (kinesis) and its causes now, as he defines in his Physics and On Generation and Corruption 319b–320a, he distinguishes the coming to be from:
   −
|&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;All men are mortal.<br><br>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;All Greeks are men.<br><br>∴ All Greeks are mortal.||M a P<br><br>S a M<br><br>S a P||180px
+
关于现在的变化(运动)及其原因,正如他在《物理学》和《论生成与腐败》319b-320a 中所定义的那样,他将变化的来源区分为:
   −
所有的人都是凡人。所有的希腊人都是人。所有希腊人都是凡人。
     −
|}
     −
|}
+
# growth and diminution, which is change in quantity;
   −
|}
+
growth and diminution, which is change in quantity;
    +
增长和减少,即数量的变化;
    +
# locomotion, which is change in space; and
   −
What we today call ''Aristotelian logic'' with its [[Syllogism#Types|types of syllogism]] (methods of logical argument),{{sfn| Lagerlund | 2016}} Aristotle himself would have labelled "analytics". The term "logic" he reserved to mean ''dialectics''. Most of Aristotle's work is probably not in its original form, because it was most likely edited by students and later lecturers. The logical works of Aristotle were compiled into a set of six books called the ''[[Organon]]'' around 40 BC by [[Andronicus of Rhodes]] or others among his followers.{{sfn| Pickover | 2009 | page=52}} The books are:
+
locomotion, which is change in space; and
   −
What we today call Aristotelian logic with its types of syllogism (methods of logical argument), Aristotle himself would have labelled "analytics". The term "logic" he reserved to mean dialectics. Most of Aristotle's work is probably not in its original form, because it was most likely edited by students and later lecturers. The logical works of Aristotle were compiled into a set of six books called the Organon around 40 BC by Andronicus of Rhodes or others among his followers. The books are:
+
运动,即空间的变化; 以及
   −
今天我们所称的亚里士多德逻辑学及其三段论(逻辑论证的方法)的类型 ,Aristotle本人将其称为“分析学”。他把“逻辑”一词保留为辩证法的意思。Aristotle的大部分著作可能都不是原貌,因为它很可能是由学生和后来的讲师编辑的。大约在公元前40年左右,Aristotle的逻辑学著作被罗德岛的安东尼库斯Andronicus及其追随者中的其他人汇编成了一套6本书,名为《工具论》。这些书是:
+
# alteration, which is change in quality.
   −
# ''[[Categories (Aristotle)|Categories]]''
+
alteration, which is change in quality.
   −
Categories
+
改变,也就是质量的改变。
   −
范畴篇
     −
# ''[[On Interpretation]]''
     −
On Interpretation
+
[[File:Flute-player dolphin Alcesti Group MAN.jpg | thumb | Aristotle argued that a capability like playing the flute could be acquired – [[Potentiality and actuality (Aristotle)|the potential made actual]] – by learning.]]
解释篇
     −
# ''[[Prior Analytics]]''
+
Flute-player dolphin Alcesti Group MAN.jpg | thumb | Aristotle argued that a capability like playing the flute could be acquired – Potentiality and actuality (Aristotle)|the potential made actual
   −
Prior Analytics
+
m认为,通过学习可以获得像吹长笛这样的能力-使潜力得以实现。
   −
前分析篇
     −
# ''[[Posterior Analytics]]''
     −
Posterior Analytics
+
The coming to be is a change where nothing persists of which the resultant is a property. In that particular change he introduces the concept of potentiality (''[[Dunamis|dynamis]]'') and actuality (''[[entelecheia]]'') in association with the matter and the form. Referring to potentiality, this is what a thing is capable of doing, or being acted upon, if the conditions are right and it is not prevented by something else. For example, the seed of a plant in the soil is potentially (''dynamei'') plant, and if it is not prevented by something, it will become a plant. Potentially beings can either 'act' (''poiein'') or 'be acted upon' (''paschein''), which can be either innate or learned. For example, the eyes possess the potentiality of sight (innate – being acted upon), while the capability of playing the flute can be possessed by learning (exercise – acting). Actuality is the fulfilment of the end of the potentiality. Because the end (''telos'') is the principle of every change, and for the sake of the end exists potentiality, therefore actuality is the end. Referring then to our previous example, we could say that an actuality is when a plant does one of the activities that plants do.{{sfn| Cohen | 2016}}
   −
后分析篇
+
The coming to be is a change where nothing persists of which the resultant is a property. In that particular change he introduces the concept of potentiality (dynamis) and actuality (entelecheia) in association with the matter and the form. Referring to potentiality, this is what a thing is capable of doing, or being acted upon, if the conditions are right and it is not prevented by something else. For example, the seed of a plant in the soil is potentially (dynamei) plant, and if it is not prevented by something, it will become a plant. Potentially beings can either 'act' (poiein) or 'be acted upon' (paschein), which can be either innate or learned. For example, the eyes possess the potentiality of sight (innate – being acted upon), while the capability of playing the flute can be possessed by learning (exercise – acting). Actuality is the fulfilment of the end of the potentiality. Because the end (telos) is the principle of every change, and for the sake of the end exists potentiality, therefore actuality is the end. Referring then to our previous example, we could say that an actuality is when a plant does one of the activities that plants do.
   −
# ''[[Topics (Aristotle)|Topics]]''
+
形成是一种变化,其中没有任何东西持续存在,其结果是一种属性。在这种特殊的变化中,他引入了与物质和形式相相关的潜在性(动力)和现实性(真实性)的概念。所谓潜在性,是指一个事物在条件合适且不受其他事物阻碍的情况下,能够做什么或被什么所影响。例如,土壤中植物的种子是潜在的(dynamei )植物,如果不受某种东西的阻止,它就会成为植物。潜在的生命可以 "行动"(poiein)或 "被行动"(paschein),这可以是天生的,也可以是后天的。例如,眼睛具有视觉潜能(先天行为) ,而长笛演奏能力可以通过学习(练习作用)来实现。实际性是潜能最终的实现。因为目的是一切变化的原则,而为了目的而存在着潜能,所以现实性就是目的。那么,参照我们前面的例子,我们可以说,实际性是指植物做了植物所做的活动之一。
   −
Topics
     −
论题篇
+
{{quote | For that for the sake of which (''to hou heneka'') a thing is, is its principle, and the becoming is for the sake of the end; and the actuality is the end, and it is for the sake of this that the potentiality is acquired. For animals do not see in order that they may have sight, but they have sight that they may see.{{sfn| Metaphysics | p=IX 1050a 5–10}}}}
   −
# ''[[On Sophistical Refutations]]''
+
事物的存在,就是它的原则,成为就是它的目的;现实性就是目的,为了达到目的,才能获得潜在性。因为动物看东西不是为了它们有视力,而是它们有视力才会看。
   −
On Sophistical Refutations辩谬篇
     −
[[File:Sanzio 01 Plato Aristotle.jpg | thumb | upright | [[Plato]] (left) and Aristotle in [[Raphael]]'s 1509 fresco, ''[[The School of Athens]]''. Aristotle holds his ''[[Nicomachean Ethics]]'' and gestures to the earth, representing his view in immanent realism, whilst Plato gestures to the heavens, indicating his Theory of Forms, and holds his ''[[Timaeus (dialogue)|Timaeus]]''.{{sfn| School of Athens}}{{sfn|Stewart|2019}}]]
+
In summary, the matter used to make a house has potentiality to be a house and both the activity of building and the form of the final house are actualities, which is also a [[final cause]] or end. Then Aristotle proceeds and concludes that the actuality is prior to potentiality in formula, in time and in substantiality. With this definition of the particular substance (i.e., matter and form), Aristotle tries to solve the problem of the unity of the beings, for example, "what is it that makes a man one"? Since, according to [[Plato]] there are two Ideas: animal and biped, how then is man a unity? However, according to Aristotle, the potential being (matter) and the actual one (form) are one and the same.{{sfn| Cohen | 2016}}{{sfn| Metaphysics | p=VIII 1045a–b}}
   −
[[Plato (left) and Aristotle in Raphael's 1509 fresco, The School of Athens. Aristotle holds his Nicomachean Ethics and gestures to the earth, representing his view in immanent realism, whilst Plato gestures to the heavens, indicating his Theory of Forms, and holds his Timaeus.]]
+
In summary, the matter used to make a house has potentiality to be a house and both the activity of building and the form of the final house are actualities, which is also a final cause or end. Then Aristotle proceeds and concludes that the actuality is prior to potentiality in formula, in time and in substantiality. With this definition of the particular substance (i.e., matter and form), Aristotle tries to solve the problem of the unity of the beings, for example, "what is it that makes a man one"? Since, according to Plato there are two Ideas: animal and biped, how then is man a unity? However, according to Aristotle, the potential being (matter) and the actual one (form) are one and the same.
   −
Plato(左)和Aristotle在拉斐尔Raphael 1509年的壁画《雅典学校》中。Aristotle拿着他的《尼各马可伦理学》,对着大地做手势,代表了他的内在现实主义观点,而Plato则对着天空做手势,表示他的《形式论》,并拿着他的《提马亚斯》。
+
综上所述,用来造房子的物质具有成为房子的可能性,而建造房子的活动和最后房子的形式都是实际性,这也是最后的原因或目的。接着,m又得出结论说,实际性在公式上、在时间上和在实质上都是先于潜在性的。m用这种对特殊物质(即物质和形式)的定义,试图解决众生的统一性问题,例如,"是什么使人成为一个人"?既然按照Plato的说法,有两个意念:动物和两足动物,那么,人又如何是一个统一体呢?然而,按照m的说法,潜在的存在(物质)和实际的存在(形式)是一体的。
       +
===Epistemology===
 +
认识论
   −
The order of the books (or the teachings from which they are composed) is not certain, but this list was derived from analysis of Aristotle's writings. It goes from the basics, the analysis of simple terms in the ''Categories,'' the analysis of propositions and their elementary relations in ''On Interpretation'', to the study of more complex forms, namely, syllogisms (in the ''Analytics''){{sfn| Prior Analytics | pp= 24b18–20}}{{sfn| Bobzien | 2015}} and dialectics (in the ''Topics'' and ''Sophistical Refutations''). The first three treatises form the core of the logical theory ''stricto sensu'': the grammar of the language of logic and the correct rules of reasoning. The ''Rhetoric'' is not conventionally included, but it states that it relies on the ''Topics''.{{sfn| Smith | 2017}}
+
Aristotle's immanent realism means his [[epistemology]] is based on the study of things that exist or happen in the world, and rises to knowledge of the universal, whereas for Plato epistemology begins with knowledge of universal [[Theory of Forms|Forms]] (or ideas) and descends to knowledge of particular imitations of these.{{sfn|Smith|2017}} Aristotle uses [[Inductive reasoning|induction]] from examples alongside [[Deductive reasoning|deduction]], whereas Plato relies on deduction from ''[[A priori and a posteriori|a priori]]'' principles.{{sfn|Smith|2017}}
   −
The order of the books (or the teachings from which they are composed) is not certain, but this list was derived from analysis of Aristotle's writings. It goes from the basics, the analysis of simple terms in the Categories, the analysis of propositions and their elementary relations in On Interpretation, to the study of more complex forms, namely, syllogisms (in the Analytics) and dialectics (in the Topics and Sophistical Refutations). The first three treatises form the core of the logical theory stricto sensu: the grammar of the language of logic and the correct rules of reasoning. The Rhetoric is not conventionally included, but it states that it relies on the Topics.
+
Aristotle's immanent realism means his epistemology is based on the study of things that exist or happen in the world, and rises to knowledge of the universal, whereas for Plato epistemology begins with knowledge of universal Forms (or ideas) and descends to knowledge of particular imitations of these. Aristotle uses induction from examples alongside deduction, whereas Plato relies on deduction from a priori principles.
   −
这些书的顺序(或者说它们所组成的教义)并不确定,但是这个清单是通过对亚里士多德著作的分析中得出的。它从基础知识,《范畴篇》中对简单术语的分析,《解释篇》中对命题及其基本关系的分析,到研究更复杂的形式,即三段论(在《分析篇》中)和辩证法(在《论题篇与辩谬篇》中)。前三篇论述构成了严格意义上的逻辑理论的核心: 逻辑语言的语法和正确的推理规则。《修辞学》没有按照惯例包括在内,但它指出它依赖于《论题篇》。
+
m的内在实在论意味着他的认识论是基于在对世界上存在或发生的事物的研究,并上升到对普遍性的认识,而对柏拉图来说,认识论始于对普遍形式(或思想)的认识,并下降到对这些形式的特定模仿的认识。m在演绎推理的同时也使用例证的归纳,而Plato则依赖于先验原则的演绎推理。
         −
===Metaphysics===
+
==Natural philosophy==
形而上学
+
自然哲学
   −
{{main|Metaphysics (Aristotle)}}
+
Aristotle's "natural philosophy" spans a wide range of natural phenomena including those now covered by physics, biology and other natural sciences.{{sfn| Wildberg | 2016}} In Aristotle's terminology, "natural philosophy" is a branch of philosophy examining the phenomena of the natural world, and includes fields that would be regarded today as physics, biology and other natural sciences. Aristotle's work encompassed virtually all facets of intellectual inquiry. Aristotle makes philosophy in the broad sense coextensive with reasoning, which he also would describe as "science". Note, however, that his use of the term ''science'' carries a different meaning than that covered by the term "scientific method". For Aristotle, "all science (''dianoia'') is either practical, poetical or theoretical" (''Metaphysics'' 1025b25). His practical science includes ethics and politics; his poetical science means the study of fine arts including poetry; his theoretical science covers physics, mathematics and metaphysics.{{sfn|Wildberg|2016}}
   −
The word "metaphysics" appears to have been coined by the first century AD editor who assembled various small selections of Aristotle's works to the treatise we know by the name ''Metaphysics''.{{sfn| Cohen | 2000}} Aristotle called it "first philosophy", and distinguished it from mathematics and natural science (physics) as the contemplative (''theoretikē'') philosophy which is "theological" and studies the divine. He wrote in his ''Metaphysics'' (1026a16):
+
Aristotle's "natural philosophy" spans a wide range of natural phenomena including those now covered by physics, biology and other natural sciences. In Aristotle's terminology, "natural philosophy" is a branch of philosophy examining the phenomena of the natural world, and includes fields that would be regarded today as physics, biology and other natural sciences. Aristotle's work encompassed virtually all facets of intellectual inquiry. Aristotle makes philosophy in the broad sense coextensive with reasoning, which he also would describe as "science". Note, however, that his use of the term science carries a different meaning than that covered by the term "scientific method". For Aristotle, "all science (dianoia) is either practical, poetical or theoretical" (Metaphysics 1025b25). His practical science includes ethics and politics; his poetical science means the study of fine arts including poetry; his theoretical science covers physics, mathematics and metaphysics.
   −
The word "metaphysics" appears to have been coined by the first century AD editor who assembled various small selections of Aristotle's works to the treatise we know by the name Metaphysics. Aristotle called it "first philosophy", and distinguished it from mathematics and natural science (physics) as the contemplative (theoretikē) philosophy which is "theological" and studies the divine. He wrote in his Metaphysics (1026a16):
+
m的“自然哲学”涵盖了广泛的自然现象,包括现在被物理学、生物学和其他自然科学所覆盖的自然现象。在m的术语中,“自然哲学”是哲学的一个分支,研究自然世界的现象,包括今天被认为是物理学、生物学和其他自然科学的领域。m的著作几乎涵盖了智力探究的所有方面。m使广义的哲学与推理同时延伸,他也称之为“科学”。然而,请注意,他对“科学方法”一词的使用与“科学方法”一词所涵盖的含义不同。对于m来说,“所有的科学(dianoia)要么是实践的,要么是诗意的,要么是理论的”(《形而上学》1025b25)。他的实践科学包括伦理学和政治学,他的诗学是包括诗学在内的美术学,他的理论科学包括物理学、数学和形而上学。
   −
“形而上学”一词似乎是由公元一世纪的一位广告编辑创造的,他把Aristotle的作品中的一些小片段汇编成我们所知的《形而上学》这篇论文。Aristotle称之为“第一哲学” ,并把它与数学和自然科学(物理学)区别开来,是一种沉思的(理论)哲学,即“神学”和研究神性。他在《形而上学》(1026a16)中写道:
         +
===Physics===
 +
物理
 +
[[File:Four Classical Elements in Burning Log.svg | thumb | The four [[classical element]]s (fire, air, water, earth) of [[Empedocles]] and Aristotle illustrated with a burning log. The log releases all four elements as it is destroyed.]]
   −
{{quote | if there were no other independent things besides the composite natural ones, the study of nature would be the primary kind of knowledge; but if there is some motionless independent thing, the knowledge of this precedes it and is first philosophy, and it is universal ''in just this way'', because it is first. And it belongs to this sort of philosophy to study being as being, both what it is and what belongs to it just by virtue of being.{{sfn| Aristotle | 1999 | page=111}}}}
+
The four [[classical elements (fire, air, water, earth) of Empedocles and Aristotle illustrated with a burning log. The log releases all four elements as it is destroyed.]]
   −
如果除了复合的自然事物之外,没有其他独立的事物,那么对自然的研究将是主要的一种知识;但是,如果有不动的独立的事物,那么对于这种独立的东西的认识就先于它而成为第一哲学,因此它就具有普遍性,因为它是第一的。而这种哲学,既要研究作为存在的存在,也要研究由于存在而属于存在的存在。
+
恩培多克勒Empedocles 和Aristotle的四元素(火、气、水、土)用燃烧的圆木来说明。日志在被销毁时释放所有四个元素。]
    +
{{main | Aristotelian physics}}
   −
==== Substance ====
  −
物质
     −
{{see | Hylomorphism }}
+
====Five elements====
 +
五要素
 +
{{main | Classical element}}
       +
In his ''[[On Generation and Corruption]]'', Aristotle related each of the four elements proposed earlier by [[Empedocles]], [[Earth (classical element)|Earth]], [[Water (classical element)|Water]], [[Air (classical element)|Air]], and [[Fire (classical element)|Fire]], to two of the four sensible qualities, hot, cold, wet, and dry. In the Empedoclean scheme, all matter was made of the four elements, in differing proportions. Aristotle's scheme added the heavenly [[Aether (classical element)|Aether]], the divine substance of the [[Celestial spheres|heavenly spheres]], stars and planets.{{sfn| Lloyd | 1968 | pages=133–39, 166–69}}
   −
Aristotle examines the concepts of [[Substance theory|substance]] (''ousia'') and [[essence]] (''to ti ên einai'', "the what it was to be") in his ''Metaphysics'' (Book VII), and he concludes that a particular substance is a combination of both matter and form, a philosophical theory called [[hylomorphism]]. In Book VIII, he distinguishes the matter of the substance as the [[Material substratum|substratum]], or the stuff of which it is composed. For example, the matter of a house is the bricks, stones, timbers etc., or whatever constitutes the ''potential'' house, while the form of the substance is the ''actual'' house, namely 'covering for bodies and chattels' or any other [[Genus-differentia definition|differentia]] that let us define something as a house. The formula that gives the components is the account of the matter, and the formula that gives the differentia is the account of the form.{{sfn| Metaphysics | p=VIII 1043a 10–30}}{{sfn| Cohen | 2016}}
+
In his On Generation and Corruption, Aristotle related each of the four elements proposed earlier by Empedocles, Earth, Water, Air, and Fire, to two of the four sensible qualities, hot, cold, wet, and dry. In the Empedoclean scheme, all matter was made of the four elements, in differing proportions. Aristotle's scheme added the heavenly Aether, the divine substance of the heavenly spheres, stars and planets.
   −
Aristotle examines the concepts of substance (ousia) and essence (to ti ên einai, "the what it was to be") in his Metaphysics (Book VII), and he concludes that a particular substance is a combination of both matter and form, a philosophical theory called hylomorphism. In Book VIII, he distinguishes the matter of the substance as the substratum, or the stuff of which it is composed. For example, the matter of a house is the bricks, stones, timbers etc., or whatever constitutes the potential house, while the form of the substance is the actual house, namely 'covering for bodies and chattels' or any other differentia that let us define something as a house. The formula that gives the components is the account of the matter, and the formula that gives the differentia is the account of the form.
+
在《论世代与腐败》一书中,Aristotle将Empedocles早期提出的四种元素---- 土、水、空气和火---- 中的每一种都与四种可感知的性质中的两种相联系,即热、冷、湿和干。在恩培多克林计划中,所有物质都由四种元素以不同的比例组成。亚里士多德的方案增加了天上的以太,即天上的球体、星体和行星的神圣物质。
   −
Aristotle在《形而上学》(第七卷)中研究了物质和本质的概念,他得出结论说,一种特殊的物质是物质和形式的结合体,这是一种哲学理论,称为形式质料说。在第八卷中,他将物质区分为基础,或构成物质的材料。例如,房子的物质是砖、石头、木材等,或任何构成潜在房子的物质,而实体的形式是实际的房子,即“覆盖身体和动产”或任何其他差异,让我们定义一些东西为房子。给出分量的公式是对物质的描述,给出微分的公式是对形式的描述。
         +
{| class="wikitable"
   −
===== Immanent realism =====
+
{| class="wikitable"
内在实在论
     −
[[File:Platonic and Aristotelian Forms.svg | thumb | upright=1.6 | [[Plato]]'s [[Theory of forms|forms]] exist as [[universals]], like the ideal form of an apple. For Aristotle, both matter and form belong to the individual thing ([[hylomorphism]]).]]
+
{ | class = “ wikitable”
   −
[[Plato's forms exist as universals, like the ideal form of an apple. For Aristotle, both matter and form belong to the individual thing (hylomorphism).]]
+
|+ [[Classical element|Aristotle's elements]]{{sfn|Lloyd|1968|pages=133–39, 166–69}}
   −
Plato的形式是普遍存在的,就像苹果的理想形式一样。对于Aristotle而言,物质和形式都属于单个事物(形式质料说)
+
|+ Aristotle's elements
   −
{{main|Aristotle's theory of universals}}
+
| + Aristotle的元素
   −
Like his teacher Plato, Aristotle's philosophy aims at the [[Problem of universals|universal]]. Aristotle's [[ontology]] places the universal (''katholou'') in [[particular]]s (''kath' hekaston''), things in the world, whereas for Plato the universal is a separately existing form which actual things imitate.  For Aristotle, "form" is still what [[phenomena]] are based on, but is "instantiated" in a particular substance.{{sfn| Cohen | 2016}}
+
! Element !!{{font color|red|Hot}}/{{font color|blue|Cold}} !!{{font color|green|Wet}}/{{font color|brown|Dry}} !! Motion !! Modern [[State of matter|state<br>of matter]]
   −
Like his teacher Plato, Aristotle's philosophy aims at the universal. Aristotle's ontology places the universal (katholou) in particulars (kath' hekaston), things in the world, whereas for Plato the universal is a separately existing form which actual things imitate.  For Aristotle, "form" is still what phenomena are based on, but is "instantiated" in a particular substance.
+
! Element !!/ !!/ !! Motion !! Modern state<br>of matter
   −
和他的老师Plato一样,Aristotle的哲学也着眼于普遍性。Aristotle的本体论把普遍性(天主教)至于特殊性(凯斯的希卡斯顿),即世界上的事物中,而对Plato来说,普遍性是实际事物模仿的一种单独存在的形式。对于Aristotle来说,“形式”仍然是现象的基础,但是在特定的实体中被“实例化”了。
+
!元素!热/ 冷 湿/ 干 运动 物质的现代状态
    +
|-
    +
|-
   −
Plato argued that all things have a [[Theory of forms|universal form]], which could be either a property or a relation to other things. When we look at an apple, for example, we see an apple, and we can also analyse a form of an apple. In this distinction, there is a particular apple and a universal form of an apple. Moreover, we can place an apple next to a book, so that we can speak of both the book and apple as being next to each other. Plato argued that there are some universal forms that are not a part of particular things. For example, it is possible that there is no particular good in existence, but "good" is still a proper universal form. Aristotle disagreed with Plato on this point, arguing that all universals are instantiated at some period of time, and that there are no universals that are unattached to existing things. In addition, Aristotle disagreed with Plato about the location of universals. Where Plato spoke of the world of forms, a place where all universal forms subsist, Aristotle maintained that universals exist within each thing on which each universal is predicated. So, according to Aristotle, the form of apple exists within each apple, rather than in the world of the forms.{{sfn| Cohen | 2016}}{{sfn| Lloyd | 1968 | pages=43–47}}
+
|-
   −
Plato argued that all things have a universal form, which could be either a property or a relation to other things. When we look at an apple, for example, we see an apple, and we can also analyse a form of an apple. In this distinction, there is a particular apple and a universal form of an apple. Moreover, we can place an apple next to a book, so that we can speak of both the book and apple as being next to each other. Plato argued that there are some universal forms that are not a part of particular things. For example, it is possible that there is no particular good in existence, but "good" is still a proper universal form. Aristotle disagreed with Plato on this point, arguing that all universals are instantiated at some period of time, and that there are no universals that are unattached to existing things. In addition, Aristotle disagreed with Plato about the location of universals. Where Plato spoke of the world of forms, a place where all universal forms subsist, Aristotle maintained that universals exist within each thing on which each universal is predicated. So, according to Aristotle, the form of apple exists within each apple, rather than in the world of the forms.
+
|'''[[Earth (classical element)|Earth]]'''||{{font color|blue|Cold}}||{{font color|brown|Dry}}||Down||[[Solid]]
   −
Plato认为,一切事物都有一个普遍的形式,这个形式可以是一种属性,也可以是与其他事物的关系。例如,当我们看一个苹果时,我们看到的是一个苹果,也可以分析出一个苹果的形式。在这种区分中,有一个特殊的苹果和一个苹果的普遍形式。此外,我们还可以把苹果放在一本书旁边,这样我们就可以把书和苹果都说成是相邻的。柏拉图认为,有一些普遍形式不是特定事物的一部分。例如,有可能没有特定的善存在,但 "善 "仍然是一种恰当的普遍形式。Aristotle在这一点上不同意柏拉图的观点,认为所有的普遍性都是在某个时期被实例化的,不存在不依附于现存事物的普遍性。此外,m在普遍性的位置问题上也与柏拉图意见相左。Plato所说的形式世界,是所有普遍形式都存在的地方,而m则认为,普遍性存在于每个普遍性所依托的每个事物之中。所以,根据m的观点,苹果的形式存在于每个苹果之内,而不是存在于形式世界之中。
+
|Earth|Cold|Dry||Down||Solid
    +
地球 冷 干燥 向下 固体
    +
|-
   −
===== Potentiality and actuality =====
+
|-
潜力和现实
     −
{{see | Potentiality and actuality (Aristotle)}}
+
|-
    +
|'''[[Water (classical element)|Water]]'''||{{font color|blue|Cold}}||{{font color|green|Wet}}||Down||[[Liquid]]
    +
|Water|Cold|Wet||Down||Liquid
   −
With regard to the change (''[[Potentiality and actuality|kinesis]]'') and its causes now, as he defines in his ''[[Physics (Aristotle)|Physics]]'' and ''[[On Generation and Corruption]]'' 319b–320a, he distinguishes the coming to be from:
+
水 冷 湿 向下 液体
   −
With regard to the change (kinesis) and its causes now, as he defines in his Physics and On Generation and Corruption 319b–320a, he distinguishes the coming to be from:
+
|-
   −
关于现在的变化(运动)及其原因,正如他在《物理学》和《论生成与腐败》319b-320a 中所定义的那样,他将变化的来源区分为:
+
|-
    +
|-
    +
|'''[[Air (classical element)|Air]]'''||{{font color|red|Hot}}||{{font color|green|Wet}}||Up||[[Gas]]
   −
# growth and diminution, which is change in quantity;
+
|Air|Hot|Wet||Up||Gas
   −
growth and diminution, which is change in quantity;
+
空气 热 湿 向上 气体
   −
增长和减少,即数量的变化;
+
|-
   −
# locomotion, which is change in space; and
+
|-
   −
locomotion, which is change in space; and
+
|-
   −
运动,即空间的变化; 以及
+
|'''[[Fire (classical element)|Fire]]'''||{{font color|red|Hot}}||{{font color|brown|Dry}}||Up||[[Plasma (physics)|Plasma]]
   −
# alteration, which is change in quality.
+
|Fire|Hot|Dry||Up||Plasma
   −
alteration, which is change in quality.
+
火 热 干燥 向上 等离子体
   −
改变,也就是质量的改变。
+
|-
    +
|-
    +
|-
   −
[[File:Flute-player dolphin Alcesti Group MAN.jpg | thumb | Aristotle argued that a capability like playing the flute could be acquired – [[Potentiality and actuality (Aristotle)|the potential made actual]] – by learning.]]
+
|'''[[Aether (classical element)|Aether]]'''||(divine<br>substance)||—||Circular<br>(in heavens)||—
   −
Flute-player dolphin Alcesti Group MAN.jpg | thumb | Aristotle argued that a capability like playing the flute could be acquired – Potentiality and actuality (Aristotle)|the potential made actual
+
|Aether||(divine<br>substance)||—||Circular<br>(in heavens)||—
   −
m认为,通过学习可以获得像吹长笛这样的能力-使潜力得以实现。
+
| 以太 | | (神圣的物质) | | | ー | | 圆形的 < br > (在天堂) | | | ー
    +
|}
    +
|}
   −
The coming to be is a change where nothing persists of which the resultant is a property. In that particular change he introduces the concept of potentiality (''[[Dunamis|dynamis]]'') and actuality (''[[entelecheia]]'') in association with the matter and the form. Referring to potentiality, this is what a thing is capable of doing, or being acted upon, if the conditions are right and it is not prevented by something else. For example, the seed of a plant in the soil is potentially (''dynamei'') plant, and if it is not prevented by something, it will become a plant. Potentially beings can either 'act' (''poiein'') or 'be acted upon' (''paschein''), which can be either innate or learned. For example, the eyes possess the potentiality of sight (innate – being acted upon), while the capability of playing the flute can be possessed by learning (exercise – acting). Actuality is the fulfilment of the end of the potentiality. Because the end (''telos'') is the principle of every change, and for the sake of the end exists potentiality, therefore actuality is the end. Referring then to our previous example, we could say that an actuality is when a plant does one of the activities that plants do.{{sfn| Cohen | 2016}}
+
|}
   −
The coming to be is a change where nothing persists of which the resultant is a property. In that particular change he introduces the concept of potentiality (dynamis) and actuality (entelecheia) in association with the matter and the form. Referring to potentiality, this is what a thing is capable of doing, or being acted upon, if the conditions are right and it is not prevented by something else. For example, the seed of a plant in the soil is potentially (dynamei) plant, and if it is not prevented by something, it will become a plant. Potentially beings can either 'act' (poiein) or 'be acted upon' (paschein), which can be either innate or learned. For example, the eyes possess the potentiality of sight (innate – being acted upon), while the capability of playing the flute can be possessed by learning (exercise – acting). Actuality is the fulfilment of the end of the potentiality. Because the end (telos) is the principle of every change, and for the sake of the end exists potentiality, therefore actuality is the end. Referring then to our previous example, we could say that an actuality is when a plant does one of the activities that plants do.
     −
形成是一种变化,其中没有任何东西持续存在,其结果是一种属性。在这种特殊的变化中,他引入了与物质和形式相相关的潜在性(动力)和现实性(真实性)的概念。所谓潜在性,是指一个事物在条件合适且不受其他事物阻碍的情况下,能够做什么或被什么所影响。例如,土壤中植物的种子是潜在的(dynamei )植物,如果不受某种东西的阻止,它就会成为植物。潜在的生命可以 "行动"(poiein)或 "被行动"(paschein),这可以是天生的,也可以是后天的。例如,眼睛具有视觉潜能(先天行为) ,而长笛演奏能力可以通过学习(练习作用)来实现。实际性是潜能最终的实现。因为目的是一切变化的原则,而为了目的而存在着潜能,所以现实性就是目的。那么,参照我们前面的例子,我们可以说,实际性是指植物做了植物所做的活动之一。
      +
====Motion====
 +
运动
   −
{{quote | For that for the sake of which (''to hou heneka'') a thing is, is its principle, and the becoming is for the sake of the end; and the actuality is the end, and it is for the sake of this that the potentiality is acquired. For animals do not see in order that they may have sight, but they have sight that they may see.{{sfn| Metaphysics | p=IX 1050a 5–10}}}}
+
{{see | History of classical mechanics}}
   −
事物的存在,就是它的原则,成为就是它的目的;现实性就是目的,为了达到目的,才能获得潜在性。因为动物看东西不是为了它们有视力,而是它们有视力才会看。
      +
Aristotle describes two kinds of motion: "violent" or "unnatural motion", such as that of a thrown stone, in the ''Physics'' (254b10), and "natural motion", such as of a falling object, in ''On the Heavens'' (300a20). In violent motion, as soon as the agent stops causing it, the motion stops also; in other words, the natural state of an object is to be at rest,{{sfn| Allain | 2016}}{{efn-ua | Rhett Allain notes that [[Newton's First Law]] is "essentially a direct reply to Aristotle, that the natural state is ''not to change'' motion.{{sfn| Allain | 2016}}}} since Aristotle does not address [[friction]].{{sfn| Drabkin | 1938 | pp=60–84}} With this understanding, it can be observed that, as Aristotle stated, heavy objects (on the ground, say) require more force to make them move; and objects pushed with greater force move faster.{{sfn| Susskind | 2011}}{{efn-ua | Leonard Susskind comments that Aristotle had clearly never gone [[ice skating]] or he would have seen that it takes force to stop an object.{{sfn| Susskind | 2011}}}} This would imply the equation{{sfn| Susskind | 2011}}
   −
In summary, the matter used to make a house has potentiality to be a house and both the activity of building and the form of the final house are actualities, which is also a [[final cause]] or end. Then Aristotle proceeds and concludes that the actuality is prior to potentiality in formula, in time and in substantiality. With this definition of the particular substance (i.e., matter and form), Aristotle tries to solve the problem of the unity of the beings, for example, "what is it that makes a man one"? Since, according to [[Plato]] there are two Ideas: animal and biped, how then is man a unity? However, according to Aristotle, the potential being (matter) and the actual one (form) are one and the same.{{sfn| Cohen | 2016}}{{sfn| Metaphysics | p=VIII 1045a–b}}
+
Aristotle describes two kinds of motion: "violent" or "unnatural motion", such as that of a thrown stone, in the Physics (254b10), and "natural motion", such as of a falling object, in On the Heavens (300a20). In violent motion, as soon as the agent stops causing it, the motion stops also; in other words, the natural state of an object is to be at rest,}} since Aristotle does not address friction. With this understanding, it can be observed that, as Aristotle stated, heavy objects (on the ground, say) require more force to make them move; and objects pushed with greater force move faster.}} This would imply the equation
   −
In summary, the matter used to make a house has potentiality to be a house and both the activity of building and the form of the final house are actualities, which is also a final cause or end. Then Aristotle proceeds and concludes that the actuality is prior to potentiality in formula, in time and in substantiality. With this definition of the particular substance (i.e., matter and form), Aristotle tries to solve the problem of the unity of the beings, for example, "what is it that makes a man one"? Since, according to Plato there are two Ideas: animal and biped, how then is man a unity? However, according to Aristotle, the potential being (matter) and the actual one (form) are one and the same.
+
Aristotle描述了两种运动。"剧烈运动 "或 "非自然运动",如《物理学》(254b10)中的抛石运动,以及 "自然运动",如《论天》(300a20)中的坠物运动。在剧烈运动中,只要媒介停止引起运动,运动也就停止了,换句话说,物体的自然状态是静止的,因为Aristotle没有提到摩擦。有了这种理解,就可以观察到,正如Aristotle所说的,重的物体(比如在地上)需要更多的力来使它们移动;受到更大力推动的物体移动得更快。这就意味着这个方程这就意味着这个方程式
   −
综上所述,用来造房子的物质具有成为房子的可能性,而建造房子的活动和最后房子的形式都是实际性,这也是最后的原因或目的。接着,m又得出结论说,实际性在公式上、在时间上和在实质上都是先于潜在性的。m用这种对特殊物质(即物质和形式)的定义,试图解决众生的统一性问题,例如,"是什么使人成为一个人"?既然按照Plato的说法,有两个意念:动物和两足动物,那么,人又如何是一个统一体呢?然而,按照m的说法,潜在的存在(物质)和实际的存在(形式)是一体的。
        −
===Epistemology===
+
:: <math>F=mv</math>,
认识论
     −
Aristotle's immanent realism means his [[epistemology]] is based on the study of things that exist or happen in the world, and rises to knowledge of the universal, whereas for Plato epistemology begins with knowledge of universal [[Theory of Forms|Forms]] (or ideas) and descends to knowledge of particular imitations of these.{{sfn|Smith|2017}} Aristotle uses [[Inductive reasoning|induction]] from examples alongside [[Deductive reasoning|deduction]], whereas Plato relies on deduction from ''[[A priori and a posteriori|a priori]]'' principles.{{sfn|Smith|2017}}
+
<math>F=mv</math>,
   −
Aristotle's immanent realism means his epistemology is based on the study of things that exist or happen in the world, and rises to knowledge of the universal, whereas for Plato epistemology begins with knowledge of universal Forms (or ideas) and descends to knowledge of particular imitations of these. Aristotle uses induction from examples alongside deduction, whereas Plato relies on deduction from a priori principles.
     −
m的内在实在论意味着他的认识论是基于在对世界上存在或发生的事物的研究,并上升到对普遍性的认识,而对柏拉图来说,认识论始于对普遍形式(或思想)的认识,并下降到对这些形式的特定模仿的认识。m在演绎推理的同时也使用例证的归纳,而Plato则依赖于先验原则的演绎推理。
           −
==Natural philosophy==
+
incorrect in modern physics.{{sfn| Susskind | 2011}}
自然哲学
     −
Aristotle's "natural philosophy" spans a wide range of natural phenomena including those now covered by physics, biology and other natural sciences.{{sfn| Wildberg | 2016}} In Aristotle's terminology, "natural philosophy" is a branch of philosophy examining the phenomena of the natural world, and includes fields that would be regarded today as physics, biology and other natural sciences. Aristotle's work encompassed virtually all facets of intellectual inquiry. Aristotle makes philosophy in the broad sense coextensive with reasoning, which he also would describe as "science". Note, however, that his use of the term ''science'' carries a different meaning than that covered by the term "scientific method". For Aristotle, "all science (''dianoia'') is either practical, poetical or theoretical" (''Metaphysics'' 1025b25). His practical science includes ethics and politics; his poetical science means the study of fine arts including poetry; his theoretical science covers physics, mathematics and metaphysics.{{sfn|Wildberg|2016}}
+
incorrect in modern physics.
   −
Aristotle's "natural philosophy" spans a wide range of natural phenomena including those now covered by physics, biology and other natural sciences. In Aristotle's terminology, "natural philosophy" is a branch of philosophy examining the phenomena of the natural world, and includes fields that would be regarded today as physics, biology and other natural sciences. Aristotle's work encompassed virtually all facets of intellectual inquiry. Aristotle makes philosophy in the broad sense coextensive with reasoning, which he also would describe as "science". Note, however, that his use of the term science carries a different meaning than that covered by the term "scientific method". For Aristotle, "all science (dianoia) is either practical, poetical or theoretical" (Metaphysics 1025b25). His practical science includes ethics and politics; his poetical science means the study of fine arts including poetry; his theoretical science covers physics, mathematics and metaphysics.
+
在现代物理学中是错误的。
   −
m的“自然哲学”涵盖了广泛的自然现象,包括现在被物理学、生物学和其他自然科学所覆盖的自然现象。在m的术语中,“自然哲学”是哲学的一个分支,研究自然世界的现象,包括今天被认为是物理学、生物学和其他自然科学的领域。m的著作几乎涵盖了智力探究的所有方面。m使广义的哲学与推理同时延伸,他也称之为“科学”。然而,请注意,他对“科学方法”一词的使用与“科学方法”一词所涵盖的含义不同。对于m来说,“所有的科学(dianoia)要么是实践的,要么是诗意的,要么是理论的”(《形而上学》1025b25)。他的实践科学包括伦理学和政治学,他的诗学是包括诗学在内的美术学,他的理论科学包括物理学、数学和形而上学。
         +
Natural motion depends on the element concerned: the aether naturally moves in a circle around the heavens,{{efn-ua | For heavenly bodies like the Sun, Moon, and stars, the observed motions are "to a very good approximation" circular around the Earth's centre, (for example, the apparent rotation of the sky because of the rotation of the Earth, and the rotation of the moon around the Earth) as Aristotle stated.{{sfn| Rovelli | 2015 | pp=23–40}}}} while the 4 Empedoclean elements move vertically up (like fire, as is observed) or down (like earth) towards their natural resting places.{{sfn| Rovelli | 2015 | pp=23–40}}{{sfn| Drabkin | 1938 | pp=60–84}}{{efn-ua | Drabkin quotes numerous passages from ''Physics'' and ''On the Heavens'' (''De Caelo'') which state Aristotle's laws of motion.{{sfn| Drabkin | 1938 | pp=60–84}}}}
   −
===Physics===
+
Natural motion depends on the element concerned: the aether naturally moves in a circle around the heavens,}} while the 4 Empedoclean elements move vertically up (like fire, as is observed) or down (like earth) towards their natural resting places.
物理
  −
[[File:Four Classical Elements in Burning Log.svg | thumb | The four [[classical element]]s (fire, air, water, earth) of [[Empedocles]] and Aristotle illustrated with a burning log. The log releases all four elements as it is destroyed.]]
     −
The four [[classical elements (fire, air, water, earth) of Empedocles and Aristotle illustrated with a burning log. The log releases all four elements as it is destroyed.]]
+
自然运动取决于有关的元素:以太自然地绕天而行,而四种空净元素则垂直向上(如火,如观察到的)或向下(如土)向它们的自然静止处移动。
   −
恩培多克勒Empedocles 和Aristotle的四元素(火、气、水、土)用燃烧的圆木来说明。日志在被销毁时释放所有四个元素。]
     −
{{main | Aristotelian physics}}
+
[[File:Aristotle's laws of motion.svg | thumb | upright=1.5 | Aristotle's laws of motion. In ''[[Physics (Aristotle)|Physics]]'' he states that objects fall at a speed proportional to their weight and inversely proportional to the density of the fluid they are immersed in.{{sfn| Drabkin | 1938 | pp=60–84}} This is a correct approximation for objects in Earth's gravitational field moving in air or water.{{sfn| Rovelli | 2015 | pp=23–40}}]]
    +
Aristotle's laws of motion. In Physics he states that objects fall at a speed proportional to their weight and inversely proportional to the density of the fluid they are immersed in. This is a correct approximation for objects in Earth's gravitational field moving in air or water.]]
   −
====Five elements====
+
Aristotle的运动定律。在物理学中,他指出,物体坠落的速度与它们的重量成正比,与它们所浸泡的液体的密度成反比。这对于地球引力场中在空气或水中运动的物体来说,是一个正确的近似值。
五要素
  −
{{main | Classical element}}
        −
In his ''[[On Generation and Corruption]]'', Aristotle related each of the four elements proposed earlier by [[Empedocles]], [[Earth (classical element)|Earth]], [[Water (classical element)|Water]], [[Air (classical element)|Air]], and [[Fire (classical element)|Fire]], to two of the four sensible qualities, hot, cold, wet, and dry. In the Empedoclean scheme, all matter was made of the four elements, in differing proportions. Aristotle's scheme added the heavenly [[Aether (classical element)|Aether]], the divine substance of the [[Celestial spheres|heavenly spheres]], stars and planets.{{sfn| Lloyd | 1968 | pages=133–39, 166–69}}
     −
In his On Generation and Corruption, Aristotle related each of the four elements proposed earlier by Empedocles, Earth, Water, Air, and Fire, to two of the four sensible qualities, hot, cold, wet, and dry. In the Empedoclean scheme, all matter was made of the four elements, in differing proportions. Aristotle's scheme added the heavenly Aether, the divine substance of the heavenly spheres, stars and planets.
+
In the ''Physics'' (215a25), Aristotle effectively states a quantitative law, that the speed, v, of a falling body is proportional (say, with constant c) to its weight, W, and inversely proportional to the density,{{efn-ua | Drabkin agrees that density is treated quantitatively in this passage, but without a sharp definition of density as weight per unit volume.{{sfn| Drabkin | 1938 | pp=60–84}}}} ρ, of the fluid in which it is falling:{{sfn| Rovelli | 2015 | pp=23–40}}{{sfn| Drabkin | 1938 | pp=60–84}}
   −
在《论世代与腐败》一书中,Aristotle将Empedocles早期提出的四种元素---- 土、水、空气和火---- 中的每一种都与四种可感知的性质中的两种相联系,即热、冷、湿和干。在恩培多克林计划中,所有物质都由四种元素以不同的比例组成。亚里士多德的方案增加了天上的以太,即天上的球体、星体和行星的神圣物质。
+
In the Physics (215a25), Aristotle effectively states a quantitative law, that the speed, v, of a falling body is proportional (say, with constant c) to its weight, W, and inversely proportional to the density,}} ρ, of the fluid in which it is falling:
    +
在《物理学》(215a25)中,Aristotle有效地阐述了一个定量定律,即下落物体的速度v与物体的重量W成正比(即c不变),与下落物体所在液体的密度成反比:
      −
{| class="wikitable"
     −
{| class="wikitable"
+
:: <math>v=c\frac{W}{\rho}</math>
   −
{ | class = “ wikitable”
+
<math>v=c\frac{W}{\rho}</math>
   −
|+ [[Classical element|Aristotle's elements]]{{sfn|Lloyd|1968|pages=133–39, 166–69}}
+
[ math > v = c frac { w }{ rho } </math >
   −
|+ Aristotle's elements
     −
| + Aristotle的元素
     −
! Element !!{{font color|red|Hot}}/{{font color|blue|Cold}} !!{{font color|green|Wet}}/{{font color|brown|Dry}} !! Motion !! Modern [[State of matter|state<br>of matter]]
+
Aristotle implies that in a [[vacuum]] the speed of fall would become infinite, and concludes from this apparent absurdity that a vacuum is not possible.{{sfn| Rovelli | 2015 | pp=23–40}}{{sfn| Drabkin | 1938 | pp=60–84}} Opinions have varied on whether Aristotle intended to state quantitative laws. Henri Carteron held the "extreme view"{{sfn| Drabkin | 1938 | pp=60–84}} that Aristotle's concept of force was basically qualitative,{{sfn| Carteron | 1923 | pages=1–32 and passim}} but other authors reject this.{{sfn| Drabkin | 1938 | pp=60–84}}
   −
! Element !!/ !!/ !! Motion !! Modern state<br>of matter
+
Aristotle implies that in a vacuum the speed of fall would become infinite, and concludes from this apparent absurdity that a vacuum is not possible. Opinions have varied on whether Aristotle intended to state quantitative laws. Henri Carteron held the "extreme view" that Aristotle's concept of force was basically qualitative, but other authors reject this.
   −
!元素!热/ 冷 湿/ 干 运动 物质的现代状态
+
Aristotle暗示,在真空中下落的速度将是无限的,并从这个明显的荒谬得出结论,真空是不可能的。对于Aristotle是否有意阐述数量法则,人们的意见不一。亨利·卡特隆(Henri Carteron)持“极端观点”,认为Aristotle的力概念基本上是定性的,但其他作者反对这种观点。
   −
|-
     −
|-
     −
|-
+
[[Archimedes]] corrected Aristotle's theory that bodies move towards their natural resting places; metal boats can float if they [[Archimedes' principle|displace enough water]]; floating depends in Archimedes' scheme on the mass and volume of the object, not as Aristotle thought its elementary composition.{{sfn| Rovelli | 2015 | pp=23–40}}
   −
|'''[[Earth (classical element)|Earth]]'''||{{font color|blue|Cold}}||{{font color|brown|Dry}}||Down||[[Solid]]
+
Archimedes corrected Aristotle's theory that bodies move towards their natural resting places; metal boats can float if they displace enough water; floating depends in Archimedes' scheme on the mass and volume of the object, not as Aristotle thought its elementary composition.
   −
|Earth|Cold|Dry||Down||Solid
+
阿基米德Archimedes纠正了Aristotle的理论,即物体会朝着它们自然休息的地方移动; 金属船只如果置换了足够多的水就能浮起来; 在Archimedes的理论中,浮力取决于物体的质量和体积,而不是Aristotle认为的物体的基本构成。
   −
地球 冷 干燥 向下 固体
     −
|-
     −
|-
+
Aristotle's writings on motion remained influential until the [[Early Modern]] period. [[John Philoponus]] (in the [[Middle Ages]]) and [[Galileo Galilei|Galileo]] are said to have shown by experiment that Aristotle's claim that a heavier object falls faster than a lighter object is incorrect.{{sfn| Wildberg | 2016}} A contrary opinion is given by [[Carlo Rovelli]], who argues that Aristotle's physics of motion is correct within its domain of validity, that of objects in the [[Earth]]'s gravitational field immersed in a fluid such as air. In this system, heavy bodies in steady fall indeed travel faster than light ones (whether friction is ignored, or not{{sfn| Rovelli | 2015 | pp=23–40}}), and they do fall more slowly in a denser medium.{{sfn| Susskind | 2011}}{{efn-ua | Philoponus and Galileo correctly objected that for the transient phase (still increasing in speed) with heavy objects falling a short distance, the law does not apply: Galileo used balls on a short incline to show this. Rovelli notes that "Two heavy balls with the same shape and different weight do fall at different speeds from an aeroplane, confirming Aristotle's theory, not Galileo's."{{sfn| Rovelli | 2015 | pp=23–40}}}}
   −
|-
+
Aristotle's writings on motion remained influential until the Early Modern period. John Philoponus (in the Middle Ages) and Galileo are said to have shown by experiment that Aristotle's claim that a heavier object falls faster than a lighter object is incorrect. A contrary opinion is given by Carlo Rovelli, who argues that Aristotle's physics of motion is correct within its domain of validity, that of objects in the Earth's gravitational field immersed in a fluid such as air. In this system, heavy bodies in steady fall indeed travel faster than light ones (whether friction is ignored, or not), and they do fall more slowly in a denser medium.
   −
|'''[[Water (classical element)|Water]]'''||{{font color|blue|Cold}}||{{font color|green|Wet}}||Down||[[Liquid]]
+
Aristotle关于运动的著作直到近代早期仍有影响。据说约翰•菲洛波努斯John Philoponus(中世纪)和伽利略Galileo通过实验表明,Aristotle关于较重的物体比较轻的物体下落得快的说法是不正确的。卡罗.罗维利Carlo Rovelli给出了相反的意见,他认为Aristotle的运动物理学在其有效领域内是正确的,即在地球引力场中浸泡在空气等流体中的物体。在这一体系中,处于稳定下落的重体确实比轻体走得快(无论是否忽略摩擦力),而且在密度较大的介质中,重体下落的速度确实较慢。
   −
|Water|Cold|Wet||Down||Liquid
     −
水 冷 湿 向下 液体
     −
|-
+
Newton's "forced" motion corresponds to Aristotle's "violent" motion with its external agent, but Aristotle's assumption that the agent's effect stops immediately it stops acting (e.g., the ball leaves the thrower's hand) has awkward consequences: he has to suppose that surrounding fluid helps to push the ball along to make it continue to rise even though the hand is no longer acting on it, resulting in the Medieval [[theory of impetus]].{{sfn| Rovelli | 2015 | pp=23–40}}
   −
|-
+
Newton's "forced" motion corresponds to Aristotle's "violent" motion with its external agent, but Aristotle's assumption that the agent's effect stops immediately it stops acting (e.g., the ball leaves the thrower's hand) has awkward consequences: he has to suppose that surrounding fluid helps to push the ball along to make it continue to rise even though the hand is no longer acting on it, resulting in the Medieval theory of impetus.
   −
|-
+
牛顿Newton的“被迫”运动相当于亚里士多德的“暴力”运动及其外部因素,但Aristotle的假设,该因素的影响立即停止(例如,球离开投掷者的手),这就产生了尴尬的后果: 他必须假设周围的液体帮助推动球前进,使球继续上升,即使手不再作用于球,也会产生中世纪的推动力理论。
   −
|'''[[Air (classical element)|Air]]'''||{{font color|red|Hot}}||{{font color|green|Wet}}||Up||[[Gas]]
     −
|Air|Hot|Wet||Up||Gas
     −
空气 热 湿 向上 气体
+
====Four causes====
 +
四个原因
   −
|-
+
{{main | Four causes}}
   −
|-
+
[[File:Aristotle's Four Causes of a Table.svg | thumb | upright=1.6 | Aristotle argued by analogy with woodwork that a thing takes its form from [[four causes]]: in the case of a table, the wood used ([[material cause]]), its design ([[formal cause]]), the tools and techniques used ([[efficient cause]]), and its decorative or practical purpose ([[final cause]]).{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=88–90}}]]
   −
|-
+
Aristotle argued by analogy with woodwork that a thing takes its form from [[four causes: in the case of a table, the wood used (material cause), its design (formal cause), the tools and techniques used (efficient cause), and its decorative or practical purpose (final cause).
   −
|'''[[Fire (classical element)|Fire]]'''||{{font color|red|Hot}}||{{font color|brown|Dry}}||Up||[[Plasma (physics)|Plasma]]
+
Aristotle通过与木制品的类比论证了一个事物的形式有四个原因:以桌子为例,使用的木材(材料原因),它的设计(形式原因),使用的工具和技术(有效原因),以及它的装饰或实用目的(最终原因)。
   −
|Fire|Hot|Dry||Up||Plasma
     −
火 热 干燥 向上 等离子体
     −
|-
+
Aristotle suggested that the reason for anything coming about can be attributed to four different types of simultaneously active factors. His term ''aitia'' is traditionally translated as "cause", but it does not always refer to temporal sequence; it might be better translated as "explanation", but the traditional rendering will be employed here.{{sfn| Lloyd | 1996 | pages=96–100, 106–07}}{{sfn| Hankinson | 1998 | page=159}}
   −
|-
+
Aristotle suggested that the reason for anything coming about can be attributed to four different types of simultaneously active factors. His term aitia is traditionally translated as "cause", but it does not always refer to temporal sequence; it might be better translated as "explanation", but the traditional rendering will be employed here.
   −
|-
+
Aristotle认为,任何事情发生的原因,都可以归因于同时存在的四种不同类型的积极因素。他的术语aitia传统上被翻译为“原因”,但它并不总是指时间序列;将它翻译成“解释”可能更好,但这里将采用传统的呈现方式。
   −
|'''[[Aether (classical element)|Aether]]'''||(divine<br>substance)||—||Circular<br>(in heavens)||
+
* [[Material cause]] describes the material out of which something is composed. Thus the material cause of a table is wood. It is not about action. It does not mean that one domino knocks over another domino.{{sfn| Lloyd | 1996 | pages=96–100, 106–07}}
   −
|Aether||(divine<br>substance)||—||Circular<br>(in heavens)||—
+
物质原因描述的是组成某物的物质。因此,制作桌子的材料是木头。这不是行动的问题。这并不意味着一张多米诺骨牌会击倒另一张。
   −
| 以太 | | (神圣的物质) | | | ー | | 圆形的 < br > (在天堂) | | |
+
* The [[formal cause]] is its form, i.e., the arrangement of that matter. It tells us what a thing is, that a thing is determined by the definition, form, pattern, essence, whole, synthesis or archetype. It embraces the account of causes in terms of fundamental principles or general laws, as the whole (i.e., macrostructure) is the cause of its parts, a relationship known as the whole-part causation. Plainly put, the formal cause is the idea in the mind of the sculptor that brings the sculpture into being. A simple example of the formal cause is the mental image or idea that allows an artist, architect, or engineer to create a drawing.{{sfn| Lloyd | 1996 | pages=96–100, 106–07}}
   −
|}
+
形式上的原因是它的形式,即该事物的安排。它告诉我们一个事物是什么,一个事物是由定义、形式、模式、本质、整体、综合或原型决定的。它包含了用基本原理或一般规律来说明原因,因为整体(即宏观结构)是其部分的原因,这种关系称为整体-部分因果关系。通俗地说,形式原因就是雕塑家头脑中的想法,使雕塑作品得以产生。形式因的一个简单的例子,就是让艺术家、建筑师或工程师创造出图纸的心理意象或想法。
   −
|}
+
* The [[efficient cause]] is "the primary source", or that from which the change under consideration proceeds. It identifies 'what makes of what is made and what causes change of what is changed' and so suggests all sorts of agents, nonliving or living, acting as the sources of change or movement or rest. Representing the current understanding of causality as the relation of cause and effect, this covers the modern definitions of "cause" as either the agent or agency or particular events or states of affairs. In the case of two dominoes, when the first is knocked over it causes the second also to fall over. In the case of animals, this agency is a combination of how it develops from the egg, and how its body functions.{{sfn| Lloyd | 1996 | pages=96–100, 106–07}} In the case of animals, this agency is a combination of [[developmental biology|how it develops from the egg]], and [[physiology|how its body functions]].{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=91–92, 369–73}}
   −
|}
+
有效原因是 "主要来源",或者说,所考虑的变化是从这里开始的。它确定了 "是什么造就了什么,是什么引起了被改变的东西的变化",因此暗示了各种代理人,无论是非生物的还是生物的,都是变化或运动或休息的来源。代表目前对因果关系的理解是因果关系,这涵盖了现代对 "原因 "的定义,要么是代理人或机构,要么是特定的事件或事态。在两个多米诺骨牌的情况下,当第一个骨牌被撞倒时,会导致第二个骨牌也倒下。就动物而言,该机构是鸡蛋如何发育以及其身体功能的综合体。
    +
* The [[final cause]] (''telos'') is its purpose, the reason why a thing exists or is done, including both purposeful and instrumental actions and activities. The final cause is the purpose or function that something is supposed to serve. This covers modern ideas of motivating causes, such as volition.{{sfn| Lloyd | 1996 | pages=96–100, 106–07}} In the case of living things, it implies [[adaptation]] to a particular way of life. In the case of living things, it implies adaptation to a particular way of life.{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=91–92, 369–73}}
    +
最终的原因(''telos'')是其目的,是一件事情存在或被做的原因,包括目的性和工具性的行为和活动。最后的原因是指某一事物所要达到的目的或功能。这涵盖了现代动机原因的概念,如意志。就生物而言,它意味着适应一种特定的生活方式。
   −
====Motion====
+
====Optics====
运动
+
光学
   −
{{see | History of classical mechanics}}
+
{{further | History of optics}}
    +
Aristotle describes experiments in [[optics]] using a [[camera obscura]] in ''[[Problems (Aristotle)|Problems]]'', book 15. The apparatus consisted of a dark chamber with a small [[aperture]] that let light in. With it, he saw that whatever shape he made the hole, the sun's image always remained circular. He also noted that increasing the distance between the aperture and the image surface magnified the image.{{sfn| Lahanas}}
   −
Aristotle describes two kinds of motion: "violent" or "unnatural motion", such as that of a thrown stone, in the ''Physics'' (254b10), and "natural motion", such as of a falling object, in ''On the Heavens'' (300a20). In violent motion, as soon as the agent stops causing it, the motion stops also; in other words, the natural state of an object is to be at rest,{{sfn| Allain | 2016}}{{efn-ua | Rhett Allain notes that [[Newton's First Law]] is "essentially a direct reply to Aristotle, that the natural state is ''not to change'' motion.{{sfn| Allain | 2016}}}} since Aristotle does not address [[friction]].{{sfn| Drabkin | 1938 | pp=60–84}} With this understanding, it can be observed that, as Aristotle stated, heavy objects (on the ground, say) require more force to make them move; and objects pushed with greater force move faster.{{sfn| Susskind | 2011}}{{efn-ua | Leonard Susskind comments that Aristotle had clearly never gone [[ice skating]] or he would have seen that it takes force to stop an object.{{sfn| Susskind | 2011}}}} This would imply the equation{{sfn| Susskind | 2011}}
+
Aristotle describes experiments in optics using a camera obscura in Problems, book 15. The apparatus consisted of a dark chamber with a small aperture that let light in. With it, he saw that whatever shape he made the hole, the sun's image always remained circular. He also noted that increasing the distance between the aperture and the image surface magnified the image.
   −
Aristotle describes two kinds of motion: "violent" or "unnatural motion", such as that of a thrown stone, in the Physics (254b10), and "natural motion", such as of a falling object, in On the Heavens (300a20). In violent motion, as soon as the agent stops causing it, the motion stops also; in other words, the natural state of an object is to be at rest,}} since Aristotle does not address friction. With this understanding, it can be observed that, as Aristotle stated, heavy objects (on the ground, say) require more force to make them move; and objects pushed with greater force move faster.}} This would imply the equation
+
Aristotle在《问题》第15卷中描述了使用照相机暗箱进行光学实验的情况。该仪器由一个暗室组成,暗室有一个小孔,可以让光线进入。用它,他看到无论他把孔做成什么形状,太阳的图像总是保持圆形。他还注意到,增加光圈与图像表面之间的距离,可以放大图像。
   −
Aristotle描述了两种运动。"剧烈运动 "或 "非自然运动",如《物理学》(254b10)中的抛石运动,以及 "自然运动",如《论天》(300a20)中的坠物运动。在剧烈运动中,只要媒介停止引起运动,运动也就停止了,换句话说,物体的自然状态是静止的,因为Aristotle没有提到摩擦。有了这种理解,就可以观察到,正如Aristotle所说的,重的物体(比如在地上)需要更多的力来使它们移动;受到更大力推动的物体移动得更快。这就意味着这个方程这就意味着这个方程式
         +
====Chance and spontaneity====
 +
机会与自发性
   −
:: <math>F=mv</math>,
+
{{further | Accident (philosophy)}}
   −
<math>F=mv</math>,
+
According to Aristotle, spontaneity and chance are causes of some things, distinguishable from other types of cause such as simple necessity. Chance as an incidental cause lies in the realm of [[Accident (philosophy)|accidental things]], "from what is spontaneous". There is also more a specific kind of chance, which Aristotle names "luck", that only applies to people's moral choices.{{sfn| Physics | p=2.6}}{{sfn| Miller | 1973 | pp=204–13}}
    +
According to Aristotle, spontaneity and chance are causes of some things, distinguishable from other types of cause such as simple necessity. Chance as an incidental cause lies in the realm of accidental things, "from what is spontaneous". There is also more a specific kind of chance, which Aristotle names "luck", that only applies to people's moral choices.
    +
根据Aristotle的观点,自发性和偶然性是某些事物的原因,区别于其他类型的原因,如简单的必然性。偶然作为一种偶然的原因,存在于偶然事物的领域,即“来自于自发的东西”。还有一种特定的机会,Aristotle称之为“运气”,它只适用于人们的道德选择。
         −
incorrect in modern physics.{{sfn| Susskind | 2011}}
+
===Astronomy===
 +
天文学
 +
{{further | History of astronomy}}
   −
incorrect in modern physics.
     −
在现代物理学中是错误的。
      +
In [[astronomy]], Aristotle refuted [[Democritus]]'s claim that the [[Milky Way]] was made up of "those stars which are shaded by the earth from the sun's rays," pointing out correctly that if "the size of the sun is greater than that of the earth and the distance of the stars from the earth many times greater than that of the sun, then... the sun shines on all the stars and the earth screens none of them."{{sfn| Meteorology | p=1. 8}}
    +
In astronomy, Aristotle refuted Democritus's claim that the Milky Way was made up of "those stars which are shaded by the earth from the sun's rays," pointing out correctly that if "the size of the sun is greater than that of the earth and the distance of the stars from the earth many times greater than that of the sun, then... the sun shines on all the stars and the earth screens none of them."
   −
Natural motion depends on the element concerned: the aether naturally moves in a circle around the heavens,{{efn-ua | For heavenly bodies like the Sun, Moon, and stars, the observed motions are "to a very good approximation" circular around the Earth's centre, (for example, the apparent rotation of the sky because of the rotation of the Earth, and the rotation of the moon around the Earth) as Aristotle stated.{{sfn| Rovelli | 2015 | pp=23–40}}}} while the 4 Empedoclean elements move vertically up (like fire, as is observed) or down (like earth) towards their natural resting places.{{sfn| Rovelli | 2015 | pp=23–40}}{{sfn| Drabkin | 1938 | pp=60–84}}{{efn-ua | Drabkin quotes numerous passages from ''Physics'' and ''On the Heavens'' (''De Caelo'') which state Aristotle's laws of motion.{{sfn| Drabkin | 1938 | pp=60–84}}}}
+
在天文学上,Aristotle驳斥了德谟克利特Democritus关于银河系是由 "那些被地球遮挡住太阳光线的恒星 "组成的说法,正确地指出,如果 "太阳的大小大于地球的大小,恒星与地球的距离比太阳的距离大许多倍,那么......太阳照耀着所有的恒星,而地球却没有屏蔽任何一颗恒星"。
   −
Natural motion depends on the element concerned: the aether naturally moves in a circle around the heavens,}} while the 4 Empedoclean elements move vertically up (like fire, as is observed) or down (like earth) towards their natural resting places.
     −
自然运动取决于有关的元素:以太自然地绕天而行,而四种空净元素则垂直向上(如火,如观察到的)或向下(如土)向它们的自然静止处移动。
      +
[[File:DenglerSW-Stromboli-20040928-1230x800.jpg | thumb | Aristotle noted that the ground level of the [[Aeolian islands]] changed before a [[volcanic eruption]].]]
   −
[[File:Aristotle's laws of motion.svg | thumb | upright=1.5 | Aristotle's laws of motion. In ''[[Physics (Aristotle)|Physics]]'' he states that objects fall at a speed proportional to their weight and inversely proportional to the density of the fluid they are immersed in.{{sfn| Drabkin | 1938 | pp=60–84}} This is a correct approximation for objects in Earth's gravitational field moving in air or water.{{sfn| Rovelli | 2015 | pp=23–40}}]]
+
Aristotle noted that the ground level of the [[Aeolian islands changed before a volcanic eruption.
   −
Aristotle's laws of motion. In Physics he states that objects fall at a speed proportional to their weight and inversely proportional to the density of the fluid they are immersed in. This is a correct approximation for objects in Earth's gravitational field moving in air or water.]]
+
Aristotle指出,在火山爆发之前,伊奥利亚群岛的地面就发生了变化。
   −
Aristotle的运动定律。在物理学中,他指出,物体坠落的速度与它们的重量成正比,与它们所浸泡的液体的密度成反比。这对于地球引力场中在空气或水中运动的物体来说,是一个正确的近似值。
         +
===Geology===
 +
地质学
 +
{{further | History of geology}}
   −
In the ''Physics'' (215a25), Aristotle effectively states a quantitative law, that the speed, v, of a falling body is proportional (say, with constant c) to its weight, W, and inversely proportional to the density,{{efn-ua | Drabkin agrees that density is treated quantitatively in this passage, but without a sharp definition of density as weight per unit volume.{{sfn| Drabkin | 1938 | pp=60–84}}}} ρ, of the fluid in which it is falling:{{sfn| Rovelli | 2015 | pp=23–40}}{{sfn| Drabkin | 1938 | pp=60–84}}
     −
In the Physics (215a25), Aristotle effectively states a quantitative law, that the speed, v, of a falling body is proportional (say, with constant c) to its weight, W, and inversely proportional to the density,}} ρ, of the fluid in which it is falling:
     −
在《物理学》(215a25)中,Aristotle有效地阐述了一个定量定律,即下落物体的速度v与物体的重量W成正比(即c不变),与下落物体所在液体的密度成反比:
+
Aristotle was one of the first people to record any [[geology|geological]] observations. He stated that [[Uniformitarianism|geological change]] was too slow to be observed in one person's lifetime.{{sfn| Moore | 1956 | page=13}}{{sfn| Meteorology | p=Book 1, Part 14}}
    +
Aristotle was one of the first people to record any geological observations. He stated that geological change was too slow to be observed in one person's lifetime.
    +
Aristotle是最早记录地质观测数据的人之一。他说,地质变化太慢,在一个人的一生中无法观察到。
   −
:: <math>v=c\frac{W}{\rho}</math>
+
The geologist [[Charles Lyell]] noted that Aristotle described such change, including "lakes that had dried up" and "deserts that had become watered by rivers", giving as examples the growth of the [[Nile delta]] since the time of [[Homer]], and "the upheaving of one of the [[Aeolian islands]], previous to a [[volcanic eruption]]."'{{sfn| Lyell | 1832 | page=17}}
   −
<math>v=c\frac{W}{\rho}</math>
+
The geologist Charles Lyell noted that Aristotle described such change, including "lakes that had dried up" and "deserts that had become watered by rivers", giving as examples the growth of the Nile delta since the time of Homer, and "the upheaving of one of the Aeolian islands, previous to a volcanic eruption."'
   −
[ math > v = c frac { w }{ rho } </math >
+
地质学家查尔斯•莱尔Charles Lyell指出,Aristotle描述了这种变化,包括 "已经干涸的湖泊 "和 "被河流浇灌的沙漠",他举例说,自荷马时代以来,尼罗河三角洲的增长,以及 "伊奥利亚群岛中的一个岛屿在火山喷发颠覆"。
       +
===Biology===
 +
生物学
 +
{{main | Aristotle's biology}}
   −
Aristotle implies that in a [[vacuum]] the speed of fall would become infinite, and concludes from this apparent absurdity that a vacuum is not possible.{{sfn| Rovelli | 2015 | pp=23–40}}{{sfn| Drabkin | 1938 | pp=60–84}} Opinions have varied on whether Aristotle intended to state quantitative laws. Henri Carteron held the "extreme view"{{sfn| Drabkin | 1938 | pp=60–84}} that Aristotle's concept of force was basically qualitative,{{sfn| Carteron | 1923 | pages=1–32 and passim}} but other authors reject this.{{sfn| Drabkin | 1938 | pp=60–84}}
+
[[File:Tremoctopus violaceus5.jpg | thumb | upright | Among many pioneering zoological observations, Aristotle described the reproductive [[hectocotylus|hectocotyl arm]] of the [[octopus]] (bottom left).]]
   −
Aristotle implies that in a vacuum the speed of fall would become infinite, and concludes from this apparent absurdity that a vacuum is not possible. Opinions have varied on whether Aristotle intended to state quantitative laws. Henri Carteron held the "extreme view" that Aristotle's concept of force was basically qualitative, but other authors reject this.
+
在许多开拓性的动物学观察中,Aristotle描述了章鱼的生殖臂(左下)。
   −
Aristotle暗示,在真空中下落的速度将是无限的,并从这个明显的荒谬得出结论,真空是不可能的。对于Aristotle是否有意阐述数量法则,人们的意见不一。亨利·卡特隆(Henri Carteron)持“极端观点”,认为Aristotle的力概念基本上是定性的,但其他作者反对这种观点。
         +
====Empirical research====
 +
实证研究
 +
Aristotle was the first person to study biology systematically,{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | page=7}} and biology forms a large part of his writings. He spent two years observing and describing the zoology of [[Lesbos]] and the surrounding seas, including in particular the Pyrrha lagoon in the centre of Lesbos.{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | page=14}}{{sfn| Thompson | 1910 | page=Prefatory Note}} His data in ''[[History of Animals]]'', ''[[Generation of Animals]]'', ''[[Movement of Animals]]'', and ''[[Parts of Animals]]'' are assembled from his own observations,<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.independent.co.uk/arts-entertainment/books/reviews/darwins-ghosts-by-rebecca-stott-7808310.html|title=Darwin's Ghosts, By Rebecca Stott
   −
[[Archimedes]] corrected Aristotle's theory that bodies move towards their natural resting places; metal boats can float if they [[Archimedes' principle|displace enough water]]; floating depends in Archimedes' scheme on the mass and volume of the object, not as Aristotle thought its elementary composition.{{sfn| Rovelli | 2015 | pp=23–40}}
+
|website=independent.co.uk|date=2 June 2012
   −
Archimedes corrected Aristotle's theory that bodies move towards their natural resting places; metal boats can float if they displace enough water; floating depends in Archimedes' scheme on the mass and volume of the object, not as Aristotle thought its elementary composition.
+
|access-date=19 June 2012}}</ref> statements given by people with specialized knowledge such as beekeepers and fishermen, and less accurate accounts provided by travellers from overseas.{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=196, 248}} His apparent emphasis on animals rather than plants is a historical accident: his works on [[botany]] have been lost, but two books on plants by his pupil Theophrastus have survived.{{sfn| Day | 2013 | pp=5805–16}}
   −
阿基米德Archimedes纠正了Aristotle的理论,即物体会朝着它们自然休息的地方移动; 金属船只如果置换了足够多的水就能浮起来; 在Archimedes的理论中,浮力取决于物体的质量和体积,而不是Aristotle认为的物体的基本构成。
+
Aristotle was the first person to study biology systematically, and biology forms a large part of his writings. He spent two years observing and describing the zoology of Lesbos and the surrounding seas, including in particular the Pyrrha lagoon in the centre of Lesbos. His data in History of Animals, Generation of Animals, Movement of Animals, and Parts of Animals are assembled from his own observations, statements given by people with specialized knowledge such as beekeepers and fishermen, and less accurate accounts provided by travellers from overseas. His apparent emphasis on animals rather than plants is a historical accident: his works on botany have been lost, but two books on plants by his pupil Theophrastus have survived.
    +
Aristotle是第一个系统研究生物学的人,生物学构成了他著作的很大一部分。他花了两年时间观察和描述莱斯博斯岛及周围海域的动物学,尤其是包括莱斯伯斯岛的皮尔哈泻湖。他在《动物的历史》、《动物的生成》、《动物的运动》和《动物的部分》中的数据是根据他自己的观察、养蜂人和渔民等具有专业知识的人的陈述以及海外旅行者提供的不太准确的描述汇集而成。他显然强调动物而不是植物,这是一个历史的偶然:他的植物学著作已经遗失,但他的学生提Theophrastus的两本植物学著作却留了下来。
    +
Aristotle reports on the sea-life visible from observation on Lesbos and the catches of fishermen. He describes the [[catfish]], [[electric ray]], and [[frogfish]] in detail, as well as [[cephalopod]]s such as the [[octopus]] and [[paper nautilus]]. His description of the [[hectocotylus|hectocotyl arm]] of cephalopods, used in sexual reproduction, was widely disbelieved until the 19th century.{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=66–74, 137}} He gives accurate descriptions of the four-chambered fore-stomachs of [[ruminant]]s,{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=118–19}} and of the [[Ovoviviparity|ovoviviparous]] embryological development of the [[hound shark]].{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | page=73}}
   −
Aristotle's writings on motion remained influential until the [[Early Modern]] period. [[John Philoponus]] (in the [[Middle Ages]]) and [[Galileo Galilei|Galileo]] are said to have shown by experiment that Aristotle's claim that a heavier object falls faster than a lighter object is incorrect.{{sfn| Wildberg | 2016}} A contrary opinion is given by [[Carlo Rovelli]], who argues that Aristotle's physics of motion is correct within its domain of validity, that of objects in the [[Earth]]'s gravitational field immersed in a fluid such as air. In this system, heavy bodies in steady fall indeed travel faster than light ones (whether friction is ignored, or not{{sfn| Rovelli | 2015 | pp=23–40}}), and they do fall more slowly in a denser medium.{{sfn| Susskind | 2011}}{{efn-ua | Philoponus and Galileo correctly objected that for the transient phase (still increasing in speed) with heavy objects falling a short distance, the law does not apply: Galileo used balls on a short incline to show this. Rovelli notes that "Two heavy balls with the same shape and different weight do fall at different speeds from an aeroplane, confirming Aristotle's theory, not Galileo's."{{sfn| Rovelli | 2015 | pp=23–40}}}}
+
Aristotle reports on the sea-life visible from observation on Lesbos and the catches of fishermen. He describes the catfish, electric ray, and frogfish in detail, as well as cephalopods such as the octopus and paper nautilus. His description of the hectocotyl arm of cephalopods, used in sexual reproduction, was widely disbelieved until the 19th century. He gives accurate descriptions of the four-chambered fore-stomachs of ruminants, and of the ovoviviparous embryological development of the hound shark.
   −
Aristotle's writings on motion remained influential until the Early Modern period. John Philoponus (in the Middle Ages) and Galileo are said to have shown by experiment that Aristotle's claim that a heavier object falls faster than a lighter object is incorrect. A contrary opinion is given by Carlo Rovelli, who argues that Aristotle's physics of motion is correct within its domain of validity, that of objects in the Earth's gravitational field immersed in a fluid such as air. In this system, heavy bodies in steady fall indeed travel faster than light ones (whether friction is ignored, or not), and they do fall more slowly in a denser medium.
+
Aristotle通过对莱斯博斯岛的观察和渔民的捕获来描述海洋生物。他详细描述了鲶鱼、电鳐和蛙鱼,以及章鱼和纸鹦鹉螺等头足类动物。直到19世纪,人们才广泛相信他所描述的头足类动物中的交接腕。他对反刍动物的四腔前胃和猎鲨的卵生胚胎发育作了准确的描述。
   −
Aristotle关于运动的著作直到近代早期仍有影响。据说约翰•菲洛波努斯John Philoponus(中世纪)和伽利略Galileo通过实验表明,Aristotle关于较重的物体比较轻的物体下落得快的说法是不正确的。卡罗.罗维利Carlo Rovelli给出了相反的意见,他认为Aristotle的运动物理学在其有效领域内是正确的,即在地球引力场中浸泡在空气等流体中的物体。在这一体系中,处于稳定下落的重体确实比轻体走得快(无论是否忽略摩擦力),而且在密度较大的介质中,重体下落的速度确实较慢。
      +
He notes that an animal's structure is well matched to function, so, among birds, the [[heron]], which lives in marshes with soft mud and lives by catching fish, has a long neck and long legs, and a sharp spear-like beak, whereas [[duck]]s that swim have short legs and webbed feet.{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=135–36}} [[Charles Darwin|Darwin]], too, noted these sorts of differences between similar kinds of animal, but unlike Aristotle used the data to come to the theory of [[evolution]].{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | page=206}} Aristotle's writings can seem to modern readers close to implying evolution, but while Aristotle was aware that new mutations or [[Hybridisation (biology)|hybridizations]] could occur, he saw these as rare accidents. For Aristotle, accidents, like heat waves in winter, must be considered distinct from natural causes. He was thus critical of Empedocles's materialist theory of a "survival of the fittest" origin of living things and their organs, and ridiculed the idea that accidents could lead to orderly results.{{sfn| Sedley | 2007 | page=189}} To put his views into modern terms, he nowhere says that different species can have a [[common descent|common ancestor]], or that one kind can [[speciation|change into another]], or that kinds can become [[extinction|extinct]].{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | page=273}}
    +
He notes that an animal's structure is well matched to function, so, among birds, the heron, which lives in marshes with soft mud and lives by catching fish, has a long neck and long legs, and a sharp spear-like beak, whereas ducks that swim have short legs and webbed feet. Darwin, too, noted these sorts of differences between similar kinds of animal, but unlike Aristotle used the data to come to the theory of evolution. Aristotle's writings can seem to modern readers close to implying evolution, but while Aristotle was aware that new mutations or hybridizations could occur, he saw these as rare accidents. For Aristotle, accidents, like heat waves in winter, must be considered distinct from natural causes. He was thus critical of Empedocles's materialist theory of a "survival of the fittest" origin of living things and their organs, and ridiculed the idea that accidents could lead to orderly results. To put his views into modern terms, he nowhere says that different species can have a common ancestor, or that one kind can change into another, or that kinds can become extinct.
   −
Newton's "forced" motion corresponds to Aristotle's "violent" motion with its external agent, but Aristotle's assumption that the agent's effect stops immediately it stops acting (e.g., the ball leaves the thrower's hand) has awkward consequences: he has to suppose that surrounding fluid helps to push the ball along to make it continue to rise even though the hand is no longer acting on it, resulting in the Medieval [[theory of impetus]].{{sfn| Rovelli | 2015 | pp=23–40}}
+
他指出,动物的结构与功能是相匹配的,因此,在鸟类中,栖息在泥沼中以捕鱼为生的苍鹭有长长的脖子和长腿,还有像矛一样锋利的喙,而游泳的鸭子有短腿和蹼足。达尔文也注意到了类似动物之间的这些差异,但与Aristotle不同的是,他利用这些数据得出了进化论。对现代读者来说,Aristotle的著作似乎暗示了进化论,但当Aristotle意识到可能会发生新的突变或杂交时,他把这些看作是罕见的意外。对亚里士多德来说,对Aristotle来说,意外就像冬天的热浪一样,必须区别于自然原因来考虑。因此,他对Empedocles关于生物及其器官 "适者生存 "起源的唯物主义理论持批判态度,并嘲笑了意外事故可以导致有序结果的观点。用现代的术语来说,他没有说过不同的物种可以有一个共同的祖先,也没有说过一种物种可以变为另一种物种,也没有说过物种可以灭绝。
   −
Newton's "forced" motion corresponds to Aristotle's "violent" motion with its external agent, but Aristotle's assumption that the agent's effect stops immediately it stops acting (e.g., the ball leaves the thrower's hand) has awkward consequences: he has to suppose that surrounding fluid helps to push the ball along to make it continue to rise even though the hand is no longer acting on it, resulting in the Medieval theory of impetus.
     −
牛顿Newton的“被迫”运动相当于亚里士多德的“暴力”运动及其外部因素,但Aristotle的假设,该因素的影响立即停止(例如,球离开投掷者的手),这就产生了尴尬的后果: 他必须假设周围的液体帮助推动球前进,使球继续上升,即使手不再作用于球,也会产生中世纪的推动力理论。
+
====Scientific style====
 +
科学风格
 +
[[File:Two of Aristotle's Growth Laws.svg | thumb | left | upright=1.4 | Aristotle inferred growth laws from his observations on animals, including that [[brood size]] decreases with body mass, whereas [[gestation]] period increases. He was correct in these predictions, at least for mammals: data are shown for mouse and elephant.]]
    +
Aristotle从他对动物的观察中推断出生长规律,包括卵数随着体重的增加而减少,而妊娠期却在增加。他的这些预测是正确的,至少对哺乳动物来说是这样:有数据显示了老鼠和大象的情况。
    +
Aristotle did not do experiments in the modern sense.{{sfn| Taylor | 1922 | page=42}} He used the ancient Greek term ''pepeiramenoi'' to mean observations, or at most investigative procedures like dissection.{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=361–65}} In ''Generation of Animals'', he finds a fertilized hen's egg of a suitable stage and opens it to see the embryo's heart beating inside.{{sfn| Leroi | 2011}}{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=197–200}}
   −
====Four causes====
+
Aristotle did not do experiments in the modern sense. He used the ancient Greek term pepeiramenoi to mean observations, or at most investigative procedures like dissection. In Generation of Animals, he finds a fertilized hen's egg of a suitable stage and opens it to see the embryo's heart beating inside.
四个原因
     −
{{main | Four causes}}
+
Aristotle没有做现代意义上的实验。他使用古希腊术语pepeiramenoi来表示观察,或者至多表示像解剖这样的研究过程。在动物繁殖过程中,他找到一个处于合适阶段的受精卵,打开它看里面胚胎的心脏跳动。
   −
[[File:Aristotle's Four Causes of a Table.svg | thumb | upright=1.6 | Aristotle argued by analogy with woodwork that a thing takes its form from [[four causes]]: in the case of a table, the wood used ([[material cause]]), its design ([[formal cause]]), the tools and techniques used ([[efficient cause]]), and its decorative or practical purpose ([[final cause]]).{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=88–90}}]]
+
Instead, he practiced a different style of science: systematically gathering data, discovering patterns common to whole groups of animals, and inferring possible causal explanations from these.{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=365–68}}{{sfn| Taylor | 1922 | page=49}} This style is common in modern biology when large amounts of data become available in a new field, such as [[genomics]]. It does not result in the same certainty as experimental science, but it sets out testable hypotheses and constructs a narrative explanation of what is observed. In this sense, Aristotle's biology is scientific.{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=365–68}}
   −
Aristotle argued by analogy with woodwork that a thing takes its form from [[four causes: in the case of a table, the wood used (material cause), its design (formal cause), the tools and techniques used (efficient cause), and its decorative or practical purpose (final cause).
+
Instead, he practiced a different style of science: systematically gathering data, discovering patterns common to whole groups of animals, and inferring possible causal explanations from these. This style is common in modern biology when large amounts of data become available in a new field, such as genomics. It does not result in the same certainty as experimental science, but it sets out testable hypotheses and constructs a narrative explanation of what is observed. In this sense, Aristotle's biology is scientific.
   −
Aristotle通过与木制品的类比论证了一个事物的形式有四个原因:以桌子为例,使用的木材(材料原因),它的设计(形式原因),使用的工具和技术(有效原因),以及它的装饰或实用目的(最终原因)。
+
相反,他实践了一种不同的科学风格:系统地收集数据,发现整个动物群体的共同模式,并从中推断出可能的因果解释。这种风格在现代生物学中很常见,当在一个新的领域(如基因组学)中出现大量数据时,就会出现这种风格。它的结果并不像实验科学那样具有确定性,但它提出了可检验的假说,并对观察到的东西构建了一种叙述性的解释。在这个意义上,Aristotle的生物学是科学的。
       +
From the data he collected and documented, Aristotle inferred quite a number of [[biological rules|rules]] relating the life-history features of the live-bearing tetrapods (terrestrial placental mammals) that he studied. Among these correct predictions are the following. Brood size decreases with (adult) body mass, so that an elephant has fewer young (usually just one) per brood than a mouse. [[Life expectancy|Lifespan]] increases with [[gestation period]], and also with body mass, so that elephants live longer than mice, have a longer period of gestation, and are heavier. As a final example, [[fecundity]] decreases with lifespan, so long-lived kinds like elephants have fewer young in total than short-lived kinds like mice.{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | page=408}}{{-}}
   −
Aristotle suggested that the reason for anything coming about can be attributed to four different types of simultaneously active factors. His term ''aitia'' is traditionally translated as "cause", but it does not always refer to temporal sequence; it might be better translated as "explanation", but the traditional rendering will be employed here.{{sfn| Lloyd | 1996 | pages=96–100, 106–07}}{{sfn| Hankinson | 1998 | page=159}}
+
From the data he collected and documented, Aristotle inferred quite a number of rules relating the life-history features of the live-bearing tetrapods (terrestrial placental mammals) that he studied. Among these correct predictions are the following. Brood size decreases with (adult) body mass, so that an elephant has fewer young (usually just one) per brood than a mouse. Lifespan increases with gestation period, and also with body mass, so that elephants live longer than mice, have a longer period of gestation, and are heavier. As a final example, fecundity decreases with lifespan, so long-lived kinds like elephants have fewer young in total than short-lived kinds like mice.
   −
Aristotle suggested that the reason for anything coming about can be attributed to four different types of simultaneously active factors. His term aitia is traditionally translated as "cause", but it does not always refer to temporal sequence; it might be better translated as "explanation", but the traditional rendering will be employed here.
+
从他收集和记录的数据中,Aristotle推断出许多他所研究的四足动物(陆生胎盘哺乳动物)生活史特征的规律。以下是正确的预测。幼体大小随着(成年)体重的增加而减少,因此大象每窝产下的幼体(通常只有一个)比老鼠少。寿命随着妊娠期和体重的增加而延长,因此大象比老鼠活得更长,妊娠期更长,体重也更重。最后一个例子是,繁殖力随着寿命的延长而减少,所以像大象这样的长寿种类的幼崽总数要少于像老鼠这样的短寿种类。
   −
Aristotle认为,任何事情发生的原因,都可以归因于同时存在的四种不同类型的积极因素。他的术语aitia传统上被翻译为“原因”,但它并不总是指时间序列;将它翻译成“解释”可能更好,但这里将采用传统的呈现方式。
+
====Classification of living things====
 +
生物分类
 +
{{further | Scala naturae}}
   −
* [[Material cause]] describes the material out of which something is composed. Thus the material cause of a table is wood. It is not about action. It does not mean that one domino knocks over another domino.{{sfn| Lloyd | 1996 | pages=96–100, 106–07}}
+
[[File:Scyliorhinus retifer embryo.JPG | thumb | Aristotle recorded that the [[embryo]] of [[Mustelus canis|<!--a different species shown-->a dogfish]] was attached by a cord to a kind of placenta (the [[yolk sac]]), like a higher animal; this formed an exception to the linear scale from highest to lowest.{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=72–74}}]]
   −
物质原因描述的是组成某物的物质。因此,制作桌子的材料是木头。这不是行动的问题。这并不意味着一张多米诺骨牌会击倒另一张。
+
Aristotle recorded that the [[embryo of <!--a different species shown-->a dogfish was attached by a cord to a kind of placenta (the yolk sac), like a higher animal; this formed an exception to the linear scale from highest to lowest.]]
   −
* The [[formal cause]] is its form, i.e., the arrangement of that matter. It tells us what a thing is, that a thing is determined by the definition, form, pattern, essence, whole, synthesis or archetype. It embraces the account of causes in terms of fundamental principles or general laws, as the whole (i.e., macrostructure) is the cause of its parts, a relationship known as the whole-part causation. Plainly put, the formal cause is the idea in the mind of the sculptor that brings the sculpture into being. A simple example of the formal cause is the mental image or idea that allows an artist, architect, or engineer to create a drawing.{{sfn| Lloyd | 1996 | pages=96–100, 106–07}}
+
Aristotle记载,角鲨的胚胎像高等动物一样,由一根绳索系在一种胎盘(卵黄囊)上;这形成了一个从最高到最低的线性尺度的例外。
   −
形式上的原因是它的形式,即该事物的安排。它告诉我们一个事物是什么,一个事物是由定义、形式、模式、本质、整体、综合或原型决定的。它包含了用基本原理或一般规律来说明原因,因为整体(即宏观结构)是其部分的原因,这种关系称为整体-部分因果关系。通俗地说,形式原因就是雕塑家头脑中的想法,使雕塑作品得以产生。形式因的一个简单的例子,就是让艺术家、建筑师或工程师创造出图纸的心理意象或想法。
+
Aristotle distinguished about 500 species of [[animal]]s,{{sfn| Bergstrom | Dugatkin | 2012 | page=35}}{{sfn| Rhodes | 1974 | page=7}} arranging these in the ''History of Animals'' in a graded scale of perfection, a ''[[scala naturae]]'', with man at the top. His system had eleven grades of animal, from highest potential to lowest, expressed in their form at birth: the highest gave [[viviparity|live birth]] to hot and wet creatures, the lowest laid cold, dry mineral-like eggs. Animals came above [[plant]]s, and these in turn were above minerals.{{sfn| Mayr | 1982 | pages=201–02}} see also:{{sfn| Lovejoy | 1976}} He grouped what the modern zoologist would call [[vertebrate]]s as the hotter "animals with blood", and below them the colder [[invertebrate]]s as "animals without blood". Those with blood were divided into the live-bearing ([[mammal]]s), and the egg-laying ([[bird]]s, [[reptile]]s, [[fish]]). Those without blood were insects, crustacea (non-shelled – cephalopods, and [[crustacea|shelled]]) and the hard-shelled [[mollusc]]s ([[bivalve]]s and [[gastropod]]s). He recognised that animals did not exactly fit into a linear scale, and noted various exceptions, such as that sharks had a [[placenta]] like the tetrapods. To a modern biologist, the explanation, not available to Aristotle,<!--Leroi | p= 113--> is [[convergent evolution]].{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=111–19}} He believed that purposive final causes guided all natural processes; this [[teleological]] view justified his observed data as an expression of formal design.{{sfn| Mason | 1979 | pp=43–44}}
   −
* The [[efficient cause]] is "the primary source", or that from which the change under consideration proceeds. It identifies 'what makes of what is made and what causes change of what is changed' and so suggests all sorts of agents, nonliving or living, acting as the sources of change or movement or rest. Representing the current understanding of causality as the relation of cause and effect, this covers the modern definitions of "cause" as either the agent or agency or particular events or states of affairs. In the case of two dominoes, when the first is knocked over it causes the second also to fall over. In the case of animals, this agency is a combination of how it develops from the egg, and how its body functions.{{sfn| Lloyd | 1996 | pages=96–100, 106–07}} In the case of animals, this agency is a combination of [[developmental biology|how it develops from the egg]], and [[physiology|how its body functions]].{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=91–92, 369–73}}
+
Aristotle distinguished about 500 species of animals, arranging these in the History of Animals in a graded scale of perfection, a scala naturae, with man at the top. His system had eleven grades of animal, from highest potential to lowest, expressed in their form at birth: the highest gave live birth to hot and wet creatures, the lowest laid cold, dry mineral-like eggs. Animals came above plants, and these in turn were above minerals. see also: He grouped what the modern zoologist would call vertebrates as the hotter "animals with blood", and below them the colder invertebrates as "animals without blood". Those with blood were divided into the live-bearing (mammals), and the egg-laying (birds, reptiles, fish). Those without blood were insects, crustacea (non-shelled – cephalopods, and shelled) and the hard-shelled molluscs (bivalves and gastropods). He recognised that animals did not exactly fit into a linear scale, and noted various exceptions, such as that sharks had a placenta like the tetrapods. To a modern biologist, the explanation, not available to Aristotle,<!--Leroi | p= 113--> is convergent evolution. He believed that purposive final causes guided all natural processes; this teleological view justified his observed data as an expression of formal design.
   −
有效原因是 "主要来源",或者说,所考虑的变化是从这里开始的。它确定了 "是什么造就了什么,是什么引起了被改变的东西的变化",因此暗示了各种代理人,无论是非生物的还是生物的,都是变化或运动或休息的来源。代表目前对因果关系的理解是因果关系,这涵盖了现代对 "原因 "的定义,要么是代理人或机构,要么是特定的事件或事态。在两个多米诺骨牌的情况下,当第一个骨牌被撞倒时,会导致第二个骨牌也倒下。就动物而言,该机构是鸡蛋如何发育以及其身体功能的综合体。
+
Aristotle区分了大约500种动物,在动物发展史上按照完美程度(即自然等级)对它们进行排列,其中人处于最顶端。他的系统将动物分为11个等级,从潜能最高的到潜能最低的,以出生时的形式表现出来:潜能最高的能生下湿热的生物,而潜能最低的能生下冰冷、干燥的类似矿物的蛋。动物在植物之上,植物又在矿物之上。另见:他将现代动物学家称之为脊椎动物的动物归类为温度较高的“带血的动物”,而温度较低的无脊椎动物则归类为“无血的动物”。那些有血液的动物被分为胎生动物(哺乳动物)和卵生动物(鸟类、爬行动物、鱼类)。那些没有血液的是昆虫、甲壳类(无壳的头足类和有壳的)和硬壳软体动物(双壳类和腹足类)。他认识到动物并不完全符合线性比例,并指出了各种例外情况,比如鲨鱼和四足动物一样有胎盘。对现代生物学家来说,亚里士多德无法解释的解释是趋同进化。他相信有目的的最终原因引导着所有的自然过程;这种目的论的观点证明他观察到的数据是形式设计的一种表现。
   −
* The [[final cause]] (''telos'') is its purpose, the reason why a thing exists or is done, including both purposeful and instrumental actions and activities. The final cause is the purpose or function that something is supposed to serve. This covers modern ideas of motivating causes, such as volition.{{sfn| Lloyd | 1996 | pages=96–100, 106–07}} In the case of living things, it implies [[adaptation]] to a particular way of life. In the case of living things, it implies adaptation to a particular way of life.{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=91–92, 369–73}}
+
{| class="wikitable" style="font-size: 80%;"
   −
最终的原因(''telos'')是其目的,是一件事情存在或被做的原因,包括目的性和工具性的行为和活动。最后的原因是指某一事物所要达到的目的或功能。这涵盖了现代动机原因的概念,如意志。就生物而言,它意味着适应一种特定的生活方式。
+
{ | class = “ wikitable” style = “ font-size: 80% ; ”
   −
====Optics====
  −
光学
     −
{{further | History of optics}}
     −
Aristotle describes experiments in [[optics]] using a [[camera obscura]] in ''[[Problems (Aristotle)|Problems]]'', book 15. The apparatus consisted of a dark chamber with a small [[aperture]] that let light in. With it, he saw that whatever shape he made the hole, the sun's image always remained circular. He also noted that increasing the distance between the aperture and the image surface magnified the image.{{sfn| Lahanas}}
+
|+ Aristotle's Scala naturae (highest to lowest)
   −
Aristotle describes experiments in optics using a camera obscura in Problems, book 15. The apparatus consisted of a dark chamber with a small aperture that let light in. With it, he saw that whatever shape he made the hole, the sun's image always remained circular. He also noted that increasing the distance between the aperture and the image surface magnified the image.
+
| + Aristotle的斯卡拉自然史(最高到最低)
   −
Aristotle在《问题》第15卷中描述了使用照相机暗箱进行光学实验的情况。该仪器由一个暗室组成,暗室有一个小孔,可以让光线进入。用它,他看到无论他把孔做成什么形状,太阳的图像总是保持圆形。他还注意到,增加光圈与图像表面之间的距离,可以放大图像。
+
{| class="wikitable" style="font-size: 80%;"
    +
! Group !! Examples<br>(given by Aristotle) !! Blood !! Legs !! Souls<br>(Rational,<br>Sensitive,<br>Vegetative) !! Qualities<br>(–,<br>–)
    +
!组! !示例 < br > (由亚里士多德给出) ! !血液! !腿部! !灵魂(理性,敏感,植物性) ! !品质 < br > (热-冷 ,< br >湿 -干)
   −
====Chance and spontaneity====
+
|+ Aristotle's ''[[Scala naturae]]'' (highest to lowest)
机会与自发性
     −
{{further | Accident (philosophy)}}
+
|-
   −
According to Aristotle, spontaneity and chance are causes of some things, distinguishable from other types of cause such as simple necessity. Chance as an incidental cause lies in the realm of [[Accident (philosophy)|accidental things]], "from what is spontaneous". There is also more a specific kind of chance, which Aristotle names "luck", that only applies to people's moral choices.{{sfn| Physics | p=2.6}}{{sfn| Miller | 1973 | pp=204–13}}
+
|-
   −
According to Aristotle, spontaneity and chance are causes of some things, distinguishable from other types of cause such as simple necessity. Chance as an incidental cause lies in the realm of accidental things, "from what is spontaneous". There is also more a specific kind of chance, which Aristotle names "luck", that only applies to people's moral choices.
+
! Group !! Examples<br>(given by Aristotle) !! Blood !! Legs !! Souls<br>(Rational,<br>Sensitive,<br>Vegetative) !! Qualities<br>({{font color|red|Hot}}–{{font color|blue|Cold}},<br>{{font color|green|Wet}}–{{font color|brown|Dry}})
   −
根据Aristotle的观点,自发性和偶然性是某些事物的原因,区别于其他类型的原因,如简单的必然性。偶然作为一种偶然的原因,存在于偶然事物的领域,即“来自于自发的东西”。还有一种特定的机会,Aristotle称之为“运气”,它只适用于人们的道德选择。
+
|Man||Man||with&nbsp;blood||2 legs||R, S, V||,
    +
人 人 带血 2条腿 R,S,V 热,湿
    +
|-
   −
===Astronomy===
+
|-
天文学
  −
{{further | History of astronomy}}
      +
|-
    +
|Man||Man||with&nbsp;blood||2 legs||R, S, V||{{font color|red|Hot}}, {{font color|green|Wet}}
   −
In [[astronomy]], Aristotle refuted [[Democritus]]'s claim that the [[Milky Way]] was made up of "those stars which are shaded by the earth from the sun's rays," pointing out correctly that if "the size of the sun is greater than that of the earth and the distance of the stars from the earth many times greater than that of the sun, then... the sun shines on all the stars and the earth screens none of them."{{sfn| Meteorology | p=1. 8}}
+
|Live-bearing tetrapods||Cat, hare||with&nbsp;blood||4 legs||S, V||,
   −
In astronomy, Aristotle refuted Democritus's claim that the Milky Way was made up of "those stars which are shaded by the earth from the sun's rays," pointing out correctly that if "the size of the sun is greater than that of the earth and the distance of the stars from the earth many times greater than that of the sun, then... the sun shines on all the stars and the earth screens none of them."
+
四足动物 猫,野兔 带血 4条腿 S,V 热,湿
 +
|-
   −
在天文学上,Aristotle驳斥了德谟克利特Democritus关于银河系是由 "那些被地球遮挡住太阳光线的恒星 "组成的说法,正确地指出,如果 "太阳的大小大于地球的大小,恒星与地球的距离比太阳的距离大许多倍,那么......太阳照耀着所有的恒星,而地球却没有屏蔽任何一颗恒星"。
+
|-
    +
|-
    +
|[[Mammal|Live-bearing tetrapods]]||Cat, [[hare]]||with&nbsp;blood||4 legs||S, V||{{font color|red|Hot}}, {{font color|green|Wet}}
   −
[[File:DenglerSW-Stromboli-20040928-1230x800.jpg | thumb | Aristotle noted that the ground level of the [[Aeolian islands]] changed before a [[volcanic eruption]].]]
+
|Cetaceans||Dolphin, whale||with&nbsp;blood||none||S, V||,
   −
Aristotle noted that the ground level of the [[Aeolian islands changed before a volcanic eruption.
+
鲸类 海豚,鲸鱼,带血, 没有 S,V 热,湿
   −
Aristotle指出,在火山爆发之前,伊奥利亚群岛的地面就发生了变化。
+
|-
    +
|-
    +
|-
   −
===Geology===
+
|[[Cetaceans]]||[[Dolphin]], [[whale]]||with&nbsp;blood||none||S, V||{{font color|red|Hot}}, {{font color|green|Wet}}
地质学
  −
{{further | History of geology}}
      +
|Birds||Bee-eater, nightjar||with&nbsp;blood||2 legs||S, V||, , except  eggs
    +
鸟类,蜂虎鸟,夜鹰,带血, 两条腿,热,湿,干鸡蛋除外
   −
Aristotle was one of the first people to record any [[geology|geological]] observations. He stated that [[Uniformitarianism|geological change]] was too slow to be observed in one person's lifetime.{{sfn| Moore | 1956 | page=13}}{{sfn| Meteorology | p=Book 1, Part 14}}
+
|-
   −
Aristotle was one of the first people to record any geological observations. He stated that geological change was too slow to be observed in one person's lifetime.
+
|-
   −
Aristotle是最早记录地质观测数据的人之一。他说,地质变化太慢,在一个人的一生中无法观察到。
+
|-
   −
The geologist [[Charles Lyell]] noted that Aristotle described such change, including "lakes that had dried up" and "deserts that had become watered by rivers", giving as examples the growth of the [[Nile delta]] since the time of [[Homer]], and "the upheaving of one of the [[Aeolian islands]], previous to a [[volcanic eruption]]."'{{sfn| Lyell | 1832 | page=17}}
+
|[[Birds]]||[[Bee-eater]], [[nightjar]]||with&nbsp;blood||2 legs||S, V||{{font color|red|Hot}}, {{font color|green|Wet}}, except {{font color|brown|Dry}} eggs
   −
The geologist Charles Lyell noted that Aristotle described such change, including "lakes that had dried up" and "deserts that had become watered by rivers", giving as examples the growth of the Nile delta since the time of Homer, and "the upheaving of one of the Aeolian islands, previous to a volcanic eruption."'
+
|Egg-laying tetrapods||Chameleon, crocodile||with&nbsp;blood||4 legs||S, V||, except scales, eggs
   −
地质学家查尔斯•莱尔Charles Lyell指出,Aristotle描述了这种变化,包括 "已经干涸的湖泊 "和 "被河流浇灌的沙漠",他举例说,自荷马时代以来,尼罗河三角洲的增长,以及 "伊奥利亚群岛中的一个岛屿在火山喷发颠覆"。
+
产卵四足动物,变色龙,鳄鱼,,带血,4条腿,S,V 寒冷,潮湿,除了鳞片,蛋
    +
|-
   −
===Biology===
+
|-
生物学
  −
{{main | Aristotle's biology}}
     −
[[File:Tremoctopus violaceus5.jpg | thumb | upright | Among many pioneering zoological observations, Aristotle described the reproductive [[hectocotylus|hectocotyl arm]] of the [[octopus]] (bottom left).]]
+
|-
   −
在许多开拓性的动物学观察中,Aristotle描述了章鱼的生殖臂(左下)。
+
|[[Reptile|Egg-laying tetrapods]]||[[Chameleon]], [[crocodile]]||with&nbsp;blood||4 legs||S, V||{{font color|blue|Cold}}, {{font color|green|Wet}} except scales, eggs
    +
|Snakes||Water snake, Ottoman viper||with&nbsp;blood||none||S, V||,  except scales, eggs
    +
蛇,水蛇,奥斯曼毒蛇,带血,没有,S,V 寒冷,潮湿,除了鳞片和蛋
   −
====Empirical research====
+
|-
实证研究
  −
Aristotle was the first person to study biology systematically,{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | page=7}} and biology forms a large part of his writings. He spent two years observing and describing the zoology of [[Lesbos]] and the surrounding seas, including in particular the Pyrrha lagoon in the centre of Lesbos.{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | page=14}}{{sfn| Thompson | 1910 | page=Prefatory Note}} His data in ''[[History of Animals]]'', ''[[Generation of Animals]]'', ''[[Movement of Animals]]'', and ''[[Parts of Animals]]'' are assembled from his own observations,<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.independent.co.uk/arts-entertainment/books/reviews/darwins-ghosts-by-rebecca-stott-7808310.html|title=Darwin's Ghosts, By Rebecca Stott
     −
|website=independent.co.uk|date=2 June 2012
+
|-
   −
|access-date=19 June 2012}}</ref> statements given by people with specialized knowledge such as beekeepers and fishermen, and less accurate accounts provided by travellers from overseas.{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=196, 248}} His apparent emphasis on animals rather than plants is a historical accident: his works on [[botany]] have been lost, but two books on plants by his pupil Theophrastus have survived.{{sfn| Day | 2013 | pp=5805–16}}
+
|-
   −
Aristotle was the first person to study biology systematically, and biology forms a large part of his writings. He spent two years observing and describing the zoology of Lesbos and the surrounding seas, including in particular the Pyrrha lagoon in the centre of Lesbos. His data in History of Animals, Generation of Animals, Movement of Animals, and Parts of Animals are assembled from his own observations, statements given by people with specialized knowledge such as beekeepers and fishermen, and less accurate accounts provided by travellers from overseas. His apparent emphasis on animals rather than plants is a historical accident: his works on botany have been lost, but two books on plants by his pupil Theophrastus have survived.
+
|[[Snakes]]||Water snake, [[Ottoman viper]]||with&nbsp;blood||none||S, V||{{font color|blue|Cold}}, {{font color|green|Wet}} except scales, eggs
   −
Aristotle是第一个系统研究生物学的人,生物学构成了他著作的很大一部分。他花了两年时间观察和描述莱斯博斯岛及周围海域的动物学,尤其是包括莱斯伯斯岛的皮尔哈泻湖。他在《动物的历史》、《动物的生成》、《动物的运动》和《动物的部分》中的数据是根据他自己的观察、养蜂人和渔民等具有专业知识的人的陈述以及海外旅行者提供的不太准确的描述汇集而成。他显然强调动物而不是植物,这是一个历史的偶然:他的植物学著作已经遗失,但他的学生提Theophrastus的两本植物学著作却留了下来。
+
|Egg-laying fishes||Sea bass, parrotfish||with&nbsp;blood||none||S, V||, , including eggs
   −
Aristotle reports on the sea-life visible from observation on Lesbos and the catches of fishermen. He describes the [[catfish]], [[electric ray]], and [[frogfish]] in detail, as well as [[cephalopod]]s such as the [[octopus]] and [[paper nautilus]]. His description of the [[hectocotylus|hectocotyl arm]] of cephalopods, used in sexual reproduction, was widely disbelieved until the 19th century.{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=66–74, 137}} He gives accurate descriptions of the four-chambered fore-stomachs of [[ruminant]]s,{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=118–19}} and of the [[Ovoviviparity|ovoviviparous]] embryological development of the [[hound shark]].{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | page=73}}
+
产卵鱼,鲈鱼,鹦嘴鱼,带血, 没有,S,V 寒冷,潮湿包括卵
   −
Aristotle reports on the sea-life visible from observation on Lesbos and the catches of fishermen. He describes the catfish, electric ray, and frogfish in detail, as well as cephalopods such as the octopus and paper nautilus. His description of the hectocotyl arm of cephalopods, used in sexual reproduction, was widely disbelieved until the 19th century. He gives accurate descriptions of the four-chambered fore-stomachs of ruminants, and of the ovoviviparous embryological development of the hound shark.
+
|-
   −
Aristotle通过对莱斯博斯岛的观察和渔民的捕获来描述海洋生物。他详细描述了鲶鱼、电鳐和蛙鱼,以及章鱼和纸鹦鹉螺等头足类动物。直到19世纪,人们才广泛相信他所描述的头足类动物中的交接腕。他对反刍动物的四腔前胃和猎鲨的卵生胚胎发育作了准确的描述。
+
|-
    +
|-
   −
He notes that an animal's structure is well matched to function, so, among birds, the [[heron]], which lives in marshes with soft mud and lives by catching fish, has a long neck and long legs, and a sharp spear-like beak, whereas [[duck]]s that swim have short legs and webbed feet.{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=135–36}} [[Charles Darwin|Darwin]], too, noted these sorts of differences between similar kinds of animal, but unlike Aristotle used the data to come to the theory of [[evolution]].{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | page=206}} Aristotle's writings can seem to modern readers close to implying evolution, but while Aristotle was aware that new mutations or [[Hybridisation (biology)|hybridizations]] could occur, he saw these as rare accidents. For Aristotle, accidents, like heat waves in winter, must be considered distinct from natural causes. He was thus critical of Empedocles's materialist theory of a "survival of the fittest" origin of living things and their organs, and ridiculed the idea that accidents could lead to orderly results.{{sfn| Sedley | 2007 | page=189}} To put his views into modern terms, he nowhere says that different species can have a [[common descent|common ancestor]], or that one kind can [[speciation|change into another]], or that kinds can become [[extinction|extinct]].{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | page=273}}
+
|Egg-laying [[fish]]es||[[Sea bass]], [[Sparisoma cretense|parrotfish]]||with&nbsp;blood||none||S, V||{{font color|blue|Cold}}, {{font color|green|Wet}}, including eggs
   −
He notes that an animal's structure is well matched to function, so, among birds, the heron, which lives in marshes with soft mud and lives by catching fish, has a long neck and long legs, and a sharp spear-like beak, whereas ducks that swim have short legs and webbed feet. Darwin, too, noted these sorts of differences between similar kinds of animal, but unlike Aristotle used the data to come to the theory of evolution. Aristotle's writings can seem to modern readers close to implying evolution, but while Aristotle was aware that new mutations or hybridizations could occur, he saw these as rare accidents. For Aristotle, accidents, like heat waves in winter, must be considered distinct from natural causes. He was thus critical of Empedocles's materialist theory of a "survival of the fittest" origin of living things and their organs, and ridiculed the idea that accidents could lead to orderly results. To put his views into modern terms, he nowhere says that different species can have a common ancestor, or that one kind can change into another, or that kinds can become extinct.
+
|(Among the egg-laying fishes):<br>placental selachians||Shark, skate||with&nbsp;blood||none||S, V||, , but placenta like tetrapods
   −
他指出,动物的结构与功能是相匹配的,因此,在鸟类中,栖息在泥沼中以捕鱼为生的苍鹭有长长的脖子和长腿,还有像矛一样锋利的喙,而游泳的鸭子有短腿和蹼足。达尔文也注意到了类似动物之间的这些差异,但与Aristotle不同的是,他利用这些数据得出了进化论。对现代读者来说,Aristotle的著作似乎暗示了进化论,但当Aristotle意识到可能会发生新的突变或杂交时,他把这些看作是罕见的意外。对亚里士多德来说,对Aristotle来说,意外就像冬天的热浪一样,必须区别于自然原因来考虑。因此,他对Empedocles关于生物及其器官 "适者生存 "起源的唯物主义理论持批判态度,并嘲笑了意外事故可以导致有序结果的观点。用现代的术语来说,他没有说过不同的物种可以有一个共同的祖先,也没有说过一种物种可以变为另一种物种,也没有说过物种可以灭绝。
+
产卵鱼类中的胎盘类,鲨鱼,鳐鱼,带血,没有,S,V,寒冷,潮湿但胎盘像四足动物
    +
|-
   −
====Scientific style====
+
|-
科学风格
  −
[[File:Two of Aristotle's Growth Laws.svg | thumb | left | upright=1.4 | Aristotle inferred growth laws from his observations on animals, including that [[brood size]] decreases with body mass, whereas [[gestation]] period increases. He was correct in these predictions, at least for mammals: data are shown for mouse and elephant.]]
     −
Aristotle从他对动物的观察中推断出生长规律,包括卵数随着体重的增加而减少,而妊娠期却在增加。他的这些预测是正确的,至少对哺乳动物来说是这样:有数据显示了老鼠和大象的情况。
+
|-
   −
Aristotle did not do experiments in the modern sense.{{sfn| Taylor | 1922 | page=42}} He used the ancient Greek term ''pepeiramenoi'' to mean observations, or at most investigative procedures like dissection.{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=361–65}} In ''Generation of Animals'', he finds a fertilized hen's egg of a suitable stage and opens it to see the embryo's heart beating inside.{{sfn| Leroi | 2011}}{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=197–200}}
+
|(Among the egg-laying fishes):<br>placental [[selachian]]s||[[Shark]], [[Skate (fish)|skate]]||with&nbsp;blood||none||S, V||{{font color|blue|Cold}}, {{font color|green|Wet}}, but [[placenta]] like tetrapods
   −
Aristotle did not do experiments in the modern sense. He used the ancient Greek term pepeiramenoi to mean observations, or at most investigative procedures like dissection. In Generation of Animals, he finds a fertilized hen's egg of a suitable stage and opens it to see the embryo's heart beating inside.
+
|Crustaceans||Shrimp, crab||without||many legs||S, V||,  except shell
   −
Aristotle没有做现代意义上的实验。他使用古希腊术语pepeiramenoi来表示观察,或者至多表示像解剖这样的研究过程。在动物繁殖过程中,他找到一个处于合适阶段的受精卵,打开它看里面胚胎的心脏跳动。
+
甲壳类动物虾,蟹,没有,多腿,S,V 寒冷,潮湿除外壳
   −
Instead, he practiced a different style of science: systematically gathering data, discovering patterns common to whole groups of animals, and inferring possible causal explanations from these.{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=365–68}}{{sfn| Taylor | 1922 | page=49}} This style is common in modern biology when large amounts of data become available in a new field, such as [[genomics]]. It does not result in the same certainty as experimental science, but it sets out testable hypotheses and constructs a narrative explanation of what is observed. In this sense, Aristotle's biology is scientific.{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=365–68}}
+
|-
   −
Instead, he practiced a different style of science: systematically gathering data, discovering patterns common to whole groups of animals, and inferring possible causal explanations from these. This style is common in modern biology when large amounts of data become available in a new field, such as genomics. It does not result in the same certainty as experimental science, but it sets out testable hypotheses and constructs a narrative explanation of what is observed. In this sense, Aristotle's biology is scientific.
+
|-
   −
相反,他实践了一种不同的科学风格:系统地收集数据,发现整个动物群体的共同模式,并从中推断出可能的因果解释。这种风格在现代生物学中很常见,当在一个新的领域(如基因组学)中出现大量数据时,就会出现这种风格。它的结果并不像实验科学那样具有确定性,但它提出了可检验的假说,并对观察到的东西构建了一种叙述性的解释。在这个意义上,Aristotle的生物学是科学的。
+
|-
    +
|[[Crustaceans]]||[[Shrimp]], [[crab]]||without||many legs||S, V||{{font color|blue|Cold}}, {{font color|green|Wet}} except shell
   −
From the data he collected and documented, Aristotle inferred quite a number of [[biological rules|rules]] relating the life-history features of the live-bearing tetrapods (terrestrial placental mammals) that he studied. Among these correct predictions are the following. Brood size decreases with (adult) body mass, so that an elephant has fewer young (usually just one) per brood than a mouse. [[Life expectancy|Lifespan]] increases with [[gestation period]], and also with body mass, so that elephants live longer than mice, have a longer period of gestation, and are heavier. As a final example, [[fecundity]] decreases with lifespan, so long-lived kinds like elephants have fewer young in total than short-lived kinds like mice.{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | page=408}}{{-}}
+
|Cephalopods||Squid, octopus||without||tentacles||S, V||,
   −
From the data he collected and documented, Aristotle inferred quite a number of rules relating the life-history features of the live-bearing tetrapods (terrestrial placental mammals) that he studied. Among these correct predictions are the following. Brood size decreases with (adult) body mass, so that an elephant has fewer young (usually just one) per brood than a mouse. Lifespan increases with gestation period, and also with body mass, so that elephants live longer than mice, have a longer period of gestation, and are heavier. As a final example, fecundity decreases with lifespan, so long-lived kinds like elephants have fewer young in total than short-lived kinds like mice.
+
头足类动物,鱿鱼,章鱼,没有 触须,S,V 寒冷,潮湿
   −
从他收集和记录的数据中,Aristotle推断出许多他所研究的四足动物(陆生胎盘哺乳动物)生活史特征的规律。以下是正确的预测。幼体大小随着(成年)体重的增加而减少,因此大象每窝产下的幼体(通常只有一个)比老鼠少。寿命随着妊娠期和体重的增加而延长,因此大象比老鼠活得更长,妊娠期更长,体重也更重。最后一个例子是,繁殖力随着寿命的延长而减少,所以像大象这样的长寿种类的幼崽总数要少于像老鼠这样的短寿种类。
+
|-
   −
====Classification of living things====
+
|-
生物分类
  −
{{further | Scala naturae}}
     −
[[File:Scyliorhinus retifer embryo.JPG | thumb | Aristotle recorded that the [[embryo]] of [[Mustelus canis|<!--a different species shown-->a dogfish]] was attached by a cord to a kind of placenta (the [[yolk sac]]), like a higher animal; this formed an exception to the linear scale from highest to lowest.{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=72–74}}]]
+
|-
   −
Aristotle recorded that the [[embryo of <!--a different species shown-->a dogfish was attached by a cord to a kind of placenta (the yolk sac), like a higher animal; this formed an exception to the linear scale from highest to lowest.]]
+
|[[Cephalopods]]||[[Squid]], [[octopus]]||without||tentacles||S, V||{{font color|blue|Cold}}, {{font color|green|Wet}}
   −
Aristotle记载,角鲨的胚胎像高等动物一样,由一根绳索系在一种胎盘(卵黄囊)上;这形成了一个从最高到最低的线性尺度的例外。
+
|Hard-shelled animals||Cockle, trumpet snail||without||none||S, V||,  (mineral shell)
   −
Aristotle distinguished about 500 species of [[animal]]s,{{sfn| Bergstrom | Dugatkin | 2012 | page=35}}{{sfn| Rhodes | 1974 | page=7}} arranging these in the ''History of Animals'' in a graded scale of perfection, a ''[[scala naturae]]'', with man at the top. His system had eleven grades of animal, from highest potential to lowest, expressed in their form at birth: the highest gave [[viviparity|live birth]] to hot and wet creatures, the lowest laid cold, dry mineral-like eggs. Animals came above [[plant]]s, and these in turn were above minerals.{{sfn| Mayr | 1982 | pages=201–02}} see also:{{sfn| Lovejoy | 1976}} He grouped what the modern zoologist would call [[vertebrate]]s as the hotter "animals with blood", and below them the colder [[invertebrate]]s as "animals without blood". Those with blood were divided into the live-bearing ([[mammal]]s), and the egg-laying ([[bird]]s, [[reptile]]s, [[fish]]). Those without blood were insects, crustacea (non-shelled – cephalopods, and [[crustacea|shelled]]) and the hard-shelled [[mollusc]]s ([[bivalve]]s and [[gastropod]]s). He recognised that animals did not exactly fit into a linear scale, and noted various exceptions, such as that sharks had a [[placenta]] like the tetrapods. To a modern biologist, the explanation, not available to Aristotle,<!--Leroi | p= 113--> is [[convergent evolution]].{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=111–19}} He believed that purposive final causes guided all natural processes; this [[teleological]] view justified his observed data as an expression of formal design.{{sfn| Mason | 1979 | pp=43–44}}
+
硬壳动物,海扇类,喇叭螺 没有,没有 S,V寒冷,干燥(矿物克)
   −
Aristotle distinguished about 500 species of animals, arranging these in the History of Animals in a graded scale of perfection, a scala naturae, with man at the top. His system had eleven grades of animal, from highest potential to lowest, expressed in their form at birth: the highest gave live birth to hot and wet creatures, the lowest laid cold, dry mineral-like eggs. Animals came above plants, and these in turn were above minerals. see also: He grouped what the modern zoologist would call vertebrates as the hotter "animals with blood", and below them the colder invertebrates as "animals without blood". Those with blood were divided into the live-bearing (mammals), and the egg-laying (birds, reptiles, fish). Those without blood were insects, crustacea (non-shelled – cephalopods, and shelled) and the hard-shelled molluscs (bivalves and gastropods). He recognised that animals did not exactly fit into a linear scale, and noted various exceptions, such as that sharks had a placenta like the tetrapods. To a modern biologist, the explanation, not available to Aristotle,<!--Leroi | p= 113--> is convergent evolution. He believed that purposive final causes guided all natural processes; this teleological view justified his observed data as an expression of formal design.
+
|-
   −
Aristotle区分了大约500种动物,在动物发展史上按照完美程度(即自然等级)对它们进行排列,其中人处于最顶端。他的系统将动物分为11个等级,从潜能最高的到潜能最低的,以出生时的形式表现出来:潜能最高的能生下湿热的生物,而潜能最低的能生下冰冷、干燥的类似矿物的蛋。动物在植物之上,植物又在矿物之上。另见:他将现代动物学家称之为脊椎动物的动物归类为温度较高的“带血的动物”,而温度较低的无脊椎动物则归类为“无血的动物”。那些有血液的动物被分为胎生动物(哺乳动物)和卵生动物(鸟类、爬行动物、鱼类)。那些没有血液的是昆虫、甲壳类(无壳的头足类和有壳的)和硬壳软体动物(双壳类和腹足类)。他认识到动物并不完全符合线性比例,并指出了各种例外情况,比如鲨鱼和四足动物一样有胎盘。对现代生物学家来说,亚里士多德无法解释的解释是趋同进化。他相信有目的的最终原因引导着所有的自然过程;这种目的论的观点证明他观察到的数据是形式设计的一种表现。
+
|-
   −
{| class="wikitable" style="font-size: 80%;"
+
|-
   −
{ | class = “ wikitable” style = “ font-size: 80% ; ”
+
|[[Mollusc|Hard-shelled animals]]||[[Cockle (bivalve)|Cockle]], [[Charonia variegata|trumpet snail]]||without||none||S, V||{{font color|blue|Cold}}, {{font color|brown|Dry}} (mineral shell)
    +
|Larva-bearing insects||Ant, cicada||without||6 legs||S, V||,
    +
幼虫,蚂蚁,蝉,没有,6条腿,S,V寒冷,干燥
   −
|+ Aristotle's Scala naturae (highest to lowest)
+
|-
 
  −
| + Aristotle的斯卡拉自然史(最高到最低)
  −
 
  −
{| class="wikitable" style="font-size: 80%;"
  −
 
  −
! Group !! Examples<br>(given by Aristotle) !! Blood !! Legs !! Souls<br>(Rational,<br>Sensitive,<br>Vegetative) !! Qualities<br>(–,<br>–)
  −
 
  −
!组! !示例 < br > (由亚里士多德给出) ! !血液! !腿部! !灵魂(理性,敏感,植物性) ! !品质 < br > (热-冷 ,< br >湿 -干)
  −
 
  −
|+ Aristotle's ''[[Scala naturae]]'' (highest to lowest)
      
|-
 
|-
第967行: 第908行:  
|-
 
|-
   −
! Group !! Examples<br>(given by Aristotle) !! Blood !! Legs !! Souls<br>(Rational,<br>Sensitive,<br>Vegetative) !! Qualities<br>({{font color|red|Hot}}–{{font color|blue|Cold}},<br>{{font color|green|Wet}}–{{font color|brown|Dry}})
+
|Larva-bearing insects||[[Ant]], [[cicada]]||without||6 legs||S, V||{{font color|blue|Cold}}, {{font color|brown|Dry}}
   −
|Man||Man||with&nbsp;blood||2 legs||R, S, V||,  
+
|Spontaneously-generating||Sponges, worms||without||none||S, V||, or , from earth
   −
人 人 带血 2条腿 R,S,V 热,湿
+
从地球上自发产生的,海绵,蠕虫 没有 没有 S,V 寒冷,潮湿或干燥,来自地球
    
|-
 
|-
第979行: 第920行:  
|-
 
|-
   −
|Man||Man||with&nbsp;blood||2 legs||R, S, V||{{font color|red|Hot}}, {{font color|green|Wet}}
+
|[[Spontaneous generation|Spontaneously-generating]]||[[Sponges]], [[worm]]s||without||none||S, V||{{font color|blue|Cold}}, {{font color|green|Wet}} or {{font color|brown|Dry}}, from earth
 +
 
 +
|Plants||Fig||without||none||V||,
   −
|Live-bearing tetrapods||Cat, hare||with&nbsp;blood||4 legs||S, V||,  
+
植物,无花果,没有,没有 V 寒冷,干燥
   −
四足动物 猫,野兔 带血 4条腿 S,V 热,湿
   
|-
 
|-
   第990行: 第932行:  
|-
 
|-
   −
|[[Mammal|Live-bearing tetrapods]]||Cat, [[hare]]||with&nbsp;blood||4 legs||S, V||{{font color|red|Hot}}, {{font color|green|Wet}}
+
|[[Plants]]||[[Common fig|Fig]]||without||none||V||{{font color|blue|Cold}}, {{font color|brown|Dry}}
   −
|Cetaceans||Dolphin, whale||with&nbsp;blood||none||S, V||,  
+
|Minerals||Iron||without||none||none||,  
   −
鲸类 海豚,鲸鱼,带血, 没有 S,V 热,湿
+
矿物,铁,没有,没有,没有 寒冷,干燥
    
|-
 
|-
   −
|-
+
|}
   −
|-
+
|}
   −
|[[Cetaceans]]||[[Dolphin]], [[whale]]||with&nbsp;blood||none||S, V||{{font color|red|Hot}}, {{font color|green|Wet}}
+
|[[Mineral]]s||Iron||without||none||none||{{font color|blue|Cold}}, {{font color|brown|Dry}}
   −
|Birds||Bee-eater, nightjar||with&nbsp;blood||2 legs||S, V||, , except  eggs
+
|}
   −
鸟类,蜂虎鸟,夜鹰,带血, 两条腿,热,湿,干鸡蛋除外
     −
|-
     −
|-
+
===Psychology===
 +
心理学
   −
|-
     −
|[[Birds]]||[[Bee-eater]], [[nightjar]]||with&nbsp;blood||2 legs||S, V||{{font color|red|Hot}}, {{font color|green|Wet}}, except {{font color|brown|Dry}} eggs
+
====Soul====
 +
灵魂
   −
|Egg-laying tetrapods||Chameleon, crocodile||with&nbsp;blood||4 legs||S, V||,  except scales, eggs
+
{{further | On the Soul}}
   −
产卵四足动物,变色龙,鳄鱼,,带血,4条腿,S,V 寒冷,潮湿,除了鳞片,蛋
+
[[File:Aristotelian Soul.png | thumb | upright=1.5 | Aristotle proposed a three-part [[Soul#Aristotle|structure for souls]] of plants, animals, and humans, making humans unique in having all three types of soul.]]
   −
|-
+
Aristotle proposed a three-part structure for souls of plants, animals, and humans, making humans unique in having all three types of soul.
   −
|-
+
Aristotle提出了植物、动物和人类的灵魂的三部分结构,这使得人类独特地拥有这三种类型的灵魂。
   −
|-
+
Aristotle's [[psychology]], given in his treatise ''[[On the Soul]]'' (''peri psychēs''), posits three kinds of [[soul]] ("psyches"): the vegetative soul, the sensitive soul, and the rational soul. Humans have a rational soul. The human soul incorporates the powers of the other kinds: Like the vegetative soul it can grow and nourish itself; like the sensitive soul it can experience sensations and move locally. The unique part of the human, rational soul is its ability to receive forms of other things and to compare them using the ''[[Nous#Aristotle|nous]]'' (intellect) and ''logos'' (reason).{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=156–63}}
   −
|[[Reptile|Egg-laying tetrapods]]||[[Chameleon]], [[crocodile]]||with&nbsp;blood||4 legs||S, V||{{font color|blue|Cold}}, {{font color|green|Wet}} except scales, eggs
+
Aristotle's psychology, given in his treatise On the Soul (peri psychēs), posits three kinds of soul ("psyches"): the vegetative soul, the sensitive soul, and the rational soul. Humans have a rational soul. The human soul incorporates the powers of the other kinds: Like the vegetative soul it can grow and nourish itself; like the sensitive soul it can experience sensations and move locally. The unique part of the human, rational soul is its ability to receive forms of other things and to compare them using the nous (intellect) and logos (reason).
   −
|Snakes||Water snake, Ottoman viper||with&nbsp;blood||none||S, V||,  except scales, eggs
+
Aristotle的心理学,在他的论文《论灵魂》(peri psychēs)中,提出了三种灵魂("psyches"):植物性灵魂、敏感性灵魂和理性灵魂。人类有一个理性的灵魂。人类的灵魂融合了其他种类的力量。像植物性灵魂一样,它可以生长和滋养自己;像敏感的灵魂一样,它可以体验感觉和局部移动。人的理性灵魂的独特之处在于它能接受其他事物的形式,并能用nous(智力)和logos(理智)来比较它们。
   −
蛇,水蛇,奥斯曼毒蛇,带血,没有,S,V 寒冷,潮湿,除了鳞片和蛋
+
For Aristotle, the soul is the [[Hylomorphism#Body–soul hylomorphism|form]] of a living being. Because all beings are composites of form and matter, the form of living beings is that which endows them with what is specific to living beings, e.g. the ability to initiate movement (or in the case of plants, growth and chemical transformations, which Aristotle considers types of movement).{{sfn| Shields | 2016}} In contrast to earlier philosophers, but in accordance with the Egyptians, he placed the rational soul in the heart, rather than the brain.{{sfn| Mason | 1979 | p=45}} Notable is Aristotle's division of sensation and thought, which generally differed from the concepts of previous philosophers, with the exception of [[Alcmaeon of Croton|Alcmaeon]].{{sfn| Guthrie | 2010 | p=348}}
   −
|-
+
For Aristotle, the soul is the form of a living being. Because all beings are composites of form and matter, the form of living beings is that which endows them with what is specific to living beings, e.g. the ability to initiate movement (or in the case of plants, growth and chemical transformations, which Aristotle considers types of movement). In contrast to earlier philosophers, but in accordance with the Egyptians, he placed the rational soul in the heart, rather than the brain. Notable is Aristotle's division of sensation and thought, which generally differed from the concepts of previous philosophers, with the exception of Alcmaeon.
   −
|-
+
在Aristotle看来,灵魂是生命体的形式。因为所有的生命都是形式和物质的复合体,所以生命体的形式就是赋予生命体特有的东西,例如发起运动的能力(或者在植物的情况下,发起生长和化学转化,Aristotle认为这是运动的类型)。与早期的哲学家不同,但与埃及人一致,他把理性的灵魂放在心里,而不是大脑。值得注意的是亚里士多德对感觉和思维的划分,除阿尔克马翁Alcmaeon外,一般都与以前哲学家的概念不同。
   −
|-
     −
|[[Snakes]]||Water snake, [[Ottoman viper]]||with&nbsp;blood||none||S, V||{{font color|blue|Cold}}, {{font color|green|Wet}} except scales, eggs
+
====Memory====
 +
记忆
   −
|Egg-laying fishes||Sea bass, parrotfish||with&nbsp;blood||none||S, V||, , including eggs
+
According to Aristotle in ''On the Soul'', memory is the ability to hold a perceived experience in the mind and to distinguish between the internal "appearance" and an occurrence in the past.{{sfn| Bloch | 2007 | p=12}} In other words, a memory is a mental picture ([[wikt:phantasm|phantasm]]) that can be recovered. Aristotle believed an impression is left on a semi-fluid bodily organ that undergoes several changes in order to make a memory. A memory occurs when [[stimulus (psychology)|stimuli]] such as sights or sounds are so complex that the nervous system cannot receive all the impressions at once. These changes are the same as those involved in the operations of sensation, Aristotelian '[[common sense]]', and thinking.{{sfn| Bloch | 2007 | p=61}}{{sfn| Carruthers | 2007 | p=16}}
   −
产卵鱼,鲈鱼,鹦嘴鱼,带血, 没有,S,V 寒冷,潮湿包括卵
+
According to Aristotle in On the Soul, memory is the ability to hold a perceived experience in the mind and to distinguish between the internal "appearance" and an occurrence in the past. In other words, a memory is a mental picture (phantasm) that can be recovered. Aristotle believed an impression is left on a semi-fluid bodily organ that undergoes several changes in order to make a memory. A memory occurs when stimuli such as sights or sounds are so complex that the nervous system cannot receive all the impressions at once. These changes are the same as those involved in the operations of sensation, Aristotelian 'common sense', and thinking.
   −
|-
+
根据Aristotle在《论灵魂》一书中的观点,记忆是指将感知到的经验保存在脑海中,并将内部的 "表象 "与过去发生的事情区分开来的能力。换句话说,记忆是一种可以恢复的心理图景(幻象)。Aristotle认为,印象是在半流体的身体器官上留下的,经过几次变化,才能形成记忆。当景物或声音等刺激物非常复杂,以至于神经系统不能同时接受所有的印象时,就会产生记忆。这些变化与感觉、Aristotle的 "常识 "和思维的操作一样。
   −
|-
+
Aristotle uses the term 'memory' for the actual retaining of an experience in the impression that can develop from sensation, and for the intellectual anxiety that comes with the impression because it is formed at a particular time and processing specific contents. Memory is of the past, prediction is of the future, and sensation is of the present. Retrieval of impressions cannot be performed suddenly. A transitional channel is needed and located in our past experiences, both for our previous experience and present experience.{{sfn| Bloch | 2007 | p=25}}
   −
|-
+
Aristotle uses the term 'memory' for the actual retaining of an experience in the impression that can develop from sensation, and for the intellectual anxiety that comes with the impression because it is formed at a particular time and processing specific contents. Memory is of the past, prediction is of the future, and sensation is of the present. Retrieval of impressions cannot be performed suddenly. A transitional channel is needed and located in our past experiences, both for our previous experience and present experience.
   −
|Egg-laying [[fish]]es||[[Sea bass]], [[Sparisoma cretense|parrotfish]]||with&nbsp;blood||none||S, V||{{font color|blue|Cold}}, {{font color|green|Wet}}, including eggs
+
Aristotle用 "记忆 "一词,是指在印象中实际保留一种经验,而这种经验可以从感觉中发展出来,同时,由于印象是在特定的时间和加工特定的内容中形成的,因此,这种印象会带来知识上的焦虑。记忆是过去的,预测是未来的,感觉是现在的。印象的检索不能突然进行。需要一个过渡通道,位于我们过去的经验中,既是我们以前的经验,也是现在的经验。
   −
|(Among the egg-laying fishes):<br>placental selachians||Shark, skate||with&nbsp;blood||none||S, V||, , but placenta like tetrapods
+
Because Aristotle believes people receive all kinds of sense perceptions and perceive them as impressions, people are continually weaving together new impressions of experiences. To search for these impressions, people search the memory itself.{{sfn| Warren | 1921 | p=30}} Within the memory, if one experience is offered instead of a specific memory, that person will reject this experience until they find what they are looking for. Recollection occurs when one retrieved experience naturally follows another. If the chain of "images" is needed, one memory will stimulate the next. When people recall experiences, they stimulate certain previous experiences until they reach the one that is needed.{{sfn| Warren | 1921 | p=25}} Recollection is thus the self-directed activity of retrieving the information stored in a memory impression.{{sfn| Carruthers | 2007 | p=19}} Only humans can remember impressions of intellectual activity, such as numbers and words. Animals that have perception of time can retrieve memories of their past observations. Remembering involves only perception of the things remembered and of the time passed.{{sfn| Warren | 1921 | p=296}}
   −
产卵鱼类中的胎盘类,鲨鱼,鳐鱼,带血,没有,S,V,寒冷,潮湿但胎盘像四足动物
+
Because Aristotle believes people receive all kinds of sense perceptions and perceive them as impressions, people are continually weaving together new impressions of experiences. To search for these impressions, people search the memory itself. Within the memory, if one experience is offered instead of a specific memory, that person will reject this experience until they find what they are looking for. Recollection occurs when one retrieved experience naturally follows another. If the chain of "images" is needed, one memory will stimulate the next. When people recall experiences, they stimulate certain previous experiences until they reach the one that is needed. Recollection is thus the self-directed activity of retrieving the information stored in a memory impression. Only humans can remember impressions of intellectual activity, such as numbers and words. Animals that have perception of time can retrieve memories of their past observations. Remembering involves only perception of the things remembered and of the time passed.
   −
|-
+
因为Aristotle认为,人们接受各种感觉知觉,并把它们当作印象来认识,所以人们不断地把新的经验印象编织在一起。为了寻找这些印象,人们搜索记忆本身。在记忆中,如果提供一种经验而不是特定的记忆,那么这个人就会拒绝这种经验,直到找到他们所要找的东西。当一个检索到的经验自然而然地跟在另一个经验后面时,就会出现回忆。如果需要 "图像 "的链条,一个记忆会刺激下一个记忆。当人们回忆经验时,他们会刺激以前的某些经验,直到达到需要的经验。因此,回忆是检索存储在记忆印象中的信息的自发活动。只有人类能记住数字、文字等智力活动的印象。有时间知觉的动物可以检索过去观察的记忆。记忆只涉及对所记事物和所过时间的感知。
   −
|-
+
[[File:Aristotle Senses Perception Memory Dreams Action.svg | thumb | upright=2.3 | Senses, perception, memory, dreams, action in Aristotle's psychology. Impressions are stored in the [[sensorium]] (the heart), linked by his [[laws of association]] (similarity, contrast, and [[Contiguity (psychology)|contiguity]]).]]
   −
|-
+
Senses, perception, memory, dreams, action in Aristotle's psychology. Impressions are stored in the sensorium (the heart), linked by his laws of association (similarity, contrast, and contiguity).
   −
|(Among the egg-laying fishes):<br>placental [[selachian]]s||[[Shark]], [[Skate (fish)|skate]]||with&nbsp;blood||none||S, V||{{font color|blue|Cold}}, {{font color|green|Wet}}, but [[placenta]] like tetrapods
+
Aristotle心理学中的感觉、知觉、记忆、梦、行动。印象被储存在感观(心)中,由他的联想法则(相似性、对比性和相邻性)联系起来。
   −
|Crustaceans||Shrimp, crab||without||many legs||S, V||,  except shell
+
Aristotle believed the chain of thought, which ends in recollection of certain impressions, was connected systematically in relationships such as similarity, contrast, and [[Contiguity (psychology)|contiguity]], described in his [[laws of association]]. Aristotle believed that past experiences are hidden within the mind. A force operates to awaken the hidden material to bring up the actual experience. According to Aristotle, association is the power innate in a mental state, which operates upon the unexpressed remains of former experiences, allowing them to rise and be recalled.{{sfn| Warren | 1921 | p=259}}{{sfn | Sorabji | 2006 | p=54}}
   −
甲壳类动物虾,蟹,没有,多腿,S,V 寒冷,潮湿除外壳
+
Aristotle believed the chain of thought, which ends in recollection of certain impressions, was connected systematically in relationships such as similarity, contrast, and contiguity, described in his laws of association. Aristotle believed that past experiences are hidden within the mind. A force operates to awaken the hidden material to bring up the actual experience. According to Aristotle, association is the power innate in a mental state, which operates upon the unexpressed remains of former experiences, allowing them to rise and be recalled.
   −
|-
+
Aristotle认为,以回忆某些印象为终结的思维链,在他的联想定律中描述的相似性、对比性和相邻性等关系中,是有系统地连接起来的。Aristotle认为,过去的经验是隐藏在头脑中的。一种力量的运作唤醒了隐藏的材料,使实际的经验浮现出来。根据Aristotle的观点,联想是一种精神状态中与生俱来的力量,它作用于过去经验中未被表达的残余,使它们得以升起并被唤起。
   −
|-
     −
|-
+
====Dreams====
 +
   −
|[[Crustaceans]]||[[Shrimp]], [[crab]]||without||many legs||S, V||{{font color|blue|Cold}}, {{font color|green|Wet}} except shell
+
{{see | Dream#Classical history}}
   −
|Cephalopods||Squid, octopus||without||tentacles||S, V||,  
+
Aristotle describes sleep in ''On Sleep and Wakefulness''.{{sfn| Holowchak | 1996 | pp=405–23}} Sleep takes place as a result of overuse of the senses{{sfn| Shute | 1941 | pages=115–18}} or of digestion,{{sfn| Holowchak | 1996 | pp=405–23}} so it is vital to the body.{{sfn| Shute | 1941 | pages=115–18}} While a person is asleep, the critical activities, which include thinking, sensing, recalling and remembering, do not function as they do during wakefulness. Since a person cannot sense during sleep they can not have desire, which is the result of sensation. However, the senses are able to work during sleep,{{sfn| Shute | 1941 | pages=115–18}} albeit differently,{{sfn| Holowchak | 1996 | pp=405–23}} unless they are weary.{{sfn| Shute | 1941 | pages=115–18}}
   −
头足类动物,鱿鱼,章鱼,没有 触须,S,V 寒冷,潮湿
+
Aristotle describes sleep in On Sleep and Wakefulness. Sleep takes place as a result of overuse of the senses or of digestion, so it is vital to the body. While a person is asleep, the critical activities, which include thinking, sensing, recalling and remembering, do not function as they do during wakefulness. Since a person cannot sense during sleep they can not have desire, which is the result of sensation. However, the senses are able to work during sleep, albeit differently, unless they are weary.
   −
|-
+
Aristotle在《论睡眠与觉醒》中对睡眠进行了描述。睡眠的发生是感官的过度使用或消化的结果,所以它对身体至关重要。当一个人处于睡眠状态时,包括思考、感知、回忆和记忆在内的关键活动,不会像清醒时那样发挥作用。由于人在睡眠中不能感知,他们就不能有欲望,而欲望是感觉的结果。然而,感官在睡眠期间能够工作,尽管方式不同,除非它们疲惫不堪。
   −
|-
+
Dreams do not involve actually sensing a stimulus. In dreams, sensation is still involved, but in an altered manner.{{sfn| Shute | 1941 | pages=115–18}} Aristotle explains that when a person stares at a moving stimulus such as the waves in a body of water, and then look away, the next thing they look at appears to have a wavelike motion. When a person perceives a stimulus and the stimulus is no longer the focus of their attention, it leaves an impression.{{sfn| Holowchak | 1996 | pp=405–23}} When the body is awake and the senses are functioning properly, a person constantly encounters new stimuli to sense and so the impressions of previously perceived stimuli are ignored.{{sfn| Shute | 1941 | pages=115–18}} However, during sleep the impressions made throughout the day are noticed as there are no new distracting sensory experiences.{{sfn| Holowchak | 1996 | pp=405–23}} So, dreams result from these lasting impressions. Since impressions are all that are left and not the exact stimuli, dreams do not resemble the actual waking experience.{{sfn| Modrak | 2009 | pp=169–81}} During sleep, a person is in an altered state of mind. Aristotle compares a sleeping person to a person who is overtaken by strong feelings toward a stimulus. For example, a person who has a strong infatuation with someone may begin to think they see that person everywhere because they are so overtaken by their feelings. Since a person sleeping is in a suggestible state and unable to make judgements, they become easily deceived by what appears in their dreams, like the infatuated person.{{sfn| Holowchak | 1996 | pp=405–23}} This leads the person to believe the dream is real, even when the dreams are absurd in nature.{{sfn| Holowchak | 1996 | pp=405–23}} In ''De Anima'' iii 3, Aristotle ascribes the ability to create, to store, and to recall images in the absence of perception to the faculty of imagination, ''phantasia''.{{sfn| Shields | 2016}}
   −
|-
+
Dreams do not involve actually sensing a stimulus. In dreams, sensation is still involved, but in an altered manner. Aristotle explains that when a person stares at a moving stimulus such as the waves in a body of water, and then look away, the next thing they look at appears to have a wavelike motion. When a person perceives a stimulus and the stimulus is no longer the focus of their attention, it leaves an impression. When the body is awake and the senses are functioning properly, a person constantly encounters new stimuli to sense and so the impressions of previously perceived stimuli are ignored. However, during sleep the impressions made throughout the day are noticed as there are no new distracting sensory experiences. So, dreams result from these lasting impressions. Since impressions are all that are left and not the exact stimuli, dreams do not resemble the actual waking experience. During sleep, a person is in an altered state of mind. Aristotle compares a sleeping person to a person who is overtaken by strong feelings toward a stimulus. For example, a person who has a strong infatuation with someone may begin to think they see that person everywhere because they are so overtaken by their feelings. Since a person sleeping is in a suggestible state and unable to make judgements, they become easily deceived by what appears in their dreams, like the infatuated person. This leads the person to believe the dream is real, even when the dreams are absurd in nature. In De Anima iii 3, Aristotle ascribes the ability to create, to store, and to recall images in the absence of perception to the faculty of imagination, phantasia.
   −
|[[Cephalopods]]||[[Squid]], [[octopus]]||without||tentacles||S, V||{{font color|blue|Cold}}, {{font color|green|Wet}}
+
梦并不涉及到实际的感觉刺激。在梦中,感觉仍然参与其中,但以一种改变的方式。Aristotle解释说,当一个人盯着一个移动的刺激物,如水体中的波浪,然后把目光移开,他们所看的下一个东西就会出现波浪般的运动。当一个人感知到一个刺激物,而这个刺激物不再是他们注意的焦点时,就会留下印象。当身体清醒,感官功能正常时,人不断地遇到新的刺激物来感知,所以以前感知到的刺激物的印象就被忽略了。但是,在睡眠中,由于没有新的干扰感官体验,所以一整天的印象都会被注意到。所以,梦是这些持久印象的结果。由于留下的只是印象,而不是确切的刺激,所以梦境与实际的清醒经验并不相似。在睡眠中,人的精神状态发生了改变。亚里士多德把睡眠中的人比作一个对刺激物产生强烈感情的人。例如,一个对某人有强烈迷恋的人可能会开始认为他们到处都能看到那个人,因为他们被自己的感情冲昏了头脑。由于睡眠中的人处于易受暗示的状态,无法做出判断,所以很容易被梦中出现的东西所欺骗,就像那个痴情的人一样。这使人相信梦境是真实的,即使梦境的本质是荒谬的。在《德阿尼玛三世》3中,Aristotle把在没有知觉的情况下创造、储存和回忆形象的能力归结为想象力的能力,即幻觉。
   −
|Hard-shelled animals||Cockle, trumpet snail||without||none||S, V||,  (mineral shell)
     −
硬壳动物,海扇类,喇叭螺 没有,没有 S,V寒冷,干燥(矿物克)
+
One component of Aristotle's theory of dreams disagrees with previously held beliefs. He claimed that dreams are not foretelling and not sent by a divine being. Aristotle reasoned naturalistically that instances in which dreams do resemble future events are simply coincidences.{{sfn| Webb | 1990 | pages=174–84}} Aristotle claimed that a dream is first established by the fact that the person is asleep when they experience it. If a person had an image appear for a moment after waking up or if they see something in the dark it is not considered a dream because they were awake when it occurred. Secondly, any sensory experience that is perceived while a person is asleep does not qualify as part of a dream. For example, if, while a person is sleeping, a door shuts and in their dream they hear a door is shut, this sensory experience is not part of the dream. Lastly, the images of dreams must be a result of lasting impressions of waking sensory experiences.{{sfn| Modrak | 2009 | pp=169–81}}
   −
|-
+
One component of Aristotle's theory of dreams disagrees with previously held beliefs. He claimed that dreams are not foretelling and not sent by a divine being. Aristotle reasoned naturalistically that instances in which dreams do resemble future events are simply coincidences. Aristotle claimed that a dream is first established by the fact that the person is asleep when they experience it. If a person had an image appear for a moment after waking up or if they see something in the dark it is not considered a dream because they were awake when it occurred. Secondly, any sensory experience that is perceived while a person is asleep does not qualify as part of a dream. For example, if, while a person is sleeping, a door shuts and in their dream they hear a door is shut, this sensory experience is not part of the dream. Lastly, the images of dreams must be a result of lasting impressions of waking sensory experiences.
   −
|-
+
Aristotle的梦境理论中有一个内容与以前的信念不一致。他声称,梦不是预言,也不是由神灵发出的。Aristotle从自然主义的角度推理,梦境确实与未来事件相似的事例只是巧合。Aristotle称,梦的成立首先要看人在经历梦的时候是否睡着了。如果一个人在醒来后有一个影像出现了一会儿,或者他们在黑暗中看到了一些东西,就不认为是梦,因为当梦发生时他们是清醒的。其次,任何在人睡觉时被感知到的感官体验都不能算作梦的一部分。例如,如果一个人在睡觉的时候,一扇门关上了,而在梦中他们听到门被关上了,这种感官体验不属于梦的一部分。最后,梦中的影像必须是清醒的感官体验的持久印象的结果。
   −
|-
     −
|[[Mollusc|Hard-shelled animals]]||[[Cockle (bivalve)|Cockle]], [[Charonia variegata|trumpet snail]]||without||none||S, V||{{font color|blue|Cold}}, {{font color|brown|Dry}} (mineral shell)
+
==Practical philosophy==
 +
实践哲学
 +
Aristotle's practical philosophy covers areas such as ethics, politics, economics, and rhetoric.{{sfn| Wildberg | 2016}}
   −
|Larva-bearing insects||Ant, cicada||without||6 legs||S, V||,  
+
Aristotle's practical philosophy covers areas such as ethics, politics, economics, and rhetoric.
 +
 
 +
Aristotle的实践哲学涵盖了伦理学、政治学、经济学和修辞学等领域。
   −
幼虫,蚂蚁,蝉,没有,6条腿,S,V寒冷,干燥
+
{| class="wikitable floatright" align=right style="font-size: 80%;"
   −
|-
+
{ | class = “ wikitable floatright” align = right style = “ font-size: 80% ;
   −
|-
+
|+ Virtues and their accompanying vices
   −
|-
+
| + 美德及伴随的恶习
   −
|Larva-bearing insects||[[Ant]], [[cicada]]||without||6 legs||S, V||{{font color|blue|Cold}}, {{font color|brown|Dry}}
+
{| class="wikitable floatright" align=right style="font-size: 80%;"
   −
|Spontaneously-generating||Sponges, worms||without||none||S, V||,  or , from earth
+
! Too little !! Virtuous mean !! Too much
   −
从地球上自发产生的,海绵,蠕虫 没有 没有 S,V 寒冷,潮湿或干燥,来自地球
+
!太少了 均值 太多了
   −
|-
+
|+ Virtues and their accompanying vices{{sfn|Aristotle (384–322 B.C.E.)}}
    
|-
 
|-
第1,122行: 第1,065行:  
|-
 
|-
   −
|[[Spontaneous generation|Spontaneously-generating]]||[[Sponges]], [[worm]]s||without||none||S, V||{{font color|blue|Cold}}, {{font color|green|Wet}} or {{font color|brown|Dry}}, from earth
+
! Too little !! Virtuous mean !! Too much
   −
|Plants||Fig||without||none||V||,
+
|Humbleness||High-mindedness||Vainglory
 
+
谦虚 胸怀大志 虚荣
植物,无花果,没有,没有 V 寒冷,干燥
+
|Humbleness||High-mindedness||Vainglory
    
|-
 
|-
第1,134行: 第1,077行:  
|-
 
|-
   −
|[[Plants]]||[[Common fig|Fig]]||without||none||V||{{font color|blue|Cold}}, {{font color|brown|Dry}}
+
|Humbleness||High-mindedness||Vainglory
   −
|Minerals||Iron||without||none||none||,
+
|Lack of purpose||Right ambition||Over-ambition
   −
矿物,铁,没有,没有,没有 寒冷,干燥
+
缺乏目标 正确的野心 过于野心勃勃
    
|-
 
|-
   −
|}
+
|-
   −
|}
+
|-
   −
|[[Mineral]]s||Iron||without||none||none||{{font color|blue|Cold}}, {{font color|brown|Dry}}
+
|Lack of purpose||Right ambition||Over-ambition
   −
|}
+
|Spiritlessness||Good temper||Irascibility
    +
无精打采 脾气好 脾气暴躁
    +
|-
   −
===Psychology===
+
|-
心理学
      +
|-
   −
====Soul====
+
|Spiritlessness||Good temper||Irascibility
灵魂
     −
{{further | On the Soul}}
+
|Rudeness||Civility||Obsequiousness
   −
[[File:Aristotelian Soul.png | thumb | upright=1.5 | Aristotle proposed a three-part [[Soul#Aristotle|structure for souls]] of plants, animals, and humans, making humans unique in having all three types of soul.]]
+
粗鲁,礼貌,谄媚
   −
Aristotle proposed a three-part structure for souls of plants, animals, and humans, making humans unique in having all three types of soul.
+
|-
   −
Aristotle提出了植物、动物和人类的灵魂的三部分结构,这使得人类独特地拥有这三种类型的灵魂。
+
|-
   −
Aristotle's [[psychology]], given in his treatise ''[[On the Soul]]'' (''peri psychēs''), posits three kinds of [[soul]] ("psyches"): the vegetative soul, the sensitive soul, and the rational soul. Humans have a rational soul. The human soul incorporates the powers of the other kinds: Like the vegetative soul it can grow and nourish itself; like the sensitive soul it can experience sensations and move locally. The unique part of the human, rational soul is its ability to receive forms of other things and to compare them using the ''[[Nous#Aristotle|nous]]'' (intellect) and ''logos'' (reason).{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | pages=156–63}}
+
|-
   −
Aristotle's psychology, given in his treatise On the Soul (peri psychēs), posits three kinds of soul ("psyches"): the vegetative soul, the sensitive soul, and the rational soul. Humans have a rational soul. The human soul incorporates the powers of the other kinds: Like the vegetative soul it can grow and nourish itself; like the sensitive soul it can experience sensations and move locally. The unique part of the human, rational soul is its ability to receive forms of other things and to compare them using the nous (intellect) and logos (reason).
+
|Rudeness||Civility||Obsequiousness
   −
Aristotle的心理学,在他的论文《论灵魂》(peri psychēs)中,提出了三种灵魂("psyches"):植物性灵魂、敏感性灵魂和理性灵魂。人类有一个理性的灵魂。人类的灵魂融合了其他种类的力量。像植物性灵魂一样,它可以生长和滋养自己;像敏感的灵魂一样,它可以体验感觉和局部移动。人的理性灵魂的独特之处在于它能接受其他事物的形式,并能用nous(智力)和logos(理智)来比较它们。
+
|Cowardice||Courage||Rashness
   −
For Aristotle, the soul is the [[Hylomorphism#Body–soul hylomorphism|form]] of a living being. Because all beings are composites of form and matter, the form of living beings is that which endows them with what is specific to living beings, e.g. the ability to initiate movement (or in the case of plants, growth and chemical transformations, which Aristotle considers types of movement).{{sfn| Shields | 2016}} In contrast to earlier philosophers, but in accordance with the Egyptians, he placed the rational soul in the heart, rather than the brain.{{sfn| Mason | 1979 | p=45}} Notable is Aristotle's division of sensation and thought, which generally differed from the concepts of previous philosophers, with the exception of [[Alcmaeon of Croton|Alcmaeon]].{{sfn| Guthrie | 2010 | p=348}}
+
懦弱,勇气,鲁莽
   −
For Aristotle, the soul is the form of a living being. Because all beings are composites of form and matter, the form of living beings is that which endows them with what is specific to living beings, e.g. the ability to initiate movement (or in the case of plants, growth and chemical transformations, which Aristotle considers types of movement). In contrast to earlier philosophers, but in accordance with the Egyptians, he placed the rational soul in the heart, rather than the brain. Notable is Aristotle's division of sensation and thought, which generally differed from the concepts of previous philosophers, with the exception of Alcmaeon.
+
|-
   −
在Aristotle看来,灵魂是生命体的形式。因为所有的生命都是形式和物质的复合体,所以生命体的形式就是赋予生命体特有的东西,例如发起运动的能力(或者在植物的情况下,发起生长和化学转化,Aristotle认为这是运动的类型)。与早期的哲学家不同,但与埃及人一致,他把理性的灵魂放在心里,而不是大脑。值得注意的是亚里士多德对感觉和思维的划分,除阿尔克马翁Alcmaeon外,一般都与以前哲学家的概念不同。
+
|-
    +
|-
   −
====Memory====
+
|Cowardice||Courage||Rashness
记忆
     −
According to Aristotle in ''On the Soul'', memory is the ability to hold a perceived experience in the mind and to distinguish between the internal "appearance" and an occurrence in the past.{{sfn| Bloch | 2007 | p=12}} In other words, a memory is a mental picture ([[wikt:phantasm|phantasm]]) that can be recovered. Aristotle believed an impression is left on a semi-fluid bodily organ that undergoes several changes in order to make a memory. A memory occurs when [[stimulus (psychology)|stimuli]] such as sights or sounds are so complex that the nervous system cannot receive all the impressions at once. These changes are the same as those involved in the operations of sensation, Aristotelian '[[common sense]]', and thinking.{{sfn| Bloch | 2007 | p=61}}{{sfn| Carruthers | 2007 | p=16}}
+
|Insensibility||Self-control||Intemperance
   −
According to Aristotle in On the Soul, memory is the ability to hold a perceived experience in the mind and to distinguish between the internal "appearance" and an occurrence in the past. In other words, a memory is a mental picture (phantasm) that can be recovered. Aristotle believed an impression is left on a semi-fluid bodily organ that undergoes several changes in order to make a memory. A memory occurs when stimuli such as sights or sounds are so complex that the nervous system cannot receive all the impressions at once. These changes are the same as those involved in the operations of sensation, Aristotelian 'common sense', and thinking.
+
麻木不仁| | 自我控制 | | 放纵
   −
根据Aristotle在《论灵魂》一书中的观点,记忆是指将感知到的经验保存在脑海中,并将内部的 "表象 "与过去发生的事情区分开来的能力。换句话说,记忆是一种可以恢复的心理图景(幻象)。Aristotle认为,印象是在半流体的身体器官上留下的,经过几次变化,才能形成记忆。当景物或声音等刺激物非常复杂,以至于神经系统不能同时接受所有的印象时,就会产生记忆。这些变化与感觉、Aristotle的 "常识 "和思维的操作一样。
+
|-
   −
Aristotle uses the term 'memory' for the actual retaining of an experience in the impression that can develop from sensation, and for the intellectual anxiety that comes with the impression because it is formed at a particular time and processing specific contents. Memory is of the past, prediction is of the future, and sensation is of the present. Retrieval of impressions cannot be performed suddenly. A transitional channel is needed and located in our past experiences, both for our previous experience and present experience.{{sfn| Bloch | 2007 | p=25}}
+
|-
   −
Aristotle uses the term 'memory' for the actual retaining of an experience in the impression that can develop from sensation, and for the intellectual anxiety that comes with the impression because it is formed at a particular time and processing specific contents. Memory is of the past, prediction is of the future, and sensation is of the present. Retrieval of impressions cannot be performed suddenly. A transitional channel is needed and located in our past experiences, both for our previous experience and present experience.
+
|-
   −
Aristotle用 "记忆 "一词,是指在印象中实际保留一种经验,而这种经验可以从感觉中发展出来,同时,由于印象是在特定的时间和加工特定的内容中形成的,因此,这种印象会带来知识上的焦虑。记忆是过去的,预测是未来的,感觉是现在的。印象的检索不能突然进行。需要一个过渡通道,位于我们过去的经验中,既是我们以前的经验,也是现在的经验。
+
|Insensibility||Self-control||Intemperance
   −
Because Aristotle believes people receive all kinds of sense perceptions and perceive them as impressions, people are continually weaving together new impressions of experiences. To search for these impressions, people search the memory itself.{{sfn| Warren | 1921 | p=30}} Within the memory, if one experience is offered instead of a specific memory, that person will reject this experience until they find what they are looking for. Recollection occurs when one retrieved experience naturally follows another. If the chain of "images" is needed, one memory will stimulate the next. When people recall experiences, they stimulate certain previous experiences until they reach the one that is needed.{{sfn| Warren | 1921 | p=25}} Recollection is thus the self-directed activity of retrieving the information stored in a memory impression.{{sfn| Carruthers | 2007 | p=19}} Only humans can remember impressions of intellectual activity, such as numbers and words. Animals that have perception of time can retrieve memories of their past observations. Remembering involves only perception of the things remembered and of the time passed.{{sfn| Warren | 1921 | p=296}}
+
|Sarcasm||Sincerity||Boastfulness
   −
Because Aristotle believes people receive all kinds of sense perceptions and perceive them as impressions, people are continually weaving together new impressions of experiences. To search for these impressions, people search the memory itself. Within the memory, if one experience is offered instead of a specific memory, that person will reject this experience until they find what they are looking for. Recollection occurs when one retrieved experience naturally follows another. If the chain of "images" is needed, one memory will stimulate the next. When people recall experiences, they stimulate certain previous experiences until they reach the one that is needed. Recollection is thus the self-directed activity of retrieving the information stored in a memory impression. Only humans can remember impressions of intellectual activity, such as numbers and words. Animals that have perception of time can retrieve memories of their past observations. Remembering involves only perception of the things remembered and of the time passed.
+
讽刺 真诚 自夸
   −
因为Aristotle认为,人们接受各种感觉知觉,并把它们当作印象来认识,所以人们不断地把新的经验印象编织在一起。为了寻找这些印象,人们搜索记忆本身。在记忆中,如果提供一种经验而不是特定的记忆,那么这个人就会拒绝这种经验,直到找到他们所要找的东西。当一个检索到的经验自然而然地跟在另一个经验后面时,就会出现回忆。如果需要 "图像 "的链条,一个记忆会刺激下一个记忆。当人们回忆经验时,他们会刺激以前的某些经验,直到达到需要的经验。因此,回忆是检索存储在记忆印象中的信息的自发活动。只有人类能记住数字、文字等智力活动的印象。有时间知觉的动物可以检索过去观察的记忆。记忆只涉及对所记事物和所过时间的感知。
+
|-
   −
[[File:Aristotle Senses Perception Memory Dreams Action.svg | thumb | upright=2.3 | Senses, perception, memory, dreams, action in Aristotle's psychology. Impressions are stored in the [[sensorium]] (the heart), linked by his [[laws of association]] (similarity, contrast, and [[Contiguity (psychology)|contiguity]]).]]
+
|-
   −
Senses, perception, memory, dreams, action in Aristotle's psychology. Impressions are stored in the sensorium (the heart), linked by his laws of association (similarity, contrast, and contiguity).
+
|-
   −
Aristotle心理学中的感觉、知觉、记忆、梦、行动。印象被储存在感观(心)中,由他的联想法则(相似性、对比性和相邻性)联系起来。
+
|Sarcasm||Sincerity||Boastfulness
   −
Aristotle believed the chain of thought, which ends in recollection of certain impressions, was connected systematically in relationships such as similarity, contrast, and [[Contiguity (psychology)|contiguity]], described in his [[laws of association]]. Aristotle believed that past experiences are hidden within the mind. A force operates to awaken the hidden material to bring up the actual experience. According to Aristotle, association is the power innate in a mental state, which operates upon the unexpressed remains of former experiences, allowing them to rise and be recalled.{{sfn| Warren | 1921 | p=259}}{{sfn | Sorabji | 2006 | p=54}}
+
|Boorishness||Wit||Buffoonery
 +
粗鲁 机智 滑稽
 +
|Boorishness||Wit||Buffoonery
   −
Aristotle believed the chain of thought, which ends in recollection of certain impressions, was connected systematically in relationships such as similarity, contrast, and contiguity, described in his laws of association. Aristotle believed that past experiences are hidden within the mind. A force operates to awaken the hidden material to bring up the actual experience. According to Aristotle, association is the power innate in a mental state, which operates upon the unexpressed remains of former experiences, allowing them to rise and be recalled.
+
|-
   −
Aristotle认为,以回忆某些印象为终结的思维链,在他的联想定律中描述的相似性、对比性和相邻性等关系中,是有系统地连接起来的。Aristotle认为,过去的经验是隐藏在头脑中的。一种力量的运作唤醒了隐藏的材料,使实际的经验浮现出来。根据Aristotle的观点,联想是一种精神状态中与生俱来的力量,它作用于过去经验中未被表达的残余,使它们得以升起并被唤起。
+
|-
    +
|-
   −
====Dreams====
+
|Boorishness||Wit||Buffoonery
     −
{{see | Dream#Classical history}}
+
|Shamelessness||Modesty||Shyness
   −
Aristotle describes sleep in ''On Sleep and Wakefulness''.{{sfn| Holowchak | 1996 | pp=405–23}} Sleep takes place as a result of overuse of the senses{{sfn| Shute | 1941 | pages=115–18}} or of digestion,{{sfn| Holowchak | 1996 | pp=405–23}} so it is vital to the body.{{sfn| Shute | 1941 | pages=115–18}} While a person is asleep, the critical activities, which include thinking, sensing, recalling and remembering, do not function as they do during wakefulness. Since a person cannot sense during sleep they can not have desire, which is the result of sensation. However, the senses are able to work during sleep,{{sfn| Shute | 1941 | pages=115–18}} albeit differently,{{sfn| Holowchak | 1996 | pp=405–23}} unless they are weary.{{sfn| Shute | 1941 | pages=115–18}}
+
无耻 谦虚,羞怯
   −
Aristotle describes sleep in On Sleep and Wakefulness. Sleep takes place as a result of overuse of the senses or of digestion, so it is vital to the body. While a person is asleep, the critical activities, which include thinking, sensing, recalling and remembering, do not function as they do during wakefulness. Since a person cannot sense during sleep they can not have desire, which is the result of sensation. However, the senses are able to work during sleep, albeit differently, unless they are weary.
+
|-
   −
Aristotle在《论睡眠与觉醒》中对睡眠进行了描述。睡眠的发生是感官的过度使用或消化的结果,所以它对身体至关重要。当一个人处于睡眠状态时,包括思考、感知、回忆和记忆在内的关键活动,不会像清醒时那样发挥作用。由于人在睡眠中不能感知,他们就不能有欲望,而欲望是感觉的结果。然而,感官在睡眠期间能够工作,尽管方式不同,除非它们疲惫不堪。
+
|-
   −
Dreams do not involve actually sensing a stimulus. In dreams, sensation is still involved, but in an altered manner.{{sfn| Shute | 1941 | pages=115–18}} Aristotle explains that when a person stares at a moving stimulus such as the waves in a body of water, and then look away, the next thing they look at appears to have a wavelike motion. When a person perceives a stimulus and the stimulus is no longer the focus of their attention, it leaves an impression.{{sfn| Holowchak | 1996 | pp=405–23}} When the body is awake and the senses are functioning properly, a person constantly encounters new stimuli to sense and so the impressions of previously perceived stimuli are ignored.{{sfn| Shute | 1941 | pages=115–18}} However, during sleep the impressions made throughout the day are noticed as there are no new distracting sensory experiences.{{sfn| Holowchak | 1996 | pp=405–23}} So, dreams result from these lasting impressions. Since impressions are all that are left and not the exact stimuli, dreams do not resemble the actual waking experience.{{sfn| Modrak | 2009 | pp=169–81}} During sleep, a person is in an altered state of mind. Aristotle compares a sleeping person to a person who is overtaken by strong feelings toward a stimulus. For example, a person who has a strong infatuation with someone may begin to think they see that person everywhere because they are so overtaken by their feelings. Since a person sleeping is in a suggestible state and unable to make judgements, they become easily deceived by what appears in their dreams, like the infatuated person.{{sfn| Holowchak | 1996 | pp=405–23}} This leads the person to believe the dream is real, even when the dreams are absurd in nature.{{sfn| Holowchak | 1996 | pp=405–23}} In ''De Anima'' iii 3, Aristotle ascribes the ability to create, to store, and to recall images in the absence of perception to the faculty of imagination, ''phantasia''.{{sfn| Shields | 2016}}
+
|-
   −
Dreams do not involve actually sensing a stimulus. In dreams, sensation is still involved, but in an altered manner. Aristotle explains that when a person stares at a moving stimulus such as the waves in a body of water, and then look away, the next thing they look at appears to have a wavelike motion. When a person perceives a stimulus and the stimulus is no longer the focus of their attention, it leaves an impression. When the body is awake and the senses are functioning properly, a person constantly encounters new stimuli to sense and so the impressions of previously perceived stimuli are ignored. However, during sleep the impressions made throughout the day are noticed as there are no new distracting sensory experiences. So, dreams result from these lasting impressions. Since impressions are all that are left and not the exact stimuli, dreams do not resemble the actual waking experience. During sleep, a person is in an altered state of mind. Aristotle compares a sleeping person to a person who is overtaken by strong feelings toward a stimulus. For example, a person who has a strong infatuation with someone may begin to think they see that person everywhere because they are so overtaken by their feelings. Since a person sleeping is in a suggestible state and unable to make judgements, they become easily deceived by what appears in their dreams, like the infatuated person. This leads the person to believe the dream is real, even when the dreams are absurd in nature. In De Anima iii 3, Aristotle ascribes the ability to create, to store, and to recall images in the absence of perception to the faculty of imagination, phantasia.
+
|Shamelessness||Modesty||Shyness
   −
梦并不涉及到实际的感觉刺激。在梦中,感觉仍然参与其中,但以一种改变的方式。Aristotle解释说,当一个人盯着一个移动的刺激物,如水体中的波浪,然后把目光移开,他们所看的下一个东西就会出现波浪般的运动。当一个人感知到一个刺激物,而这个刺激物不再是他们注意的焦点时,就会留下印象。当身体清醒,感官功能正常时,人不断地遇到新的刺激物来感知,所以以前感知到的刺激物的印象就被忽略了。但是,在睡眠中,由于没有新的干扰感官体验,所以一整天的印象都会被注意到。所以,梦是这些持久印象的结果。由于留下的只是印象,而不是确切的刺激,所以梦境与实际的清醒经验并不相似。在睡眠中,人的精神状态发生了改变。亚里士多德把睡眠中的人比作一个对刺激物产生强烈感情的人。例如,一个对某人有强烈迷恋的人可能会开始认为他们到处都能看到那个人,因为他们被自己的感情冲昏了头脑。由于睡眠中的人处于易受暗示的状态,无法做出判断,所以很容易被梦中出现的东西所欺骗,就像那个痴情的人一样。这使人相信梦境是真实的,即使梦境的本质是荒谬的。在《德阿尼玛三世》3中,Aristotle把在没有知觉的情况下创造、储存和回忆形象的能力归结为想象力的能力,即幻觉。
+
|Callousness||Just resentment||Spitefulness
    +
冷漠,怨恨,恶意
   −
One component of Aristotle's theory of dreams disagrees with previously held beliefs. He claimed that dreams are not foretelling and not sent by a divine being. Aristotle reasoned naturalistically that instances in which dreams do resemble future events are simply coincidences.{{sfn| Webb | 1990 | pages=174–84}} Aristotle claimed that a dream is first established by the fact that the person is asleep when they experience it. If a person had an image appear for a moment after waking up or if they see something in the dark it is not considered a dream because they were awake when it occurred. Secondly, any sensory experience that is perceived while a person is asleep does not qualify as part of a dream. For example, if, while a person is sleeping, a door shuts and in their dream they hear a door is shut, this sensory experience is not part of the dream. Lastly, the images of dreams must be a result of lasting impressions of waking sensory experiences.{{sfn| Modrak | 2009 | pp=169–81}}
+
|-
   −
One component of Aristotle's theory of dreams disagrees with previously held beliefs. He claimed that dreams are not foretelling and not sent by a divine being. Aristotle reasoned naturalistically that instances in which dreams do resemble future events are simply coincidences. Aristotle claimed that a dream is first established by the fact that the person is asleep when they experience it. If a person had an image appear for a moment after waking up or if they see something in the dark it is not considered a dream because they were awake when it occurred. Secondly, any sensory experience that is perceived while a person is asleep does not qualify as part of a dream. For example, if, while a person is sleeping, a door shuts and in their dream they hear a door is shut, this sensory experience is not part of the dream. Lastly, the images of dreams must be a result of lasting impressions of waking sensory experiences.
+
|-
   −
Aristotle的梦境理论中有一个内容与以前的信念不一致。他声称,梦不是预言,也不是由神灵发出的。Aristotle从自然主义的角度推理,梦境确实与未来事件相似的事例只是巧合。Aristotle称,梦的成立首先要看人在经历梦的时候是否睡着了。如果一个人在醒来后有一个影像出现了一会儿,或者他们在黑暗中看到了一些东西,就不认为是梦,因为当梦发生时他们是清醒的。其次,任何在人睡觉时被感知到的感官体验都不能算作梦的一部分。例如,如果一个人在睡觉的时候,一扇门关上了,而在梦中他们听到门被关上了,这种感官体验不属于梦的一部分。最后,梦中的影像必须是清醒的感官体验的持久印象的结果。
+
|-
    +
|Callousness||Just resentment||Spitefulness
   −
==Practical philosophy==
+
|Pettiness||Generosity||Vulgarity
实践哲学
  −
Aristotle's practical philosophy covers areas such as ethics, politics, economics, and rhetoric.{{sfn| Wildberg | 2016}}
     −
Aristotle's practical philosophy covers areas such as ethics, politics, economics, and rhetoric.
+
朴素慷慨粗俗
   −
Aristotle的实践哲学涵盖了伦理学、政治学、经济学和修辞学等领域。
+
|-
   −
{| class="wikitable floatright" align=right style="font-size: 80%;"
+
|-
   −
{ | class = “ wikitable floatright” align = right style = “ font-size: 80% ;
+
|-
   −
|+ Virtues and their accompanying vices
+
|Pettiness||Generosity||Vulgarity
   −
| + 美德及伴随的恶习
+
|Meanness||Liberality||Wastefulness
   −
{| class="wikitable floatright" align=right style="font-size: 80%;"
+
吝啬自由浪费
   −
! Too little !! Virtuous mean !! Too much
+
|-
   −
!太少了 均值 太多了
+
|}
   −
|+ Virtues and their accompanying vices{{sfn|Aristotle (384–322 B.C.E.)}}
+
|}
   −
|-
+
|Meanness||Liberality||Wastefulness
   −
|-
+
|}
   −
! Too little !! Virtuous mean !! Too much
     −
|Humbleness||High-mindedness||Vainglory
  −
谦虚 胸怀大志 虚荣
  −
|Humbleness||High-mindedness||Vainglory
     −
|-
+
===Just war theory===
 +
公理战役理论
 +
Aristotelian [[just war theory]] is not well regarded in the present day, especially his view that warfare was justified to enslave "natural slaves". In Aristotelian philosophy, the abolition of what he considers "[[natural slavery]]" would undermine civic [[freedom]]. The pursuit of freedom is inseparable from pursuing mastery over "those who deserve to be slaves". According to ''The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle's Politics'' the targets of this aggressive warfare were non-Greeks, noting Aristotle's view that "our poets say 'it is proper for Greeks to rule non-Greeks'".{{sfn|Deslauriers|Destrée|2013|pp=157-162}}
   −
|-
+
Aristotelian just war theory is not well regarded in the present day, especially his view that warfare was justified to enslave "natural slaves". In Aristotelian philosophy, the abolition of what he considers "natural slavery" would undermine civic freedom. The pursuit of freedom is inseparable from pursuing mastery over "those who deserve to be slaves". According to The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle's Politics the targets of this aggressive warfare were non-Greeks, noting Aristotle's view that "our poets say 'it is proper for Greeks to rule non-Greeks'".
   −
|-
+
Aristotle的公理战役理论在今天并不受欢迎,特别是他认为战争是为了奴役 "自然奴隶 "而进行的正义战争。在Aristotle的哲学中,他认为“自然奴隶制”的废除会破坏公民自由。追求自由与追求掌握 "应该成为奴隶的人 "是分不开的。根据《剑桥亚里士多德政治指南》,这种侵略战争的对象是非希腊人,指出Aristotle的观点是 "我们的诗人说'希腊人统治非希腊人是合适的'"。
   −
|Humbleness||High-mindedness||Vainglory
+
Aristotle generally has a favourable opinion of war, extolling it as a chance for [[virtue]] and writing that "the leisure that accompanies peace" tends to make people "arrogant". War to "avoid becoming enslaved to others" is justified as self-defense. He writes that war "compels people to be just and temperate", however, in order to be just "war must be chosen for the sake of peace" (with the exception of wars of aggression discussed above).{{sfn|Deslauriers|Destrée|2013|pp=157-162}}
   −
|Lack of purpose||Right ambition||Over-ambition
+
Aristotle generally has a favourable opinion of war, extolling it as a chance for virtue and writing that "the leisure that accompanies peace" tends to make people "arrogant". War to "avoid becoming enslaved to others" is justified as self-defense. He writes that war "compels people to be just and temperate", however, in order to be just "war must be chosen for the sake of peace" (with the exception of wars of aggression discussed above).
   −
缺乏目标 正确的野心 过于野心勃勃
+
Aristotle一般对战争持赞成态度,赞美战争是美德的机会,并写道:"伴随和平而来的闲暇 "容易使人 "傲慢"。为了 "避免成为他人的奴隶 "而进行的战争,是正当的自卫。他写道,战争 "迫使人们变得公正和节制",然而,为了公正,"必须为了和平而选择战争"(上文讨论的侵略战争除外)。
   −
|-
     −
|-
+
===Ethics===
 +
伦理
   −
|-
     −
|Lack of purpose||Right ambition||Over-ambition
     −
|Spiritlessness||Good temper||Irascibility
+
{{main | Aristotelian ethics}}
   −
无精打采 脾气好 脾气暴躁
+
Aristotle considered ethics to be a practical rather than theoretical study, i.e., one aimed at becoming good and doing good rather than knowing for its own sake. He wrote several treatises on ethics, including most notably, the ''[[Nicomachean Ethics]]''.{{sfn| Kraut | 2001}}
   −
|-
+
Aristotle considered ethics to be a practical rather than theoretical study, i.e., one aimed at becoming good and doing good rather than knowing for its own sake. He wrote several treatises on ethics, including most notably, the Nicomachean Ethics.
   −
|-
+
Aristotle认为伦理学是一门实践性的而非理论性的研究,即旨在向善和行善,而不是为了认识而认识。他写了几篇伦理学论文,其中最著名的是《尼各马可伦理学》。
   −
|-
+
Aristotle taught that virtue has to do with the proper function (''ergon'') of a thing. An eye is only a good eye in so much as it can see, because the proper function of an eye is sight. Aristotle reasoned that humans must have a function specific to humans, and that this function must be an activity of the ''[[De Anima|psuchē]]'' (''soul'') in accordance with reason (''[[logos]]''). Aristotle identified such an optimum activity (the virtuous mean, between the accompanying vices of excess or deficiency{{sfn| Aristotle (384–322 B.C.E.)}}) of the soul as the aim of all human deliberate action, ''[[eudaimonia]]'', generally translated as "happiness" or sometimes "well being". To have the potential of ever being happy in this way necessarily requires a good character (''ēthikē'' ''[[arete (moral virtue)|aretē]]''), often translated as moral or ethical virtue or excellence.{{sfn| Nicomachean Ethics | ps= &nbsp;Book I. See for example chapter 7.}}
   −
|Spiritlessness||Good temper||Irascibility
+
Aristotle taught that virtue has to do with the proper function (ergon) of a thing. An eye is only a good eye in so much as it can see, because the proper function of an eye is sight. Aristotle reasoned that humans must have a function specific to humans, and that this function must be an activity of the psuchē (soul) in accordance with reason (logos). Aristotle identified such an optimum activity (the virtuous mean, between the accompanying vices of excess or deficiency) of the soul as the aim of all human deliberate action, eudaimonia, generally translated as "happiness" or sometimes "well being". To have the potential of ever being happy in this way necessarily requires a good character (ēthikē aretē), often translated as moral or ethical virtue or excellence.
   −
|Rudeness||Civility||Obsequiousness
+
Aristotle教导说,美德与事物的适当功能(ergon)有关。一只眼睛只有在它能看见的范围内才是一只好眼睛,因为眼睛的适当功能是视觉。Aristotle推理说,人必须有一种人类特有的功能,这种功能必须是符合理性(logos)的psuchē(灵魂)的活动。Aristotle把灵魂的这种最佳活动(在过剩或不足的与之相伴的恶习之间的良性平均)确定为人类一切刻意行动的目标,即eudaimonia,一般译为 "幸福",有时也译为 "安康"。要想以这种方式拥有永远幸福的潜力,必然需要良好的品格(ēthikē aretē),通常被译为道德或伦理的美德或卓越。
   −
粗鲁,礼貌,谄媚
+
Aristotle taught that to achieve a virtuous and potentially happy character requires a first stage of having the fortune to be habituated not deliberately, but by teachers, and experience, leading to a later stage in which one consciously chooses to do the best things. When the best people come to live life this way their practical wisdom (''[[phronesis]]'') and their intellect (''[[nous]]'') can develop with each other towards the highest possible human virtue, the wisdom of an accomplished theoretical or speculative thinker, or in other words, a philosopher.{{sfn| Nicomachean Ethics | p= Book VI}}
   −
|-
+
Aristotle taught that to achieve a virtuous and potentially happy character requires a first stage of having the fortune to be habituated not deliberately, but by teachers, and experience, leading to a later stage in which one consciously chooses to do the best things. When the best people come to live life this way their practical wisdom (phronesis) and their intellect (nous) can develop with each other towards the highest possible human virtue, the wisdom of an accomplished theoretical or speculative thinker, or in other words, a philosopher.
   −
|-
+
Aristotle教导说,要达到一种有德行的、潜在的幸福的品格,需要有一个第一阶段的幸运,不是刻意的,而是通过老师、经验的熏陶,导致后期自觉地选择做最好的事情。当最优秀的人以这种方式来生活时,他们的实践智慧(实践理性)和他们的智力(理性)可以相互发展,朝着人类最高的美德,即一个有成就的理论或投机思想家的智慧,或者换句话说,一个哲学家的智慧发展。
   −
|-
     −
|Rudeness||Civility||Obsequiousness
+
===Politics===
 +
政治
   −
|Cowardice||Courage||Rashness
     −
懦弱,勇气,鲁莽
     −
|-
+
{{main | Politics (Aristotle)}}
   −
|-
+
In addition to his works on ethics, which address the individual, Aristotle addressed the city in his work titled ''[[Politics (Aristotle)|Politics]]''. Aristotle considered the city to be a natural community. Moreover, he considered the city to be prior in importance to the family which in turn is prior to the individual, "for the whole must of necessity be prior to the part".{{sfn| Politics | pp=1253a19–24}} He famously stated that "man is by nature a political animal" and argued that humanity's defining factor among others in the animal kingdom is its rationality.{{sfn| Aristotle | 2009 | pages=320–21}} Aristotle conceived of politics as being like an organism rather than like a machine, and as a collection of parts none of which can exist without the others. Aristotle's conception of the city is organic, and he is considered one of the first to conceive of the city in this manner.{{sfn| Ebenstein | Ebenstein | 2002 | page=59}}
   −
|-
+
In addition to his works on ethics, which address the individual, Aristotle addressed the city in his work titled Politics. Aristotle considered the city to be a natural community. Moreover, he considered the city to be prior in importance to the family which in turn is prior to the individual, "for the whole must of necessity be prior to the part". He famously stated that "man is by nature a political animal" and argued that humanity's defining factor among others in the animal kingdom is its rationality. Aristotle conceived of politics as being like an organism rather than like a machine, and as a collection of parts none of which can exist without the others. Aristotle's conception of the city is organic, and he is considered one of the first to conceive of the city in this manner.
   −
|Cowardice||Courage||Rashness
+
Aristotle除了在他的伦理学著作中论述个人外,还在他题为《政治学》的著作中论述了城市。Aristotle认为城市是一个自然共同体。此外,他认为城市的重要性高于家庭,而家庭又高于个人,"因为整体必然高于部分"。他有句名言:"人在本质上是一种政治动物",认为人类在动物界其他动物中的决定性因素是其理性。Aristotle把政治设想为像一个有机体而不是像一台机器,是一个部分的集合,其中任何一个部分都不能离开其他部分而存在。Aristotle的城市概念是有机的,他被认为是最早以这种方式设想城市的人之一。
   −
|Insensibility||Self-control||Intemperance
+
[[File:Aristotle's constitutions.svg | thumb|upright=1.7 | Aristotle's classifications of political constitutions]]
   −
麻木不仁| | 自我控制 | | 放纵
+
Aristotle's classifications of political constitutions
   −
|-
+
Aristotle对政治宪法的分类
   −
|-
+
The common modern understanding of a political community as a modern state is quite different from Aristotle's understanding. Although he was aware of the existence and potential of larger empires, the natural community according to Aristotle was the city (''[[polis]]'') which functions as a political "community" or "partnership" (''koinōnia'')<!-- (1252a1) -->. The aim of the city is not just to avoid injustice or for economic stability<!-- (1280b29–31) -->, but rather to allow at least some citizens the possibility to live a good life, and to perform beautiful acts: "The political partnership must be regarded, therefore, as being for the sake of noble actions, not for the sake of living together<!-- (1281a1–3) -->." This is distinguished from modern approaches, beginning with [[social contract]] theory, according to which individuals leave the [[state of nature]] because of "fear of violent death" or its "inconveniences."{{efn-ua | For a different reading of social and economic processes in the ''Nicomachean Ethics'' and ''Politics'' see Polanyi, Karl (1957) "Aristotle Discovers the Economy" in ''Primitive, Archaic and Modern Economies: Essays of Karl Polanyi'' ed. G. Dalton, Boston 1971, 78–115.}}
   −
|-
+
The common modern understanding of a political community as a modern state is quite different from Aristotle's understanding. Although he was aware of the existence and potential of larger empires, the natural community according to Aristotle was the city (polis) which functions as a political "community" or "partnership" (koinōnia). The aim of the city is not just to avoid injustice or for economic stability, but rather to allow at least some citizens the possibility to live a good life, and to perform beautiful acts: "The political partnership must be regarded, therefore, as being for the sake of noble actions, not for the sake of living together." This is distinguished from modern approaches, beginning with social contract theory, according to which individuals leave the state of nature because of "fear of violent death" or its "inconveniences."
   −
|Insensibility||Self-control||Intemperance
+
现代人对作为现代国家的政治共同体的普遍理解与Aristotle的理解大相径庭。尽管他意识到更大帝国的存在和潜力,但Aristotle认为的自然共同体是作为政治 "共同体 "或 "伙伴关系"(koinōnia)的城市(城邦)。城市的目的不仅仅是为了避免不公正,也不仅仅是为了经济稳定,而是至少要让一些公民有可能过上好的生活,有可能做出美好的行为。"因此,政治伙伴关系必须被视为是为了高尚的行为,而不是为了共同生活。" 这有别于从社会契约论开始的现代方法,根据这种方法,个人因为 "害怕暴力死亡 "或其 "不便 "而离开自然状态。
   −
|Sarcasm||Sincerity||Boastfulness
     −
讽刺 真诚 自夸
+
In ''[[Protrepticus (Aristotle)|Protrepticus]]'', the character 'Aristotle' states:{{sfn| Hutchinson | Johnson | 2015 | p=22}}
   −
|-
+
In Protrepticus, the character 'Aristotle' states:
   −
|-
+
在《 劝勉篇 》中,Aristotle这样写道:
   −
|-
     −
|Sarcasm||Sincerity||Boastfulness
     −
|Boorishness||Wit||Buffoonery
+
{{quote | For we all agree that the most excellent man should rule, i.e., the supreme by nature, and that the law rules and alone is authoritative; but the law is a kind of intelligence, i.e. a discourse based on intelligence. And again, what standard do we have, what criterion of good things, that is more precise than the intelligent man? For all that this man will choose, if the choice is based on his knowledge, are good things and their contraries are bad. And since everybody chooses most of all what conforms to their own proper dispositions (a just man choosing to live justly, a man with bravery to live bravely, likewise a self-controlled man to live with self-control), it is clear that the intelligent man will choose most of all to be intelligent; for this is the function of that capacity. Hence it's evident that, according to the most authoritative judgment, intelligence is supreme among goods.{{sfn| Hutchinson | Johnson | 2015 | p=22}}}}
粗鲁 机智 滑稽
  −
|Boorishness||Wit||Buffoonery
     −
|-
+
因为我们都认为,最优秀的人应该是统治者,也就是本质上的最高者,法律的统治,只有法律才是权威的;但法律是一种智慧,也就是以智慧为基础的话语。再如,我们有什么标准,有什么好东西的标准,比聪明人更精确呢?因为这个人会选择的所有东西,如果是基于他的知识而选择的,都是好东西,而它们的反面是坏东西。既然每个人都会选择最符合自己适当性情的东西(一个公正的人选择公正地生活,一个勇敢的人选择勇敢地生活,同样,一个自制的人选择自制地生活),那么很明显,聪明的人最会选择聪明的东西;因为这是这种能力的功能。因此,很明显,根据最权威的判断,智慧在商品中是至高无上的。
   −
|-
     −
|-
+
===Economics===
 +
经济学
   −
|Boorishness||Wit||Buffoonery
+
{{main | Politics (Aristotle)}}
   −
|Shamelessness||Modesty||Shyness
+
Aristotle made substantial contributions to [[economics|economic thought]], especially to thought in the Middle Ages.{{sfn| Robbins | 2000 | pages=20–24}} In ''[[Politics (Aristotle)|Politics]]'', Aristotle addresses the city, [[property]], and [[trade]]. His response to criticisms of [[private property]], in [[Lionel Robbins]]'s view, anticipated later proponents of private property among philosophers and economists, as it related to the overall [[utility]] of social arrangements.{{sfn| Robbins | 2000 | pages=20–24}} Aristotle believed that although communal arrangements may seem beneficial to society, and that although private property is often blamed for social strife, such evils in fact come from [[human nature]]. In ''Politics'', Aristotle offers one of the earliest accounts of the origin of [[money]].{{sfn| Robbins | 2000 | pages=20–24}} Money came into use because people became dependent on one another, importing what they needed and exporting the surplus. For the sake of convenience, people then agreed to deal in something that is intrinsically useful and easily applicable, such as iron or [[silver]].{{sfn| Aristotle | 1948 | pages=16–28}}
   −
无耻 谦虚,羞怯
+
Aristotle made substantial contributions to economic thought, especially to thought in the Middle Ages. In Politics, Aristotle addresses the city, property, and trade. His response to criticisms of private property, in Lionel Robbins's view, anticipated later proponents of private property among philosophers and economists, as it related to the overall utility of social arrangements. Aristotle believed that although communal arrangements may seem beneficial to society, and that although private property is often blamed for social strife, such evils in fact come from human nature. In Politics, Aristotle offers one of the earliest accounts of the origin of money. Money came into use because people became dependent on one another, importing what they needed and exporting the surplus. For the sake of convenience, people then agreed to deal in something that is intrinsically useful and easily applicable, such as iron or silver.
   −
|-
+
Aristotle对经济思想,特别是对中世纪的思想做出了实质性的贡献。在《政治学》中,Aristotle论述了城市、财产和贸易问题。在莱昂内尔•罗宾斯Lionel Robbins看来,他对私有财产批评的回应,预见到了后来哲学家和经济学家中私有财产的支持者,因为它关系到社会安排的整体效用。Aristotle认为,虽然公有制安排看似对社会有益,虽然私有财产常常被指责为社会纷争的原因,但这种弊端其实来自于人性。在《政治学》中,Aristotle对货币的起源提出了一个最早的说法。货币之所以会被使用,是因为人们开始相互依赖,进口自己需要的东西,出口多余的东西。为了方便起见,人们便同意用铁或银等本质上有用且容易适用的东西进行交易。
   −
|-
     −
|-
+
Aristotle's discussions on [[retail]] and [[interest]] was a major influence on economic thought in the Middle Ages. He had a low opinion of retail, believing that contrary to using money to procure things one needs in managing the household, retail trade seeks to make a [[profit (economics)|profit]]. It thus uses goods as a means to an end, rather than as an end unto itself. He believed that retail trade was in this way unnatural. Similarly, Aristotle considered making a profit through interest unnatural, as it makes a gain out of the money itself, and not from its use.{{sfn| Aristotle | 1948 | pages=16–28}}
   −
|Shamelessness||Modesty||Shyness
+
Aristotle's discussions on retail and interest was a major influence on economic thought in the Middle Ages. He had a low opinion of retail, believing that contrary to using money to procure things one needs in managing the household, retail trade seeks to make a profit. It thus uses goods as a means to an end, rather than as an end unto itself. He believed that retail trade was in this way unnatural. Similarly, Aristotle considered making a profit through interest unnatural, as it makes a gain out of the money itself, and not from its use.
   −
|Callousness||Just resentment||Spitefulness
+
Aristotle关于零售和利息的讨论对中世纪的经济思想产生了重大影响。他不看好零售业,认为零售业与用金钱来采购自己管理家庭所需的东西相反,零售业追求的是利润。因此,它把商品作为达到目的的手段,而不是作为目的本身。他认为,零售贸易在这种方式上是不自然的。同样,Aristotle认为,通过利息获利是不自然的,因为它从货币本身而不是从货币的使用中获得收益。
   −
冷漠,怨恨,恶意
+
Aristotle gave a summary of the function of money that was perhaps remarkably precocious for his time. He wrote that because it is impossible to determine the value of every good through a count of the number of other goods it is worth, the necessity arises of a single universal standard of measurement. Money thus allows for the association of different goods and makes them "commensurable".{{sfn| Aristotle | 1948 | pages=16–28}} He goes on to state that money is also useful for future exchange, making it a sort of security. That is, "if we do not want a thing now, we shall be able to get it when we do want it".{{sfn| Aristotle | 1948 | pages=16–28}}
   −
|-
+
Aristotle gave a summary of the function of money that was perhaps remarkably precocious for his time. He wrote that because it is impossible to determine the value of every good through a count of the number of other goods it is worth, the necessity arises of a single universal standard of measurement. Money thus allows for the association of different goods and makes them "commensurable". He goes on to state that money is also useful for future exchange, making it a sort of security. That is, "if we do not want a thing now, we shall be able to get it when we do want it".
   −
|-
+
Aristotle总结了货币的功能,对于他那个时代来说,这个概念可能是非常早熟的。他写道,由于不可能通过计算每件商品的价值来确定它的价值,因此有必要制定一个统一的衡量标准。因此,货币可以把不同的商品联系起来,使它们 "可通约"。他接着说,货币对于未来的交换也是有用的,使它成为一种保障。也就是说,"如果我们现在不想要一件东西,那么当我们想要的时候,我们就能够得到它"。
   −
|-
     −
|Callousness||Just resentment||Spitefulness
     −
|Pettiness||Generosity||Vulgarity
     −
朴素慷慨粗俗
     −
|-
     −
|-
+
===Rhetoric and poetics===
 +
修辞学和诗学
   −
|-
+
[[File:Bénigne Gagneraux, The Blind Oedipus Commending his Children to the Gods.jpg | thumb | upright=1.3 | ''The Blind Oedipus Commending his Children to the Gods'' (1784) by [[Bénigne Gagneraux]]. In his ''[[Poetics (Aristotle)|Poetics]]'', Aristotle uses the tragedy ''[[Oedipus Rex|Oedipus Tyrannus]]'' by [[Sophocles]] as an example of how the perfect tragedy should be structured, with a generally good protagonist who starts the play prosperous, but loses everything through some ''[[hamartia]]'' (fault).{{sfn| Kaufmann | 1968 | pages=56–60}}]]
   −
|Pettiness||Generosity||Vulgarity
+
The Blind Oedipus Commending his Children to the Gods (1784) by Bénigne Gagneraux. In his Poetics, Aristotle uses the tragedy Oedipus Tyrannus by Sophocles as an example of how the perfect tragedy should be structured, with a generally good protagonist who starts the play prosperous, but loses everything through some hamartia (fault).
   −
|Meanness||Liberality||Wastefulness
+
《失明的俄狄浦斯向神明夸奖他的孩子们》(1784年),作者是贝尼涅•加格纳罗Bénigne Gagneraux。在他的《诗学》中,Aristotle以索福克勒斯Sophocles的悲剧《俄狄浦斯——暴君》为例,说明完美的悲剧应该如何结构,剧中的主人公一般都是好的,他在剧中一开始很繁荣,但由于一些过失而失去了一切。
   −
吝啬自由浪费
     −
|-
+
{{main | Rhetoric (Aristotle) | Poetics (Aristotle)}}
   −
|}
+
Aristotle's ''Rhetoric'' proposes that a speaker can use three basic kinds of appeals to persuade his audience: ''[[ethos]]'' (an appeal to the speaker's character), ''[[pathos]]'' (an appeal to the audience's emotion), and ''[[logos]]'' (an appeal to logical reasoning).{{sfn| Garver | 1994 | pages=109–10}} He also categorizes rhetoric into three genres: [[epideictic]] (ceremonial speeches dealing with praise or blame), [[Forensic rhetoric|forensic]] (judicial speeches over guilt or innocence), and [[Deliberative rhetoric|deliberative]] (speeches calling on an audience to make a decision on an issue).{{sfn| Rorty | 1996 | pages=3–7}} Aristotle also outlines two kinds of rhetorical [[Proof (truth)|proofs]]: ''[[enthymeme]]'' (proof by [[syllogism]]) and ''[[paradeigma]]'' (proof by example).{{sfn| Grimaldi | 1998 | p=71}}
   −
|}
+
Aristotle's Rhetoric proposes that a speaker can use three basic kinds of appeals to persuade his audience: ethos (an appeal to the speaker's character), pathos (an appeal to the audience's emotion), and logos (an appeal to logical reasoning). He also categorizes rhetoric into three genres: epideictic (ceremonial speeches dealing with praise or blame), forensic (judicial speeches over guilt or innocence), and deliberative (speeches calling on an audience to make a decision on an issue). Aristotle also outlines two kinds of rhetorical proofs: enthymeme (proof by syllogism) and paradeigma (proof by example).
   −
|Meanness||Liberality||Wastefulness
+
Aristotle的《修辞学》提出,演讲者可以使用三种基本的呼吁来说服他的听众:ethos(对演讲者性格的呼吁)、pathos(对听众情感的呼吁)和logos(对逻辑推理的呼吁)。他还将修辞分为三种类型:epideictic(礼仪性演讲,涉及赞美或指责)、forensic(司法性演讲,涉及有罪或无罪)和deliberative(呼吁听众就某一问题做出决定的演讲)。Aristotle还概述了两种修辞学的证明:省略推理法(推论证明)和paradeigma(例证证明)。
   −
|}
      +
Aristotle writes in his ''Poetics'' that [[epic poetry]], tragedy, comedy, [[Dithyramb|dithyrambic poetry]], painting, sculpture, music, and dance are all fundamentally acts of ''[[mimesis]]'' ("imitation"), each varying in imitation by medium, object, and manner.{{sfn| Halliwell | 2002 | pp=152–59}}{{sfn| Poetics | p= I 1447a}} He applies the term ''mimesis'' both as a property of a work of art and also as the product of the artist's intention{{sfn| Halliwell | 2002 | pp=152–59}} and contends that the audience's realisation of the ''mimesis'' is vital to understanding the work itself.{{sfn| Halliwell | 2002 | pp=152–59}} Aristotle states that ''mimesis'' is a natural instinct of humanity that separates humans from animals{{sfn| Halliwell | 2002 | pp=152–59}}{{sfn| Poetics | p= IV}} and that all human artistry "follows the pattern of nature".{{sfn| Halliwell | 2002 | pp=152–59}} Because of this, Aristotle believed that each of the mimetic arts possesses what [[Stephen Halliwell (academic)|Stephen Halliwell]] calls "highly structured procedures for the achievement of their purposes."{{sfn| Halliwell | 2002 | pp=152–59}} For example, music imitates with the media of rhythm and harmony, whereas dance imitates with rhythm alone, and poetry with language. The forms also differ in their object of imitation. Comedy, for instance, is a dramatic imitation of men worse than average; whereas tragedy imitates men slightly better than average. Lastly, the forms differ in their manner of imitation – through narrative or character, through change or no change, and through drama or no drama.{{sfn| Poetics | p=III}}
    +
Aristotle writes in his Poetics that epic poetry, tragedy, comedy, dithyrambic poetry, painting, sculpture, music, and dance are all fundamentally acts of mimesis ("imitation"), each varying in imitation by medium, object, and manner. He applies the term mimesis both as a property of a work of art and also as the product of the artist's intention and contends that the audience's realisation of the mimesis is vital to understanding the work itself. Aristotle states that mimesis is a natural instinct of humanity that separates humans from animals and that all human artistry "follows the pattern of nature". Because of this, Aristotle believed that each of the mimetic arts possesses what Stephen Halliwell calls "highly structured procedures for the achievement of their purposes." For example, music imitates with the media of rhythm and harmony, whereas dance imitates with rhythm alone, and poetry with language. The forms also differ in their object of imitation. Comedy, for instance, is a dramatic imitation of men worse than average; whereas tragedy imitates men slightly better than average. Lastly, the forms differ in their manner of imitation – through narrative or character, through change or no change, and through drama or no drama.
   −
===Just war theory===
+
Aristotle在他的《诗学》中写道,史诗、悲剧、喜剧、二律诗、绘画、雕塑、音乐和舞蹈从根本上说都是模仿行为(“模仿”) ,每一种都因媒介、对象和方式的不同而不同。他把拟态一词既作为艺术作品的一种属性,又作为艺术家意图的产物,认为观众对拟态的实现对理解作品本身至关重要。亚里士多德指出,拟态是人类区别于动物的一种自然本能,人类的一切艺术创作都 "遵循自然的模式"。正因为如此,Aristotle认为,每一种模仿艺术都拥有斯蒂芬•哈利维尔所说的 "实现其目的的高度结构化的程序"。例如,音乐是以节奏与和谐为媒介进行模仿的,而舞蹈则仅以节奏进行模仿,诗歌则以语言进行模仿。在模仿的对象上,形式也有所不同。比如喜剧是模仿比一般人差的人的戏剧性;而悲剧则是模仿比一般人稍好的人。最后,形式在模仿的方式上也有不同——通过叙事或人物,通过变化或不变化,通过戏剧或不戏剧。
公理战役理论
  −
Aristotelian [[just war theory]] is not well regarded in the present day, especially his view that warfare was justified to enslave "natural slaves". In Aristotelian philosophy, the abolition of what he considers "[[natural slavery]]" would undermine civic [[freedom]]. The pursuit of freedom is inseparable from pursuing mastery over "those who deserve to be slaves". According to ''The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle's Politics'' the targets of this aggressive warfare were non-Greeks, noting Aristotle's view that "our poets say 'it is proper for Greeks to rule non-Greeks'".{{sfn|Deslauriers|Destrée|2013|pp=157-162}}
     −
Aristotelian just war theory is not well regarded in the present day, especially his view that warfare was justified to enslave "natural slaves". In Aristotelian philosophy, the abolition of what he considers "natural slavery" would undermine civic freedom. The pursuit of freedom is inseparable from pursuing mastery over "those who deserve to be slaves". According to The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle's Politics the targets of this aggressive warfare were non-Greeks, noting Aristotle's view that "our poets say 'it is proper for Greeks to rule non-Greeks'".
     −
Aristotle的公理战役理论在今天并不受欢迎,特别是他认为战争是为了奴役 "自然奴隶 "而进行的正义战争。在Aristotle的哲学中,他认为“自然奴隶制”的废除会破坏公民自由。追求自由与追求掌握 "应该成为奴隶的人 "是分不开的。根据《剑桥亚里士多德政治指南》,这种侵略战争的对象是非希腊人,指出Aristotle的观点是 "我们的诗人说'希腊人统治非希腊人是合适的'"。
+
While it is believed that Aristotle's ''Poetics'' originally comprised two books – one on comedy and one on tragedy – only the portion that focuses on tragedy has survived. Aristotle taught that tragedy is composed of six elements: plot-structure, character, style, thought, spectacle, and lyric poetry.{{sfn| Poetics | p=VI}} The characters in a tragedy are merely a means of driving the story; and the plot, not the characters, is the chief focus of tragedy. Tragedy is the imitation of action arousing pity and fear, and is meant to effect the [[catharsis]] of those same emotions. Aristotle concludes ''Poetics'' with a discussion on which, if either, is superior: epic or tragic mimesis. He suggests that because tragedy possesses all the attributes of an epic, possibly possesses additional attributes such as spectacle and music, is more unified, and achieves the aim of its mimesis in shorter scope, it can be considered superior to epic.{{sfn| Poetics | p=XXVI}} Aristotle was a keen systematic collector of riddles, folklore, and proverbs; he and his school had a special interest in the riddles of the [[Pythia|Delphic Oracle]] and studied the fables of [[Aesop]].{{sfn| Aesop | 1998 | pages=Introduction, xi–xii}}
   −
Aristotle generally has a favourable opinion of war, extolling it as a chance for [[virtue]] and writing that "the leisure that accompanies peace" tends to make people "arrogant". War to "avoid becoming enslaved to others" is justified as self-defense. He writes that war "compels people to be just and temperate", however, in order to be just "war must be chosen for the sake of peace" (with the exception of wars of aggression discussed above).{{sfn|Deslauriers|Destrée|2013|pp=157-162}}
+
While it is believed that Aristotle's Poetics originally comprised two books – one on comedy and one on tragedy – only the portion that focuses on tragedy has survived. Aristotle taught that tragedy is composed of six elements: plot-structure, character, style, thought, spectacle, and lyric poetry. The characters in a tragedy are merely a means of driving the story; and the plot, not the characters, is the chief focus of tragedy. Tragedy is the imitation of action arousing pity and fear, and is meant to effect the catharsis of those same emotions. Aristotle concludes Poetics with a discussion on which, if either, is superior: epic or tragic mimesis. He suggests that because tragedy possesses all the attributes of an epic, possibly possesses additional attributes such as spectacle and music, is more unified, and achieves the aim of its mimesis in shorter scope, it can be considered superior to epic. Aristotle was a keen systematic collector of riddles, folklore, and proverbs; he and his school had a special interest in the riddles of the Delphic Oracle and studied the fables of Aesop.
   −
Aristotle generally has a favourable opinion of war, extolling it as a chance for virtue and writing that "the leisure that accompanies peace" tends to make people "arrogant". War to "avoid becoming enslaved to others" is justified as self-defense. He writes that war "compels people to be just and temperate", however, in order to be just "war must be chosen for the sake of peace" (with the exception of wars of aggression discussed above).
+
虽然人们认为Aristotle的《诗学》最初是由两部书组成——一部论述喜剧,一部论述悲剧,但只有集中论述悲剧的部分留存了下来。Aristotle认为悲剧由六个要素组成: 情节结构、人物、风格、思想、景观和抒情诗。悲剧中的人物只是推动故事发展的一种手段; 悲剧的主要焦点是情节,而不是人物。悲剧是对引起怜悯和恐惧的行为的模仿,是为了达到宣泄这些相同情感的效果。Aristotle在《诗学》的最后,讨论了史诗和悲剧模仿哪一个更优越。他认为,由于悲剧具有史诗的所有属性,可能还具有诸如景观和音乐等额外的属性,更加统一,并在较短的范围内达到了模仿的目的,因此可以认为它优于史诗。Aristotle热衷于系统地收集谜语、民间传说和谚语; 他和他的学派对特尔菲神谕的谜语特别感兴趣,并研究了伊索寓言。
   −
Aristotle一般对战争持赞成态度,赞美战争是美德的机会,并写道:"伴随和平而来的闲暇 "容易使人 "傲慢"。为了 "避免成为他人的奴隶 "而进行的战争,是正当的自卫。他写道,战争 "迫使人们变得公正和节制",然而,为了公正,"必须为了和平而选择战争"(上文讨论的侵略战争除外)。
        −
===Ethics===
+
===Views on women===
伦理
+
对女性的看法
    +
{{main | Aristotle's views on women}}
    +
{{further | Aristotle's biology#Inheritance}}
   −
{{main | Aristotelian ethics}}
+
Aristotle's analysis of procreation describes an active, ensouling masculine element bringing life to an inert, passive female element. On this ground, proponents of [[feminist metaphysics]] have accused Aristotle of [[misogyny]]{{sfn| Freeland | 1998}} and [[sexism]].{{sfn| Morsink | 1979 | pp=83–112}} However, Aristotle gave equal weight to women's happiness as he did to men's, and commented in his ''Rhetoric'' that the things that lead to happiness need to be in women as well as men.{{efn-ua | "Where, as among the Lacedaemonians, the state of women is bad, almost half of human life is spoilt."{{sfn| Rhetoric | p=Book I, Chapter 5}}}}
   −
Aristotle considered ethics to be a practical rather than theoretical study, i.e., one aimed at becoming good and doing good rather than knowing for its own sake. He wrote several treatises on ethics, including most notably, the ''[[Nicomachean Ethics]]''.{{sfn| Kraut | 2001}}
+
Aristotle's analysis of procreation describes an active, ensouling masculine element bringing life to an inert, passive female element. On this ground, proponents of feminist metaphysics have accused Aristotle of misogyny and sexism. However, Aristotle gave equal weight to women's happiness as he did to men's, and commented in his Rhetoric that the things that lead to happiness need to be in women as well as men.
   −
Aristotle considered ethics to be a practical rather than theoretical study, i.e., one aimed at becoming good and doing good rather than knowing for its own sake. He wrote several treatises on ethics, including most notably, the Nicomachean Ethics.
+
Aristotle对生育的分析描述了一个主动的、合体的男性元素给一个惰性的、被动的女性元素带来生命。基于此,女权主义形而上学的支持者指责Aristotle厌恶女性和性别歧视。然而,Aristotle对女人的幸福和对男人的幸福给予了同等的重视,并在他的修辞学中评论说,通向幸福的东西幸福的东西既要在妇女身上,也要在男子身上。
   −
Aristotle认为伦理学是一门实践性的而非理论性的研究,即旨在向善和行善,而不是为了认识而认识。他写了几篇伦理学论文,其中最著名的是《尼各马可伦理学》。
     −
Aristotle taught that virtue has to do with the proper function (''ergon'') of a thing. An eye is only a good eye in so much as it can see, because the proper function of an eye is sight. Aristotle reasoned that humans must have a function specific to humans, and that this function must be an activity of the ''[[De Anima|psuchē]]'' (''soul'') in accordance with reason (''[[logos]]''). Aristotle identified such an optimum activity (the virtuous mean, between the accompanying vices of excess or deficiency{{sfn| Aristotle (384–322 B.C.E.)}}) of the soul as the aim of all human deliberate action, ''[[eudaimonia]]'', generally translated as "happiness" or sometimes "well being". To have the potential of ever being happy in this way necessarily requires a good character (''ēthikē'' ''[[arete (moral virtue)|aretē]]''), often translated as moral or ethical virtue or excellence.{{sfn| Nicomachean Ethics | ps= &nbsp;Book I. See for example chapter 7.}}
+
==Influence==
 +
影响
   −
Aristotle taught that virtue has to do with the proper function (ergon) of a thing. An eye is only a good eye in so much as it can see, because the proper function of an eye is sight. Aristotle reasoned that humans must have a function specific to humans, and that this function must be an activity of the psuchē (soul) in accordance with reason (logos). Aristotle identified such an optimum activity (the virtuous mean, between the accompanying vices of excess or deficiency) of the soul as the aim of all human deliberate action, eudaimonia, generally translated as "happiness" or sometimes "well being". To have the potential of ever being happy in this way necessarily requires a good character (ēthikē aretē), often translated as moral or ethical virtue or excellence.
+
{{see | List of writers influenced by Aristotle}}
   −
Aristotle教导说,美德与事物的适当功能(ergon)有关。一只眼睛只有在它能看见的范围内才是一只好眼睛,因为眼睛的适当功能是视觉。Aristotle推理说,人必须有一种人类特有的功能,这种功能必须是符合理性(logos)的psuchē(灵魂)的活动。Aristotle把灵魂的这种最佳活动(在过剩或不足的与之相伴的恶习之间的良性平均)确定为人类一切刻意行动的目标,即eudaimonia,一般译为 "幸福",有时也译为 "安康"。要想以这种方式拥有永远幸福的潜力,必然需要良好的品格(ēthikē aretē),通常被译为道德或伦理的美德或卓越。
+
更多信息:受Aristotle影响的作家名单
 +
More than 2300 years after his death, Aristotle remains one of the most influential people who ever lived.{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | p=8}}{{sfn| Aristotle's Influence | 2018}} He contributed to almost every field of human knowledge then in existence, and he was the founder of many new fields. According to the philosopher [[Bryan Magee]], "it is doubtful whether any human being has ever known as much as he did".{{sfn| Magee | 2010 | page=34}} Among countless other achievements, Aristotle was the founder of [[formal logic]],{{sfn| Guthrie | 1990 | page=156}}<!--{{sfn| Case | p=518}}--> pioneered the study of [[zoology]], and left every future scientist and philosopher in his debt through his contributions to the scientific method.{{sfn| Aristotle (Greek philosopher)}}{{sfn| Durant | 2006 | page=92}}{{sfn| Kukkonen | 2010 | pages=70–77}} Taneli Kukkonen, writing in ''The Classical Tradition'', observes that his achievement in founding two sciences is unmatched, and his reach in influencing "every branch of intellectual enterprise" including Western ethical and political theory, theology, rhetoric and literary analysis is equally long. As a result, Kukkonen argues, any analysis of reality today "will almost certainly carry Aristotelian overtones ... evidence of an exceptionally forceful mind."{{sfn| Kukkonen | 2010 | pages=70–77}} [[Jonathan Barnes]] wrote that "an account of Aristotle's intellectual afterlife would be little less than a history of European thought".{{sfn| Barnes | 1982 | page=86}}
   −
Aristotle taught that to achieve a virtuous and potentially happy character requires a first stage of having the fortune to be habituated not deliberately, but by teachers, and experience, leading to a later stage in which one consciously chooses to do the best things. When the best people come to live life this way their practical wisdom (''[[phronesis]]'') and their intellect (''[[nous]]'') can develop with each other towards the highest possible human virtue, the wisdom of an accomplished theoretical or speculative thinker, or in other words, a philosopher.{{sfn| Nicomachean Ethics | p= Book VI}}
+
More than 2300 years after his death, Aristotle remains one of the most influential people who ever lived. He contributed to almost every field of human knowledge then in existence, and he was the founder of many new fields. According to the philosopher Bryan Magee, "it is doubtful whether any human being has ever known as much as he did". Among countless other achievements, Aristotle was the founder of formal logic,<!----> pioneered the study of zoology, and left every future scientist and philosopher in his debt through his contributions to the scientific method. Taneli Kukkonen, writing in The Classical Tradition, observes that his achievement in founding two sciences is unmatched, and his reach in influencing "every branch of intellectual enterprise" including Western ethical and political theory, theology, rhetoric and literary analysis is equally long. As a result, Kukkonen argues, any analysis of reality today "will almost certainly carry Aristotelian overtones ... evidence of an exceptionally forceful mind." Jonathan Barnes wrote that "an account of Aristotle's intellectual afterlife would be little less than a history of European thought".
   −
Aristotle taught that to achieve a virtuous and potentially happy character requires a first stage of having the fortune to be habituated not deliberately, but by teachers, and experience, leading to a later stage in which one consciously chooses to do the best things. When the best people come to live life this way their practical wisdom (phronesis) and their intellect (nous) can develop with each other towards the highest possible human virtue, the wisdom of an accomplished theoretical or speculative thinker, or in other words, a philosopher.
+
Aristotle去世2300多年后,他仍然是有史以来最有影响力的人物之一。他对当时存在的人类知识的几乎每一个领域都做出了贡献,他还是许多新领域的创始人。哲学家布莱恩 · 马吉Bryan Magee认为,“很怀疑是否有人像他一样知道这么多。”。在无数的成就中,Aristotle是形式逻辑的创始人,开创了动物学研究,他对科学方法的贡献让每一个未来的科学家和哲学家都感激不尽。狄克礼•库克宁Taneli Kukkonen 在《古典传统》一书中写道,他在创立两门科学方面的成就是无与伦比的,他在影响“知识事业的每一个分支” ,包括西方伦理和政治理论、神学、修辞学和文学分析的影响也同样长久。因此,Kukkonen 认为,今天对现实的任何分析“几乎肯定会带有Aristotle的色彩... ... 证明他的思想异常强大。”乔纳森•巴恩斯Jonathan Barnes写道: “对Aristotle的知识后世的描述将不亚于一部欧洲思想史。”。
   −
Aristotle教导说,要达到一种有德行的、潜在的幸福的品格,需要有一个第一阶段的幸运,不是刻意的,而是通过老师、经验的熏陶,导致后期自觉地选择做最好的事情。当最优秀的人以这种方式来生活时,他们的实践智慧(实践理性)和他们的智力(理性)可以相互发展,朝着人类最高的美德,即一个有成就的理论或投机思想家的智慧,或者换句话说,一个哲学家的智慧发展。
      +
===On his successor, Theophrastus===
   −
===Politics===
+
他的后继者泰奥弗拉斯托斯
政治
      +
[[File:161Theophrastus 161 frontespizio.jpg | thumb | upright | [[Book frontispiece|Frontispiece]] to a 1644 version of [[Theophrastus]]'s ''[[Historia Plantarum (Theophrastus)|Historia Plantarum]]'', originally written around 300 BC]]
    +
Frontispiece to a 1644 version of Theophrastus's Historia Plantarum, originally written around 300 BC
   −
{{main | Politics (Aristotle)}}
+
Theophrastus的《植物历史》1644年版本的卷首插图,最初写于公元前300年左右
   −
In addition to his works on ethics, which address the individual, Aristotle addressed the city in his work titled ''[[Politics (Aristotle)|Politics]]''. Aristotle considered the city to be a natural community. Moreover, he considered the city to be prior in importance to the family which in turn is prior to the individual, "for the whole must of necessity be prior to the part".{{sfn| Politics | pp=1253a19–24}} He famously stated that "man is by nature a political animal" and argued that humanity's defining factor among others in the animal kingdom is its rationality.{{sfn| Aristotle | 2009 | pages=320–21}} Aristotle conceived of politics as being like an organism rather than like a machine, and as a collection of parts none of which can exist without the others. Aristotle's conception of the city is organic, and he is considered one of the first to conceive of the city in this manner.{{sfn| Ebenstein | Ebenstein | 2002 | page=59}}
+
{{main | Theophrastus | Historia Plantarum (Theophrastus)}}
   −
In addition to his works on ethics, which address the individual, Aristotle addressed the city in his work titled Politics. Aristotle considered the city to be a natural community. Moreover, he considered the city to be prior in importance to the family which in turn is prior to the individual, "for the whole must of necessity be prior to the part". He famously stated that "man is by nature a political animal" and argued that humanity's defining factor among others in the animal kingdom is its rationality. Aristotle conceived of politics as being like an organism rather than like a machine, and as a collection of parts none of which can exist without the others. Aristotle's conception of the city is organic, and he is considered one of the first to conceive of the city in this manner.
+
Aristotle's pupil and successor, [[Theophrastus]], wrote the ''[[Historia Plantarum (Theophrastus)|History of Plants]]'', a pioneering work in botany. Some of his technical terms remain in use, such as [[carpel]] from ''carpos'', fruit, and [[pericarp]], from ''pericarpion'', seed chamber.{{sfn| Hooker | 1831 | page=219}}
 +
Theophrastus was much less concerned with formal causes than Aristotle was, instead pragmatically describing how plants functioned.{{sfn| Mayr | 1982 | pp= 90–91}}{{sfn| Mason | 1979 | p= 46}}
   −
Aristotle除了在他的伦理学著作中论述个人外,还在他题为《政治学》的著作中论述了城市。Aristotle认为城市是一个自然共同体。此外,他认为城市的重要性高于家庭,而家庭又高于个人,"因为整体必然高于部分"。他有句名言:"人在本质上是一种政治动物",认为人类在动物界其他动物中的决定性因素是其理性。Aristotle把政治设想为像一个有机体而不是像一台机器,是一个部分的集合,其中任何一个部分都不能离开其他部分而存在。Aristotle的城市概念是有机的,他被认为是最早以这种方式设想城市的人之一。
+
Aristotle's pupil and successor, Theophrastus, wrote the History of Plants, a pioneering work in botany. Some of his technical terms remain in use, such as carpel from carpos, fruit, and pericarp, from pericarpion, seed chamber. Theophrastus was much less concerned with formal causes than Aristotle was, instead pragmatically describing how plants functioned.
   −
[[File:Aristotle's constitutions.svg | thumb|upright=1.7 | Aristotle's classifications of political constitutions]]
+
Aristotle的学生和后继者Theophrastus撰写了植物学史,这是一部植物学的开创性著作。他的某些技术术语仍然在使用,如心皮,果实,果皮,从外皮,种子室。与亚里士多德相比,Theophrastus对形式上的原因的关注要少得多,而是实事求是地描述植物是如何运作的。
   −
Aristotle's classifications of political constitutions
     −
Aristotle对政治宪法的分类
     −
The common modern understanding of a political community as a modern state is quite different from Aristotle's understanding. Although he was aware of the existence and potential of larger empires, the natural community according to Aristotle was the city (''[[polis]]'') which functions as a political "community" or "partnership" (''koinōnia'')<!-- (1252a1) -->. The aim of the city is not just to avoid injustice or for economic stability<!-- (1280b29–31) -->, but rather to allow at least some citizens the possibility to live a good life, and to perform beautiful acts: "The political partnership must be regarded, therefore, as being for the sake of noble actions, not for the sake of living together<!-- (1281a1–3) -->." This is distinguished from modern approaches, beginning with [[social contract]] theory, according to which individuals leave the [[state of nature]] because of "fear of violent death" or its "inconveniences."{{efn-ua | For a different reading of social and economic processes in the ''Nicomachean Ethics'' and ''Politics'' see Polanyi, Karl (1957) "Aristotle Discovers the Economy" in ''Primitive, Archaic and Modern Economies: Essays of Karl Polanyi'' ed. G. Dalton, Boston 1971, 78–115.}}
+
===On later Greek philosophers===
 +
关于后来的希腊哲学家
 +
{{further | Peripatetic school}}
   −
The common modern understanding of a political community as a modern state is quite different from Aristotle's understanding. Although he was aware of the existence and potential of larger empires, the natural community according to Aristotle was the city (polis) which functions as a political "community" or "partnership" (koinōnia). The aim of the city is not just to avoid injustice or for economic stability, but rather to allow at least some citizens the possibility to live a good life, and to perform beautiful acts: "The political partnership must be regarded, therefore, as being for the sake of noble actions, not for the sake of living together." This is distinguished from modern approaches, beginning with social contract theory, according to which individuals leave the state of nature because of "fear of violent death" or its "inconveniences."
+
The immediate influence of Aristotle's work was felt as the Lyceum grew into the [[Peripatetic school]]. Aristotle's notable students included [[Aristoxenus]], [[Dicaearchus]], [[Demetrius of Phalerum]], [[Eudemos of Rhodes]], [[Harpalus]], [[Hephaestion]], [[Mnason of Phocis]], [[Nicomachus (son of Aristotle)|Nicomachus]], and Theophrastus. Aristotle's influence over Alexander the Great is seen in the latter's bringing with him on his expedition a host of zoologists, botanists, and researchers. He had also learned a great deal about Persian customs and traditions from his teacher. Although his respect for Aristotle was diminished as his travels made it clear that much of Aristotle's geography was clearly wrong, when the old philosopher released his works to the public, Alexander complained "Thou hast not done well to publish thy acroamatic doctrines; for in what shall I surpass other men if those doctrines wherein I have been trained are to be all men's common property?"{{sfn| Plutarch | 1919 | p= Part 1, 7:7}}
   −
现代人对作为现代国家的政治共同体的普遍理解与Aristotle的理解大相径庭。尽管他意识到更大帝国的存在和潜力,但Aristotle认为的自然共同体是作为政治 "共同体 "或 "伙伴关系"(koinōnia)的城市(城邦)。城市的目的不仅仅是为了避免不公正,也不仅仅是为了经济稳定,而是至少要让一些公民有可能过上好的生活,有可能做出美好的行为。"因此,政治伙伴关系必须被视为是为了高尚的行为,而不是为了共同生活。" 这有别于从社会契约论开始的现代方法,根据这种方法,个人因为 "害怕暴力死亡 "或其 "不便 "而离开自然状态。
+
The immediate influence of Aristotle's work was felt as the Lyceum grew into the Peripatetic school. Aristotle's notable students included Aristoxenus, Dicaearchus, Demetrius of Phalerum, Eudemos of Rhodes, Harpalus, Hephaestion, Mnason of Phocis, Nicomachus, and Theophrastus. Aristotle's influence over Alexander the Great is seen in the latter's bringing with him on his expedition a host of zoologists, botanists, and researchers. He had also learned a great deal about Persian customs and traditions from his teacher. Although his respect for Aristotle was diminished as his travels made it clear that much of Aristotle's geography was clearly wrong, when the old philosopher released his works to the public, Alexander complained "Thou hast not done well to publish thy acroamatic doctrines; for in what shall I surpass other men if those doctrines wherein I have been trained are to be all men's common property?"
    +
当吕克昂学院发展成为逍遥学派时,Aristotle的作品随即产生了影响。Aristotle著名的学生包括阿里斯托克西努斯Aristoxenus、狄卡伊尔库斯Dicaearchus、法勒鲁姆的德米特里Demetrius of Phalerum、罗得岛的尤德莫斯Eudemos of Rhodes、哈帕卢斯Harpalus、 赫菲谢耳Hephaestion、  弗西斯的姆纳松Mnason of Phocis、尼各马库斯Nicomachus和Theophrastus。Aristotle对Alexandria大帝的影响体现在Alexandria大帝远征时带来的大批动物学家、植物学家和研究人员。他还从他的老师那里学到了很多关于波斯风俗和传统的知识。尽管他对Aristotle的尊敬有所减弱,因为他的远征清楚地表明,Aristotle的许多地理学说显然是错误的,但当这位老哲学家将他的作品公之于众时,Alexandria抱怨道: “你发表你的晦涩难懂的学说并不好,因为如果我所接受的这些学说成为所有人的共同财产,那么我还能在什么方面超越其他人呢? ”
   −
In ''[[Protrepticus (Aristotle)|Protrepticus]]'', the character 'Aristotle' states:{{sfn| Hutchinson | Johnson | 2015 | p=22}}
     −
In Protrepticus, the character 'Aristotle' states:
     −
在《 劝勉篇 》中,Aristotle这样写道:
         +
===On Hellenistic science===
 +
关于希腊化科学
   −
{{quote | For we all agree that the most excellent man should rule, i.e., the supreme by nature, and that the law rules and alone is authoritative; but the law is a kind of intelligence, i.e. a discourse based on intelligence. And again, what standard do we have, what criterion of good things, that is more precise than the intelligent man? For all that this man will choose, if the choice is based on his knowledge, are good things and their contraries are bad. And since everybody chooses most of all what conforms to their own proper dispositions (a just man choosing to live justly, a man with bravery to live bravely, likewise a self-controlled man to live with self-control), it is clear that the intelligent man will choose most of all to be intelligent; for this is the function of that capacity. Hence it's evident that, according to the most authoritative judgment, intelligence is supreme among goods.{{sfn| Hutchinson | Johnson | 2015 | p=22}}}}
+
{{details | Ancient Greek medicine}}
 +
更多信息:古希腊医学
   −
因为我们都认为,最优秀的人应该是统治者,也就是本质上的最高者,法律的统治,只有法律才是权威的;但法律是一种智慧,也就是以智慧为基础的话语。再如,我们有什么标准,有什么好东西的标准,比聪明人更精确呢?因为这个人会选择的所有东西,如果是基于他的知识而选择的,都是好东西,而它们的反面是坏东西。既然每个人都会选择最符合自己适当性情的东西(一个公正的人选择公正地生活,一个勇敢的人选择勇敢地生活,同样,一个自制的人选择自制地生活),那么很明显,聪明的人最会选择聪明的东西;因为这是这种能力的功能。因此,很明显,根据最权威的判断,智慧在商品中是至高无上的。
+
After Theophrastus, the Lyceum failed to produce any original work. Though interest in Aristotle's ideas survived, they were generally taken unquestioningly.{{sfn| Annas | 2001 | page=252}} It is not until the age of [[Alexandria]] under the [[Ptolemaic Kingdom|Ptolemies]] that advances in biology can be again found.
    +
After Theophrastus, the Lyceum failed to produce any original work. Though interest in Aristotle's ideas survived, they were generally taken unquestioningly. It is not until the age of Alexandria under the Ptolemies that advances in biology can be again found.
   −
===Economics===
+
在Theophrastus之后,吕克昂学院未能创作出任何原创作品。尽管人们对Aristotle思想的兴趣依然存在,但人们普遍毫无疑问地接受了这些思想。直到托勒密统治下的亚历山大时代,生物学的进步才得以重见天日。
经济学
     −
{{main | Politics (Aristotle)}}
     −
Aristotle made substantial contributions to [[economics|economic thought]], especially to thought in the Middle Ages.{{sfn| Robbins | 2000 | pages=20–24}} In ''[[Politics (Aristotle)|Politics]]'', Aristotle addresses the city, [[property]], and [[trade]]. His response to criticisms of [[private property]], in [[Lionel Robbins]]'s view, anticipated later proponents of private property among philosophers and economists, as it related to the overall [[utility]] of social arrangements.{{sfn| Robbins | 2000 | pages=20–24}} Aristotle believed that although communal arrangements may seem beneficial to society, and that although private property is often blamed for social strife, such evils in fact come from [[human nature]]. In ''Politics'', Aristotle offers one of the earliest accounts of the origin of [[money]].{{sfn| Robbins | 2000 | pages=20–24}} Money came into use because people became dependent on one another, importing what they needed and exporting the surplus. For the sake of convenience, people then agreed to deal in something that is intrinsically useful and easily applicable, such as iron or [[silver]].{{sfn| Aristotle | 1948 | pages=16–28}}
+
The first medical teacher at Alexandria, [[Herophilos|Herophilus of Chalcedon]], corrected Aristotle, placing intelligence in the brain, and connected the nervous system to motion and sensation. Herophilus also distinguished between [[vein]]s and [[artery|arteries]], noting that the latter [[pulse]] while the former do not.{{sfn| Mason | 1979 | p= 56}} Though a few ancient [[atomism|atomists]] such as [[Lucretius]] challenged the [[teleology|teleological]] viewpoint of Aristotelian ideas about life, teleology (and after the rise of Christianity, [[natural theology]]) would remain central to biological thought essentially until the 18th and 19th centuries. [[Ernst Mayr]] states that there was "nothing of any real consequence in biology after Lucretius and Galen until the Renaissance."{{sfn| Mayr | 1985 | pp=90–94}}
   −
Aristotle made substantial contributions to economic thought, especially to thought in the Middle Ages. In Politics, Aristotle addresses the city, property, and trade. His response to criticisms of private property, in Lionel Robbins's view, anticipated later proponents of private property among philosophers and economists, as it related to the overall utility of social arrangements. Aristotle believed that although communal arrangements may seem beneficial to society, and that although private property is often blamed for social strife, such evils in fact come from human nature. In Politics, Aristotle offers one of the earliest accounts of the origin of money. Money came into use because people became dependent on one another, importing what they needed and exporting the surplus. For the sake of convenience, people then agreed to deal in something that is intrinsically useful and easily applicable, such as iron or silver.
+
The first medical teacher at Alexandria, Herophilus of Chalcedon, corrected Aristotle, placing intelligence in the brain, and connected the nervous system to motion and sensation. Herophilus also distinguished between veins and arteries, noting that the latter pulse while the former do not. Though a few ancient atomists such as Lucretius challenged the teleological viewpoint of Aristotelian ideas about life, teleology (and after the rise of Christianity, natural theology) would remain central to biological thought essentially until the 18th and 19th centuries. Ernst Mayr states that there was "nothing of any real consequence in biology after Lucretius and Galen until the Renaissance."
   −
Aristotle对经济思想,特别是对中世纪的思想做出了实质性的贡献。在《政治学》中,Aristotle论述了城市、财产和贸易问题。在莱昂内尔•罗宾斯Lionel Robbins看来,他对私有财产批评的回应,预见到了后来哲学家和经济学家中私有财产的支持者,因为它关系到社会安排的整体效用。Aristotle认为,虽然公有制安排看似对社会有益,虽然私有财产常常被指责为社会纷争的原因,但这种弊端其实来自于人性。在《政治学》中,Aristotle对货币的起源提出了一个最早的说法。货币之所以会被使用,是因为人们开始相互依赖,进口自己需要的东西,出口多余的东西。为了方便起见,人们便同意用铁或银等本质上有用且容易适用的东西进行交易。
+
亚历山大的第一位医学老师,来自查尔斯顿的赫罗菲菲罗斯Herophilus,纠正了Aristotle的错误,将智慧置于大脑,并将神经系统与运动和感觉联系起来。Herophilus还区分了静脉和动脉,指出后者有脉搏,而前者没有。尽管少数古代原子论者,如 卢克莱修斯Lucretius挑战了Aristotle关于生命的心学观点,但心学(以及基督教兴起后的自然神学)在18、19世纪之前基本上仍然是生物学思想的核心。恩斯特 · 迈尔Ernst Mayr 说,“在Lucretius和盖伦Galen之后,直到文艺复兴时期,生物学上没有任何实质性的结果。”
    +
===On Byzantine scholars===
 +
关于拜占庭学者
   −
Aristotle's discussions on [[retail]] and [[interest]] was a major influence on economic thought in the Middle Ages. He had a low opinion of retail, believing that contrary to using money to procure things one needs in managing the household, retail trade seeks to make a [[profit (economics)|profit]]. It thus uses goods as a means to an end, rather than as an end unto itself. He believed that retail trade was in this way unnatural. Similarly, Aristotle considered making a profit through interest unnatural, as it makes a gain out of the money itself, and not from its use.{{sfn| Aristotle | 1948 | pages=16–28}}
+
{{see also | Commentaries on Aristotle | Byzantine Aristotelianism}}
   −
Aristotle's discussions on retail and interest was a major influence on economic thought in the Middle Ages. He had a low opinion of retail, believing that contrary to using money to procure things one needs in managing the household, retail trade seeks to make a profit. It thus uses goods as a means to an end, rather than as an end unto itself. He believed that retail trade was in this way unnatural. Similarly, Aristotle considered making a profit through interest unnatural, as it makes a gain out of the money itself, and not from its use.
+
另请参阅:亚里士多德和拜占庭亚里士多德主义评论
   −
Aristotle关于零售和利息的讨论对中世纪的经济思想产生了重大影响。他不看好零售业,认为零售业与用金钱来采购自己管理家庭所需的东西相反,零售业追求的是利润。因此,它把商品作为达到目的的手段,而不是作为目的本身。他认为,零售贸易在这种方式上是不自然的。同样,Aristotle认为,通过利息获利是不自然的,因为它从货币本身而不是从货币的使用中获得收益。
+
Greek Christian scribes played a crucial role in the preservation of Aristotle by copying all the extant Greek language manuscripts of the corpus. The first Greek Christians to comment extensively on Aristotle were Philoponus, Elias, and David in the sixth century, and [[Stephen of Alexandria]] in the early seventh century.{{sfn| Sorabji | 1990 | pages=20, 28, 35–36}} [[John Philoponus]] stands out for having attempted a fundamental critique of Aristotle's views on the eternity of the world, movement, and other elements of Aristotelian thought.{{sfn| Sorabji | 1990 | pages=233–74}} Philoponus questioned Aristotle's teaching of physics, noting its flaws and introducing the [[theory of impetus]] to explain his observations.{{sfn|Lindberg|1992|p=162}}
   −
Aristotle gave a summary of the function of money that was perhaps remarkably precocious for his time. He wrote that because it is impossible to determine the value of every good through a count of the number of other goods it is worth, the necessity arises of a single universal standard of measurement. Money thus allows for the association of different goods and makes them "commensurable".{{sfn| Aristotle | 1948 | pages=16–28}} He goes on to state that money is also useful for future exchange, making it a sort of security. That is, "if we do not want a thing now, we shall be able to get it when we do want it".{{sfn| Aristotle | 1948 | pages=16–28}}
+
Greek Christian scribes played a crucial role in the preservation of Aristotle by copying all the extant Greek language manuscripts of the corpus. The first Greek Christians to comment extensively on Aristotle were Philoponus, Elias, and David in the sixth century, and Stephen of Alexandria in the early seventh century. John Philoponus stands out for having attempted a fundamental critique of Aristotle's views on the eternity of the world, movement, and other elements of Aristotelian thought. Philoponus questioned Aristotle's teaching of physics, noting its flaws and introducing the theory of impetus to explain his observations.
   −
Aristotle gave a summary of the function of money that was perhaps remarkably precocious for his time. He wrote that because it is impossible to determine the value of every good through a count of the number of other goods it is worth, the necessity arises of a single universal standard of measurement. Money thus allows for the association of different goods and makes them "commensurable". He goes on to state that money is also useful for future exchange, making it a sort of security. That is, "if we do not want a thing now, we shall be able to get it when we do want it".
+
希腊基督教抄写员抄写了所有现存的希腊语手稿,对保存Aristotle的著作起到了至关重要的作用。第一个广泛评论Aristotle的希腊基督徒是六世纪的斐洛波诺斯Philoponus、以利亚Elias和大卫David,以及七世纪初的亚历山大•斯蒂芬Stephen of Alexandria 。John Philoponus站出来,因为他试图对Aristotle关于世界永恒、运动和Aristotle思想的其他要素观点进行根本性的批判。Philoponus质疑Aristotle的物理学教学,指出其缺陷,并引入了动力理论来解释他的观察。
   −
Aristotle总结了货币的功能,对于他那个时代来说,这个概念可能是非常早熟的。他写道,由于不可能通过计算每件商品的价值来确定它的价值,因此有必要制定一个统一的衡量标准。因此,货币可以把不同的商品联系起来,使它们 "可通约"。他接着说,货币对于未来的交换也是有用的,使它成为一种保障。也就是说,"如果我们现在不想要一件东西,那么当我们想要的时候,我们就能够得到它"。
      +
After a hiatus of several centuries, formal commentary by Eustratius and [[Michael of Ephesus]] reappeared in the late eleventh and early twelfth centuries, apparently sponsored by [[Anna Comnena]].{{sfn|Sorabji|1990|pp=20–21, 28–29, 393–406, 407–08}}
    +
After a hiatus of several centuries, formal commentary by Eustratius and Michael of Ephesus reappeared in the late eleventh and early twelfth centuries, apparently sponsored by Anna Comnena.
    +
在中断了几个世纪之后,以弗所的 尤斯特拉修斯和米迦勒 Michael 的正式评论在11世纪末和12世纪初重新出现,显然是由 安娜•康姆纳Anna Comnena 发起的。
         −
===Rhetoric and poetics===
+
===On the medieval Islamic world===
修辞学和诗学
+
在中世纪的伊斯兰世界
   −
[[File:Bénigne Gagneraux, The Blind Oedipus Commending his Children to the Gods.jpg | thumb | upright=1.3 | ''The Blind Oedipus Commending his Children to the Gods'' (1784) by [[Bénigne Gagneraux]]. In his ''[[Poetics (Aristotle)|Poetics]]'', Aristotle uses the tragedy ''[[Oedipus Rex|Oedipus Tyrannus]]'' by [[Sophocles]] as an example of how the perfect tragedy should be structured, with a generally good protagonist who starts the play prosperous, but loses everything through some ''[[hamartia]]'' (fault).{{sfn| Kaufmann | 1968 | pages=56–60}}]]
+
{{further|Logic in Islamic philosophy|Transmission of the Greek Classics}}
   −
The Blind Oedipus Commending his Children to the Gods (1784) by Bénigne Gagneraux. In his Poetics, Aristotle uses the tragedy Oedipus Tyrannus by Sophocles as an example of how the perfect tragedy should be structured, with a generally good protagonist who starts the play prosperous, but loses everything through some hamartia (fault).
+
[[File:Arabic aristotle.jpg | thumb|upright | Islamic portrayal of Aristotle, c. 1220]]
   −
《失明的俄狄浦斯向神明夸奖他的孩子们》(1784年),作者是贝尼涅•加格纳罗Bénigne Gagneraux。在他的《诗学》中,Aristotle以索福克勒斯Sophocles的悲剧《俄狄浦斯——暴君》为例,说明完美的悲剧应该如何结构,剧中的主人公一般都是好的,他在剧中一开始很繁荣,但由于一些过失而失去了一切。
+
Islamic portrayal of Aristotle, c. 1220
    +
伊斯兰对亚里士多德的描绘,约1220年
   −
{{main | Rhetoric (Aristotle) | Poetics (Aristotle)}}
+
Aristotle was one of the most revered Western thinkers in early [[Islamic theology]]. Most of the still extant works of Aristotle,{{sfn|Kennedy-Day|1998}} as well as a number of the original Greek commentaries, were translated into Arabic and studied by Muslim philosophers, scientists and scholars. [[Averroes]], [[Avicenna]] and [[Alpharabius]], who wrote on Aristotle in great depth, also influenced [[Thomas Aquinas]] and other Western Christian scholastic philosophers. [[Alkindus]] greatly admired Aristotle's philosophy,{{sfn|Staley|1989}} and Averroes spoke of Aristotle as the "exemplar" for all future philosophers.{{sfn|Averroes|1953|p=III, 2, 43}} Medieval Muslim scholars regularly described Aristotle as the "First Teacher".{{sfn|Kennedy-Day|1998}} The title "teacher" was first given to Aristotle by Muslim scholars, and was later used by Western philosophers (as in the famous poem of [[Dante Alighieri|Dante]]) who were influenced by the tradition of [[Islamic philosophy]].{{sfn|Nasr|1996|pp=59–60}}
   −
Aristotle's ''Rhetoric'' proposes that a speaker can use three basic kinds of appeals to persuade his audience: ''[[ethos]]'' (an appeal to the speaker's character), ''[[pathos]]'' (an appeal to the audience's emotion), and ''[[logos]]'' (an appeal to logical reasoning).{{sfn| Garver | 1994 | pages=109–10}} He also categorizes rhetoric into three genres: [[epideictic]] (ceremonial speeches dealing with praise or blame), [[Forensic rhetoric|forensic]] (judicial speeches over guilt or innocence), and [[Deliberative rhetoric|deliberative]] (speeches calling on an audience to make a decision on an issue).{{sfn| Rorty | 1996 | pages=3–7}} Aristotle also outlines two kinds of rhetorical [[Proof (truth)|proofs]]: ''[[enthymeme]]'' (proof by [[syllogism]]) and ''[[paradeigma]]'' (proof by example).{{sfn| Grimaldi | 1998 | p=71}}
+
Aristotle was one of the most revered Western thinkers in early Islamic theology. Most of the still extant works of Aristotle, as well as a number of the original Greek commentaries, were translated into Arabic and studied by Muslim philosophers, scientists and scholars. Averroes, Avicenna and Alpharabius, who wrote on Aristotle in great depth, also influenced Thomas Aquinas and other Western Christian scholastic philosophers. Alkindus greatly admired Aristotle's philosophy, and Averroes spoke of Aristotle as the "exemplar" for all future philosophers. Medieval Muslim scholars regularly described Aristotle as the "First Teacher". The title "teacher" was first given to Aristotle by Muslim scholars, and was later used by Western philosophers (as in the famous poem of Dante) who were influenced by the tradition of Islamic philosophy.
   −
Aristotle's Rhetoric proposes that a speaker can use three basic kinds of appeals to persuade his audience: ethos (an appeal to the speaker's character), pathos (an appeal to the audience's emotion), and logos (an appeal to logical reasoning). He also categorizes rhetoric into three genres: epideictic (ceremonial speeches dealing with praise or blame), forensic (judicial speeches over guilt or innocence), and deliberative (speeches calling on an audience to make a decision on an issue). Aristotle also outlines two kinds of rhetorical proofs: enthymeme (proof by syllogism) and paradeigma (proof by example).
+
Aristotle是早期伊斯兰教神学派别最受尊敬的西方思想家之一。现存的Aristotle的大部分著作,以及一些希腊原文注释,被翻译成阿拉伯语,被穆斯林哲学家,科学家和学者研究。阿维罗伊斯Averroes、阿维森纳Avicenna和阿尔法拉比乌斯Alpharabius对Aristotle的著述颇有深度,他们也影响了托马斯 · 阿奎那Thomas Aquinas和其他西方基督教哲学家。阿尔金杜斯Alkindus非常推崇亚里士多德的哲学,Avicenna称Aristotle是未来所有哲学家的“典范”。中世纪的穆斯林学者经常把亚里士多德称为“第一导师”。“老师”这个头衔最初是由穆斯林学者赋予Aristotle的,后来受到伊斯兰哲学传统的影响,西方哲学家也使用这个称号(如但丁的著名诗歌)
   −
Aristotle的《修辞学》提出,演讲者可以使用三种基本的呼吁来说服他的听众:ethos(对演讲者性格的呼吁)、pathos(对听众情感的呼吁)和logos(对逻辑推理的呼吁)。他还将修辞分为三种类型:epideictic(礼仪性演讲,涉及赞美或指责)、forensic(司法性演讲,涉及有罪或无罪)和deliberative(呼吁听众就某一问题做出决定的演讲)。Aristotle还概述了两种修辞学的证明:省略推理法(推论证明)和paradeigma(例证证明)。
        −
Aristotle writes in his ''Poetics'' that [[epic poetry]], tragedy, comedy, [[Dithyramb|dithyrambic poetry]], painting, sculpture, music, and dance are all fundamentally acts of ''[[mimesis]]'' ("imitation"), each varying in imitation by medium, object, and manner.{{sfn| Halliwell | 2002 | pp=152–59}}{{sfn| Poetics | p= I 1447a}} He applies the term ''mimesis'' both as a property of a work of art and also as the product of the artist's intention{{sfn| Halliwell | 2002 | pp=152–59}} and contends that the audience's realisation of the ''mimesis'' is vital to understanding the work itself.{{sfn| Halliwell | 2002 | pp=152–59}} Aristotle states that ''mimesis'' is a natural instinct of humanity that separates humans from animals{{sfn| Halliwell | 2002 | pp=152–59}}{{sfn| Poetics | p= IV}} and that all human artistry "follows the pattern of nature".{{sfn| Halliwell | 2002 | pp=152–59}} Because of this, Aristotle believed that each of the mimetic arts possesses what [[Stephen Halliwell (academic)|Stephen Halliwell]] calls "highly structured procedures for the achievement of their purposes."{{sfn| Halliwell | 2002 | pp=152–59}} For example, music imitates with the media of rhythm and harmony, whereas dance imitates with rhythm alone, and poetry with language. The forms also differ in their object of imitation. Comedy, for instance, is a dramatic imitation of men worse than average; whereas tragedy imitates men slightly better than average. Lastly, the forms differ in their manner of imitation – through narrative or character, through change or no change, and through drama or no drama.{{sfn| Poetics | p=III}}
     −
Aristotle writes in his Poetics that epic poetry, tragedy, comedy, dithyrambic poetry, painting, sculpture, music, and dance are all fundamentally acts of mimesis ("imitation"), each varying in imitation by medium, object, and manner. He applies the term mimesis both as a property of a work of art and also as the product of the artist's intention and contends that the audience's realisation of the mimesis is vital to understanding the work itself. Aristotle states that mimesis is a natural instinct of humanity that separates humans from animals and that all human artistry "follows the pattern of nature". Because of this, Aristotle believed that each of the mimetic arts possesses what Stephen Halliwell calls "highly structured procedures for the achievement of their purposes." For example, music imitates with the media of rhythm and harmony, whereas dance imitates with rhythm alone, and poetry with language. The forms also differ in their object of imitation. Comedy, for instance, is a dramatic imitation of men worse than average; whereas tragedy imitates men slightly better than average. Lastly, the forms differ in their manner of imitation – through narrative or character, through change or no change, and through drama or no drama.
     −
Aristotle在他的《诗学》中写道,史诗、悲剧、喜剧、二律诗、绘画、雕塑、音乐和舞蹈从根本上说都是模仿行为(“模仿”) ,每一种都因媒介、对象和方式的不同而不同。他把拟态一词既作为艺术作品的一种属性,又作为艺术家意图的产物,认为观众对拟态的实现对理解作品本身至关重要。亚里士多德指出,拟态是人类区别于动物的一种自然本能,人类的一切艺术创作都 "遵循自然的模式"。正因为如此,Aristotle认为,每一种模仿艺术都拥有斯蒂芬•哈利维尔所说的 "实现其目的的高度结构化的程序"。例如,音乐是以节奏与和谐为媒介进行模仿的,而舞蹈则仅以节奏进行模仿,诗歌则以语言进行模仿。在模仿的对象上,形式也有所不同。比如喜剧是模仿比一般人差的人的戏剧性;而悲剧则是模仿比一般人稍好的人。最后,形式在模仿的方式上也有不同——通过叙事或人物,通过变化或不变化,通过戏剧或不戏剧。
+
===On medieval Europe===
 +
在中世纪的欧洲
    +
{{anchor|Phyllis}}
   −
While it is believed that Aristotle's ''Poetics'' originally comprised two books – one on comedy and one on tragedy – only the portion that focuses on tragedy has survived. Aristotle taught that tragedy is composed of six elements: plot-structure, character, style, thought, spectacle, and lyric poetry.{{sfn| Poetics | p=VI}} The characters in a tragedy are merely a means of driving the story; and the plot, not the characters, is the chief focus of tragedy. Tragedy is the imitation of action arousing pity and fear, and is meant to effect the [[catharsis]] of those same emotions. Aristotle concludes ''Poetics'' with a discussion on which, if either, is superior: epic or tragic mimesis. He suggests that because tragedy possesses all the attributes of an epic, possibly possesses additional attributes such as spectacle and music, is more unified, and achieves the aim of its mimesis in shorter scope, it can be considered superior to epic.{{sfn| Poetics | p=XXVI}} Aristotle was a keen systematic collector of riddles, folklore, and proverbs; he and his school had a special interest in the riddles of the [[Pythia|Delphic Oracle]] and studied the fables of [[Aesop]].{{sfn| Aesop | 1998 | pages=Introduction, xi–xii}}
+
[[File:Aristotle and Phyllis.jpg | thumb | upright | left | Woodcut of [[The tale of Phyllis and Aristotle|Aristotle ridden by Phyllis]] by [[Hans Baldung]], 1515{{sfn|Phyllis and Aristotle}}]]
   −
While it is believed that Aristotle's Poetics originally comprised two books – one on comedy and one on tragedy – only the portion that focuses on tragedy has survived. Aristotle taught that tragedy is composed of six elements: plot-structure, character, style, thought, spectacle, and lyric poetry. The characters in a tragedy are merely a means of driving the story; and the plot, not the characters, is the chief focus of tragedy. Tragedy is the imitation of action arousing pity and fear, and is meant to effect the catharsis of those same emotions. Aristotle concludes Poetics with a discussion on which, if either, is superior: epic or tragic mimesis. He suggests that because tragedy possesses all the attributes of an epic, possibly possesses additional attributes such as spectacle and music, is more unified, and achieves the aim of its mimesis in shorter scope, it can be considered superior to epic. Aristotle was a keen systematic collector of riddles, folklore, and proverbs; he and his school had a special interest in the riddles of the Delphic Oracle and studied the fables of Aesop.
+
Aristotle ridden by Phyllis by Hans Baldung, 1515
   −
虽然人们认为Aristotle的《诗学》最初是由两部书组成——一部论述喜剧,一部论述悲剧,但只有集中论述悲剧的部分留存了下来。Aristotle认为悲剧由六个要素组成: 情节结构、人物、风格、思想、景观和抒情诗。悲剧中的人物只是推动故事发展的一种手段; 悲剧的主要焦点是情节,而不是人物。悲剧是对引起怜悯和恐惧的行为的模仿,是为了达到宣泄这些相同情感的效果。Aristotle在《诗学》的最后,讨论了史诗和悲剧模仿哪一个更优越。他认为,由于悲剧具有史诗的所有属性,可能还具有诸如景观和音乐等额外的属性,更加统一,并在较短的范围内达到了模仿的目的,因此可以认为它优于史诗。Aristotle热衷于系统地收集谜语、民间传说和谚语; 他和他的学派对特尔菲神谕的谜语特别感兴趣,并研究了伊索寓言。
+
菲利斯骑在亚里士多德身上,汉斯 · 巴尔顿,1515
    +
{{further|Aristotelianism|Syllogism#Medieval}}
    +
With the loss of the study of ancient Greek in the early [[medieval]] Latin West, Aristotle was practically unknown there from c. AD 600 to c. 1100 except through the Latin translation of the ''Organon'' made by [[Boethius]]. In the twelfth and thirteenth centuries, interest in Aristotle revived and Latin Christians had translations made, both from Arabic translations, such as those by [[Gerard of Cremona]],{{sfn| Hasse | 2014}} and from the original Greek, such as those by [[James of Venice]] and [[William of Moerbeke]]. After the [[Scholasticism|Scholastic]] Thomas Aquinas wrote his ''[[Summa Theologica]]'', working from Moerbeke's translations and calling Aristotle "The Philosopher",{{sfn|Aquinas|2013}} the demand for Aristotle's writings grew, and the [[Greek language|Greek]] manuscripts returned to the West, stimulating a revival of Aristotelianism in Europe that continued into the [[Renaissance]].{{sfn| Kuhn | 2018}} These thinkers blended Aristotelian philosophy with Christianity, bringing the thought of Ancient Greece into the Middle Ages. Scholars such as Boethius, [[Peter Abelard]], and [[John Buridan]] worked on Aristotelian logic.{{sfn| Lagerlund}}
   −
===Views on women===
+
With the loss of the study of ancient Greek in the early medieval Latin West, Aristotle was practically unknown there from c. AD 600 to c. 1100 except through the Latin translation of the Organon made by Boethius. In the twelfth and thirteenth centuries, interest in Aristotle revived and Latin Christians had translations made, both from Arabic translations, such as those by Gerard of Cremona, and from the original Greek, such as those by James of Venice and William of Moerbeke. After the Scholastic Thomas Aquinas wrote his Summa Theologica, working from Moerbeke's translations and calling Aristotle "The Philosopher", the demand for Aristotle's writings grew, and the Greek manuscripts returned to the West, stimulating a revival of Aristotelianism in Europe that continued into the Renaissance. These thinkers blended Aristotelian philosophy with Christianity, bringing the thought of Ancient Greece into the Middle Ages. Scholars such as Boethius, Peter Abelard, and John Buridan worked on Aristotelian logic.
对女性的看法
     −
{{main | Aristotle's views on women}}
+
随着中世纪早期拉丁美洲对古希腊文研究的缺失,Aristotle在公元600年到公元1100年期间几乎不为人所知,除了通过对波伊提乌斯Boethius《工具论》的拉丁文翻译。在12世纪和13世纪,人们对亚里士多德重新有了兴趣,拉丁基督徒也有译本,既有阿拉伯译本,如克雷莫纳的杰拉德,也有原希腊译本,如威尼斯的雅各和莫尔比克的威廉。在经院哲学家Thomas Aquinas 根据莫尔贝克Moerbeke的译本写了《神学年鉴》后,人们对Aristotle作品的需求增加了,希腊手稿也回到了西方,刺激了Aristotle主义在欧洲的复兴,并持续到文艺复兴时期。这些思想家将亚里士多德哲学与基督教相结合,将古希腊思想带入中世纪。Boethius、彼得 · 阿贝拉尔Peter Abelard和约翰 · 布里丹John Buridan等学者致力于亚里士多德逻辑学。
   −
{{further | Aristotle's biology#Inheritance}}
     −
Aristotle's analysis of procreation describes an active, ensouling masculine element bringing life to an inert, passive female element. On this ground, proponents of [[feminist metaphysics]] have accused Aristotle of [[misogyny]]{{sfn| Freeland | 1998}} and [[sexism]].{{sfn| Morsink | 1979 | pp=83–112}} However, Aristotle gave equal weight to women's happiness as he did to men's, and commented in his ''Rhetoric'' that the things that lead to happiness need to be in women as well as men.{{efn-ua | "Where, as among the Lacedaemonians, the state of women is bad, almost half of human life is spoilt."{{sfn| Rhetoric | p=Book I, Chapter 5}}}}
+
The medieval English poet [[Geoffrey Chaucer|Chaucer]] describes his student as being happy by having
   −
Aristotle's analysis of procreation describes an active, ensouling masculine element bringing life to an inert, passive female element. On this ground, proponents of feminist metaphysics have accused Aristotle of misogyny and sexism. However, Aristotle gave equal weight to women's happiness as he did to men's, and commented in his Rhetoric that the things that lead to happiness need to be in women as well as men.
+
The medieval English poet Chaucer describes his student as being happy by having
   −
Aristotle对生育的分析描述了一个主动的、合体的男性元素给一个惰性的、被动的女性元素带来生命。基于此,女权主义形而上学的支持者指责Aristotle厌恶女性和性别歧视。然而,Aristotle对女人的幸福和对男人的幸福给予了同等的重视,并在他的修辞学中评论说,通向幸福的东西幸福的东西既要在妇女身上,也要在男子身上。
+
中世纪英国诗人乔叟这样描述他的学生: 因为拥有他而感到快乐
      −
==Influence==
  −
影响
     −
{{see | List of writers influenced by Aristotle}}
+
{{quote | <poem>at his beddes heed
 +
Twenty bookes, clad in blak or reed,
 +
{{quote | <poem>at his beddes heed
 +
Of aristotle and his philosophie,</poem>}}
   −
更多信息:受Aristotle影响的作家名单
+
他宁可在他的床头前
More than 2300 years after his death, Aristotle remains one of the most influential people who ever lived.{{sfn| Leroi | 2015 | p=8}}{{sfn| Aristotle's Influence | 2018}} He contributed to almost every field of human knowledge then in existence, and he was the founder of many new fields. According to the philosopher [[Bryan Magee]], "it is doubtful whether any human being has ever known as much as he did".{{sfn| Magee | 2010 | page=34}} Among countless other achievements, Aristotle was the founder of [[formal logic]],{{sfn| Guthrie | 1990 | page=156}}<!--{{sfn| Case | p=518}}--> pioneered the study of [[zoology]], and left every future scientist and philosopher in his debt through his contributions to the scientific method.{{sfn| Aristotle (Greek philosopher)}}{{sfn| Durant | 2006 | page=92}}{{sfn| Kukkonen | 2010 | pages=70–77}} Taneli Kukkonen, writing in ''The Classical Tradition'', observes that his achievement in founding two sciences is unmatched, and his reach in influencing "every branch of intellectual enterprise" including Western ethical and political theory, theology, rhetoric and literary analysis is equally long. As a result, Kukkonen argues, any analysis of reality today "will almost certainly carry Aristotelian overtones ... evidence of an exceptionally forceful mind."{{sfn| Kukkonen | 2010 | pages=70–77}} [[Jonathan Barnes]] wrote that "an account of Aristotle's intellectual afterlife would be little less than a history of European thought".{{sfn| Barnes | 1982 | page=86}}
+
摆上二十本书,黑的或红的封面,
 +
那是亚里士多德和他的哲学
   −
More than 2300 years after his death, Aristotle remains one of the most influential people who ever lived. He contributed to almost every field of human knowledge then in existence, and he was the founder of many new fields. According to the philosopher Bryan Magee, "it is doubtful whether any human being has ever known as much as he did". Among countless other achievements, Aristotle was the founder of formal logic,<!----> pioneered the study of zoology, and left every future scientist and philosopher in his debt through his contributions to the scientific method. Taneli Kukkonen, writing in The Classical Tradition, observes that his achievement in founding two sciences is unmatched, and his reach in influencing "every branch of intellectual enterprise" including Western ethical and political theory, theology, rhetoric and literary analysis is equally long. As a result, Kukkonen argues, any analysis of reality today "will almost certainly carry Aristotelian overtones ... evidence of an exceptionally forceful mind." Jonathan Barnes wrote that "an account of Aristotle's intellectual afterlife would be little less than a history of European thought".
+
A [[The tale of Phyllis and Aristotle|cautionary medieval tale]] held that Aristotle advised his pupil Alexander to avoid the king's seductive mistress, Phyllis, but was himself captivated by her, and allowed her to ride him. Phyllis had secretly told Alexander what to expect, and he witnessed Phyllis proving that a woman's charms could overcome even the greatest philosopher's male intellect. Artists such as [[Hans Baldung]] produced a series of illustrations of the popular theme.{{sfn| Aristotle Phyllis}}{{sfn|Phyllis and Aristotle}}
   −
Aristotle去世2300多年后,他仍然是有史以来最有影响力的人物之一。他对当时存在的人类知识的几乎每一个领域都做出了贡献,他还是许多新领域的创始人。哲学家布莱恩 · 马吉Bryan Magee认为,“很怀疑是否有人像他一样知道这么多。”。在无数的成就中,Aristotle是形式逻辑的创始人,开创了动物学研究,他对科学方法的贡献让每一个未来的科学家和哲学家都感激不尽。狄克礼•库克宁Taneli Kukkonen 在《古典传统》一书中写道,他在创立两门科学方面的成就是无与伦比的,他在影响“知识事业的每一个分支” ,包括西方伦理和政治理论、神学、修辞学和文学分析的影响也同样长久。因此,Kukkonen 认为,今天对现实的任何分析“几乎肯定会带有Aristotle的色彩... ... 证明他的思想异常强大。”乔纳森•巴恩斯Jonathan Barnes写道: “对Aristotle的知识后世的描述将不亚于一部欧洲思想史。”。
+
A cautionary medieval tale held that Aristotle advised his pupil Alexander to avoid the king's seductive mistress, Phyllis, but was himself captivated by her, and allowed her to ride him. Phyllis had secretly told Alexander what to expect, and he witnessed Phyllis proving that a woman's charms could overcome even the greatest philosopher's male intellect. Artists such as Hans Baldung produced a series of illustrations of the popular theme.
    +
在一个中世纪的警世故事中,Aristotle建议他的学生亚历山大避开国王的情妇菲利斯,但他自己却被她迷住了,允许她骑在他身上。菲利斯Phyllis秘密地告诉亚历山大接下来会发生什么,他目睹了Phyllis证明了一个女人的魅力可以战胜哪怕是最伟大的哲学家的男性智慧。艺术家如汉斯•巴尔顿Hans Baldung创作了一系列插图的流行主题。
   −
===On his successor, Theophrastus===
+
The Italian poet Dante says of Aristotle in ''[[The Divine Comedy]]'':
   −
他的后继者泰奥弗拉斯托斯
+
The Italian poet Dante says of Aristotle in The Divine Comedy:
   −
[[File:161Theophrastus 161 frontespizio.jpg | thumb | upright | [[Book frontispiece|Frontispiece]] to a 1644 version of [[Theophrastus]]'s ''[[Historia Plantarum (Theophrastus)|Historia Plantarum]]'', originally written around 300 BC]]
+
意大利诗人但丁在《神曲》中这样评价Aristotle:
   −
Frontispiece to a 1644 version of Theophrastus's Historia Plantarum, originally written around 300 BC
     −
Theophrastus的《植物历史》1644年版本的卷首插图,最初写于公元前300年左右
     −
{{main | Theophrastus | Historia Plantarum (Theophrastus)}}
+
{| class="wikitable" style="font-size: 85%;"
   −
Aristotle's pupil and successor, [[Theophrastus]], wrote the ''[[Historia Plantarum (Theophrastus)|History of Plants]]'', a pioneering work in botany. Some of his technical terms remain in use, such as [[carpel]] from ''carpos'', fruit, and [[pericarp]], from ''pericarpion'', seed chamber.{{sfn| Hooker | 1831 | page=219}}
+
{ | class = “ wikable” style = “ font-size: 85% ; ”
Theophrastus was much less concerned with formal causes than Aristotle was, instead pragmatically describing how plants functioned.{{sfn| Mayr | 1982 | pp= 90–91}}{{sfn| Mason | 1979 | p= 46}}
     −
Aristotle's pupil and successor, Theophrastus, wrote the History of Plants, a pioneering work in botany. Some of his technical terms remain in use, such as carpel from carpos, fruit, and pericarp, from pericarpion, seed chamber. Theophrastus was much less concerned with formal causes than Aristotle was, instead pragmatically describing how plants functioned.
+
|+
   −
Aristotle的学生和后继者Theophrastus撰写了植物学史,这是一部植物学的开创性著作。他的某些技术术语仍然在使用,如心皮,果实,果皮,从外皮,种子室。与亚里士多德相比,Theophrastus对形式上的原因的关注要少得多,而是实事求是地描述植物是如何运作的。
+
|+
    +
{| class="wikitable" style="font-size: 85%;"
    +
! Dante<br>L'Inferno, Canto IV. 131–135 !! Translation<br>Hell
   −
===On later Greek philosophers===
+
!但丁《地狱篇》 ,第四章。131–135 !!地狱
关于后来的希腊哲学家
  −
{{further | Peripatetic school}}
     −
The immediate influence of Aristotle's work was felt as the Lyceum grew into the [[Peripatetic school]]. Aristotle's notable students included [[Aristoxenus]], [[Dicaearchus]], [[Demetrius of Phalerum]], [[Eudemos of Rhodes]], [[Harpalus]], [[Hephaestion]], [[Mnason of Phocis]], [[Nicomachus (son of Aristotle)|Nicomachus]], and Theophrastus. Aristotle's influence over Alexander the Great is seen in the latter's bringing with him on his expedition a host of zoologists, botanists, and researchers. He had also learned a great deal about Persian customs and traditions from his teacher. Although his respect for Aristotle was diminished as his travels made it clear that much of Aristotle's geography was clearly wrong, when the old philosopher released his works to the public, Alexander complained "Thou hast not done well to publish thy acroamatic doctrines; for in what shall I surpass other men if those doctrines wherein I have been trained are to be all men's common property?"{{sfn| Plutarch | 1919 | p= Part 1, 7:7}}
+
|+
   −
The immediate influence of Aristotle's work was felt as the Lyceum grew into the Peripatetic school. Aristotle's notable students included Aristoxenus, Dicaearchus, Demetrius of Phalerum, Eudemos of Rhodes, Harpalus, Hephaestion, Mnason of Phocis, Nicomachus, and Theophrastus. Aristotle's influence over Alexander the Great is seen in the latter's bringing with him on his expedition a host of zoologists, botanists, and researchers. He had also learned a great deal about Persian customs and traditions from his teacher. Although his respect for Aristotle was diminished as his travels made it clear that much of Aristotle's geography was clearly wrong, when the old philosopher released his works to the public, Alexander complained "Thou hast not done well to publish thy acroamatic doctrines; for in what shall I surpass other men if those doctrines wherein I have been trained are to be all men's common property?"
+
|-
   −
当吕克昂学院发展成为逍遥学派时,Aristotle的作品随即产生了影响。Aristotle著名的学生包括阿里斯托克西努斯Aristoxenus、狄卡伊尔库斯Dicaearchus、法勒鲁姆的德米特里Demetrius of Phalerum、罗得岛的尤德莫斯Eudemos of Rhodes、哈帕卢斯Harpalus、 赫菲谢耳Hephaestion、  弗西斯的姆纳松Mnason of Phocis、尼各马库斯Nicomachus和Theophrastus。Aristotle对Alexandria大帝的影响体现在Alexandria大帝远征时带来的大批动物学家、植物学家和研究人员。他还从他的老师那里学到了很多关于波斯风俗和传统的知识。尽管他对Aristotle的尊敬有所减弱,因为他的远征清楚地表明,Aristotle的许多地理学说显然是错误的,但当这位老哲学家将他的作品公之于众时,Alexandria抱怨道: “你发表你的晦涩难懂的学说并不好,因为如果我所接受的这些学说成为所有人的共同财产,那么我还能在什么方面超越其他人呢? ”
+
|-
    +
! [[Dante Alighieri|Dante]]<br>''L'Inferno'', Canto IV. 131–135 !! Translation<br>''Hell''
    +
|<poem>vidi 'l maestro di color che sanno
    +
|<poem>vidi 'l maestro di color che sanno
    +
|-
   −
===On Hellenistic science===
+
seder tra filosofica famiglia.
关于希腊化科学
     −
{{details | Ancient Greek medicine}}
+
[咒语]。
更多信息:古希腊医学
     −
After Theophrastus, the Lyceum failed to produce any original work. Though interest in Aristotle's ideas survived, they were generally taken unquestioningly.{{sfn| Annas | 2001 | page=252}} It is not until the age of [[Alexandria]] under the [[Ptolemaic Kingdom|Ptolemies]] that advances in biology can be again found.
+
|<poem>vidi 'l maestro di color che sanno
   −
After Theophrastus, the Lyceum failed to produce any original work. Though interest in Aristotle's ideas survived, they were generally taken unquestioningly. It is not until the age of Alexandria under the Ptolemies that advances in biology can be again found.
+
seder tra filosofica famiglia.
   −
在Theophrastus之后,吕克昂学院未能创作出任何原创作品。尽管人们对Aristotle思想的兴趣依然存在,但人们普遍毫无疑问地接受了这些思想。直到托勒密统治下的亚历山大时代,生物学的进步才得以重见天日。
+
Tutti lo miran, tutti onor li fanno:
    +
quivi vid'ïo Socrate e Platone
   −
The first medical teacher at Alexandria, [[Herophilos|Herophilus of Chalcedon]], corrected Aristotle, placing intelligence in the brain, and connected the nervous system to motion and sensation. Herophilus also distinguished between [[vein]]s and [[artery|arteries]], noting that the latter [[pulse]] while the former do not.{{sfn| Mason | 1979 | p= 56}} Though a few ancient [[atomism|atomists]] such as [[Lucretius]] challenged the [[teleology|teleological]] viewpoint of Aristotelian ideas about life, teleology (and after the rise of Christianity, [[natural theology]]) would remain central to biological thought essentially until the 18th and 19th centuries. [[Ernst Mayr]] states that there was "nothing of any real consequence in biology after Lucretius and Galen until the Renaissance."{{sfn| Mayr | 1985 | pp=90–94}}
+
che 'nnanzi a li altri più presso li stanno;</poem>||<poem>
 +
I saw the Master there of those who know,
   −
The first medical teacher at Alexandria, Herophilus of Chalcedon, corrected Aristotle, placing intelligence in the brain, and connected the nervous system to motion and sensation. Herophilus also distinguished between veins and arteries, noting that the latter pulse while the former do not. Though a few ancient atomists such as Lucretius challenged the teleological viewpoint of Aristotelian ideas about life, teleology (and after the rise of Christianity, natural theology) would remain central to biological thought essentially until the 18th and 19th centuries. Ernst Mayr states that there was "nothing of any real consequence in biology after Lucretius and Galen until the Renaissance."
+
我在那里见到了那位为人所知的大师,
   −
亚历山大的第一位医学老师,来自查尔斯顿的赫罗菲菲罗斯Herophilus,纠正了Aristotle的错误,将智慧置于大脑,并将神经系统与运动和感觉联系起来。Herophilus还区分了静脉和动脉,指出后者有脉搏,而前者没有。尽管少数古代原子论者,如 卢克莱修斯Lucretius挑战了Aristotle关于生命的心学观点,但心学(以及基督教兴起后的自然神学)在18、19世纪之前基本上仍然是生物学思想的核心。恩斯特 · 迈尔Ernst Mayr 说,“在Lucretius和盖伦Galen之后,直到文艺复兴时期,生物学上没有任何实质性的结果。”
+
Amid the philosophic family,
   −
===On Byzantine scholars===
+
在哲学家族中,
关于拜占庭学者
     −
{{see also | Commentaries on Aristotle | Byzantine Aristotelianism}}
+
By all admired, and by all reverenced;
   −
另请参阅:亚里士多德和拜占庭亚里士多德主义评论
+
受到所有人的敬仰和崇敬;
   −
Greek Christian scribes played a crucial role in the preservation of Aristotle by copying all the extant Greek language manuscripts of the corpus. The first Greek Christians to comment extensively on Aristotle were Philoponus, Elias, and David in the sixth century, and [[Stephen of Alexandria]] in the early seventh century.{{sfn| Sorabji | 1990 | pages=20, 28, 35–36}} [[John Philoponus]] stands out for having attempted a fundamental critique of Aristotle's views on the eternity of the world, movement, and other elements of Aristotelian thought.{{sfn| Sorabji | 1990 | pages=233–74}} Philoponus questioned Aristotle's teaching of physics, noting its flaws and introducing the [[theory of impetus]] to explain his observations.{{sfn|Lindberg|1992|p=162}}
+
There Plato too I saw, and Socrates,
   −
Greek Christian scribes played a crucial role in the preservation of Aristotle by copying all the extant Greek language manuscripts of the corpus. The first Greek Christians to comment extensively on Aristotle were Philoponus, Elias, and David in the sixth century, and Stephen of Alexandria in the early seventh century. John Philoponus stands out for having attempted a fundamental critique of Aristotle's views on the eternity of the world, movement, and other elements of Aristotelian thought. Philoponus questioned Aristotle's teaching of physics, noting its flaws and introducing the theory of impetus to explain his observations.
+
在那里我也看到了柏拉图和苏格拉底,
   −
希腊基督教抄写员抄写了所有现存的希腊语手稿,对保存Aristotle的著作起到了至关重要的作用。第一个广泛评论Aristotle的希腊基督徒是六世纪的斐洛波诺斯Philoponus、以利亚Elias和大卫David,以及七世纪初的亚历山大•斯蒂芬Stephen of Alexandria 。John Philoponus站出来,因为他试图对Aristotle关于世界永恒、运动和Aristotle思想的其他要素观点进行根本性的批判。Philoponus质疑Aristotle的物理学教学,指出其缺陷,并引入了动力理论来解释他的观察。
+
Who stood beside him closer than the rest.
    +
站在他身边的人比其他人都近。
   −
After a hiatus of several centuries, formal commentary by Eustratius and [[Michael of Ephesus]] reappeared in the late eleventh and early twelfth centuries, apparently sponsored by [[Anna Comnena]].{{sfn|Sorabji|1990|pp=20–21, 28–29, 393–406, 407–08}}
+
</poem>
   −
After a hiatus of several centuries, formal commentary by Eustratius and Michael of Ephesus reappeared in the late eleventh and early twelfth centuries, apparently sponsored by Anna Comnena.
+
</诗歌 >
   −
在中断了几个世纪之后,以弗所的 尤斯特拉修斯和米迦勒 Michael 的正式评论在11世纪末和12世纪初重新出现,显然是由 安娜•康姆纳Anna Comnena 发起的。
+
|}
    +
|}
    +
</poem>
   −
===On the medieval Islamic world===
+
|}
在中世纪的伊斯兰世界
     −
{{further|Logic in Islamic philosophy|Transmission of the Greek Classics}}
     −
[[File:Arabic aristotle.jpg | thumb|upright | Islamic portrayal of Aristotle, c. 1220]]
+
===On Early Modern scientists===
 +
论早期现代科学家
   −
Islamic portrayal of Aristotle, c. 1220
+
[[File:William Harvey ( 1578-1657) Venenbild.jpg | thumb | [[William Harvey]]'s ''[[Exercitatio Anatomica de Motu Cordis et Sanguinis in Animalibus|De Motu Cordis]]'', 1628, showed that the [[circulation of the blood|blood circulated]], contrary to classical era thinking.]]
   −
伊斯兰对亚里士多德的描绘,约1220年
+
[[William Harvey's De Motu Cordis, 1628, showed that the blood circulated, contrary to classical era thinking.]]
   −
Aristotle was one of the most revered Western thinkers in early [[Islamic theology]]. Most of the still extant works of Aristotle,{{sfn|Kennedy-Day|1998}} as well as a number of the original Greek commentaries, were translated into Arabic and studied by Muslim philosophers, scientists and scholars. [[Averroes]], [[Avicenna]] and [[Alpharabius]], who wrote on Aristotle in great depth, also influenced [[Thomas Aquinas]] and other Western Christian scholastic philosophers. [[Alkindus]] greatly admired Aristotle's philosophy,{{sfn|Staley|1989}} and Averroes spoke of Aristotle as the "exemplar" for all future philosophers.{{sfn|Averroes|1953|p=III, 2, 43}} Medieval Muslim scholars regularly described Aristotle as the "First Teacher".{{sfn|Kennedy-Day|1998}} The title "teacher" was first given to Aristotle by Muslim scholars, and was later used by Western philosophers (as in the famous poem of [[Dante Alighieri|Dante]]) who were influenced by the tradition of [[Islamic philosophy]].{{sfn|Nasr|1996|pp=59–60}}
+
[威廉 · 哈维(William Harvey)的于1628年出版的《De Motu Cordis》表明,血液循环与古典时代的思想相反。
   −
Aristotle was one of the most revered Western thinkers in early Islamic theology. Most of the still extant works of Aristotle, as well as a number of the original Greek commentaries, were translated into Arabic and studied by Muslim philosophers, scientists and scholars. Averroes, Avicenna and Alpharabius, who wrote on Aristotle in great depth, also influenced Thomas Aquinas and other Western Christian scholastic philosophers. Alkindus greatly admired Aristotle's philosophy, and Averroes spoke of Aristotle as the "exemplar" for all future philosophers. Medieval Muslim scholars regularly described Aristotle as the "First Teacher". The title "teacher" was first given to Aristotle by Muslim scholars, and was later used by Western philosophers (as in the famous poem of Dante) who were influenced by the tradition of Islamic philosophy.
+
In the [[Early Modern]] period, scientists such as [[William Harvey]] in England and [[Galileo Galilei]] in Italy reacted against the theories of Aristotle and other classical era thinkers like [[Galen]], establishing new theories based to some degree on observation and experiment. Harvey demonstrated the [[circulation of the blood]], establishing that the heart functioned as a pump rather than being the seat of the soul and the controller of the body's heat, as Aristotle thought.{{sfn| Aird | 2011 | pp=118–29}} Galileo used more doubtful arguments to displace Aristotle's physics, proposing that bodies all fall at the same speed whatever their weight.{{sfn| Machamer | 2017}}
   −
Aristotle是早期伊斯兰教神学派别最受尊敬的西方思想家之一。现存的Aristotle的大部分著作,以及一些希腊原文注释,被翻译成阿拉伯语,被穆斯林哲学家,科学家和学者研究。阿维罗伊斯Averroes、阿维森纳Avicenna和阿尔法拉比乌斯Alpharabius对Aristotle的著述颇有深度,他们也影响了托马斯 · 阿奎那Thomas Aquinas和其他西方基督教哲学家。阿尔金杜斯Alkindus非常推崇亚里士多德的哲学,Avicenna称Aristotle是未来所有哲学家的“典范”。中世纪的穆斯林学者经常把亚里士多德称为“第一导师”。“老师”这个头衔最初是由穆斯林学者赋予Aristotle的,后来受到伊斯兰哲学传统的影响,西方哲学家也使用这个称号(如但丁的著名诗歌)。
+
In the Early Modern period, scientists such as William Harvey in England and Galileo Galilei in Italy reacted against the theories of Aristotle and other classical era thinkers like Galen, establishing new theories based to some degree on observation and experiment. Harvey demonstrated the circulation of the blood, establishing that the heart functioned as a pump rather than being the seat of the soul and the controller of the body's heat, as Aristotle thought. Galileo used more doubtful arguments to displace Aristotle's physics, proposing that bodies all fall at the same speed whatever their weight.
    +
在近代早期,英国的威廉 · 哈维William Harvey和意大利的伽利略 · 伽利雷Galileo Galilei等科学家反对Aristotle和其他古典时代思想家如盖伦的理论,一定程度上建立了以观察和实验为基础的新理论。哈维证明了血液循环,证明了心脏作为一个泵的功能,而不是像Aristotle认为的那样,是灵魂的所在地和身体热量的控制器。伽利略用更多值得怀疑的论点来取代Aristotle的物理学,他提出物体不论重量大小,下落的速度都是一样的。
       +
===On 19th-century thinkers===
 +
关于19世纪思想家
    +
The 19th-century German philosopher [[Friedrich Nietzsche]] has been said to have taken nearly all of his political philosophy from Aristotle.{{sfn| Durant | 2006 | p=86}} Aristotle rigidly separated action from production, and argued for the deserved subservience of some people ("natural slaves"), and the natural superiority (virtue, ''arete'') of others. It was [[Martin Heidegger]], not Nietzsche, who elaborated a new interpretation of Aristotle, intended to warrant his deconstruction of scholastic and philosophical tradition.{{sfn| Sikka | 1997 | page=265}}
   −
===On medieval Europe===
+
The 19th-century German philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche has been said to have taken nearly all of his political philosophy from Aristotle. Aristotle rigidly separated action from production, and argued for the deserved subservience of some people ("natural slaves"), and the natural superiority (virtue, arete) of others. It was Martin Heidegger, not Nietzsche, who elaborated a new interpretation of Aristotle, intended to warrant his deconstruction of scholastic and philosophical tradition.
在中世纪的欧洲
     −
{{anchor|Phyllis}}
+
据说19世纪德国哲学家弗里德里希·尼采Friedrich Nietzsche的政治哲学几乎全部来自于Aristotle。Aristotle严格地将行动与生产分离开来,并主张某些人(“自然奴隶”)应得的服从,而另一些人的自然优越感(美德,受到尊重)。是马丁·海德格尔Martin Heidegger而不是Nietzsche,阐述了对Aristotle的新诠释,意图证明他对学术和哲学传统的解构。
   −
[[File:Aristotle and Phyllis.jpg | thumb | upright | left | Woodcut of [[The tale of Phyllis and Aristotle|Aristotle ridden by Phyllis]] by [[Hans Baldung]], 1515{{sfn|Phyllis and Aristotle}}]]
+
The English mathematician [[George Boole]] fully accepted Aristotle's logic, but decided "to go under, over, and beyond" it with his system of [[Boolean algebra|algebraic logic]] in his 1854 book ''[[The Laws of Thought]]''. This gives logic a mathematical foundation with equations, enables it to solve equations as well as check [[Validity (logic)|validity]], and allows it to handle a wider class of problems by expanding propositions of any number of terms, not just two.{{sfn| Boole | 2003}}
   −
Aristotle ridden by Phyllis by Hans Baldung, 1515
+
The English mathematician George Boole fully accepted Aristotle's logic, but decided "to go under, over, and beyond" it with his system of algebraic logic in his 1854 book The Laws of Thought. This gives logic a mathematical foundation with equations, enables it to solve equations as well as check validity, and allows it to handle a wider class of problems by expanding propositions of any number of terms, not just two.
   −
菲利斯骑在亚里士多德身上,汉斯 · 巴尔顿,1515
+
英国数学家乔治 · 布尔George Boole 完全接受Aristotle的逻辑学,但在他1854年出版的著作《思想法则》中,他决定用他的代数逻辑系统“超越”它。这就使逻辑学有了方程的数学基础,使它既能解方程,又能检验有效性,并使它能处理更广泛的一类问题,将任意数项的命题扩大,而不仅仅是两个命题。
   −
{{further|Aristotelianism|Syllogism#Medieval}}
     −
With the loss of the study of ancient Greek in the early [[medieval]] Latin West, Aristotle was practically unknown there from c. AD 600 to c. 1100 except through the Latin translation of the ''Organon'' made by [[Boethius]]. In the twelfth and thirteenth centuries, interest in Aristotle revived and Latin Christians had translations made, both from Arabic translations, such as those by [[Gerard of Cremona]],{{sfn| Hasse | 2014}} and from the original Greek, such as those by [[James of Venice]] and [[William of Moerbeke]]. After the [[Scholasticism|Scholastic]] Thomas Aquinas wrote his ''[[Summa Theologica]]'', working from Moerbeke's translations and calling Aristotle "The Philosopher",{{sfn|Aquinas|2013}} the demand for Aristotle's writings grew, and the [[Greek language|Greek]] manuscripts returned to the West, stimulating a revival of Aristotelianism in Europe that continued into the [[Renaissance]].{{sfn| Kuhn | 2018}} These thinkers blended Aristotelian philosophy with Christianity, bringing the thought of Ancient Greece into the Middle Ages. Scholars such as Boethius, [[Peter Abelard]], and [[John Buridan]] worked on Aristotelian logic.{{sfn| Lagerlund}}
+
===Modern rejection and rehabilitation===
 +
现代的废弃和复原
 +
[[File:Alexander and Aristotle.jpg | thumb|upright=1.2 | left | "That most enduring of romantic images, Aristotle tutoring the future conqueror Alexander".{{sfn|Kukkonen|2010|pages=70–77}} Illustration by {{interlanguage link|Charles Laplante|fr}}, 1866]]
   −
With the loss of the study of ancient Greek in the early medieval Latin West, Aristotle was practically unknown there from c. AD 600 to c. 1100 except through the Latin translation of the Organon made by Boethius. In the twelfth and thirteenth centuries, interest in Aristotle revived and Latin Christians had translations made, both from Arabic translations, such as those by Gerard of Cremona, and from the original Greek, such as those by James of Venice and William of Moerbeke. After the Scholastic Thomas Aquinas wrote his Summa Theologica, working from Moerbeke's translations and calling Aristotle "The Philosopher", the demand for Aristotle's writings grew, and the Greek manuscripts returned to the West, stimulating a revival of Aristotelianism in Europe that continued into the Renaissance. These thinkers blended Aristotelian philosophy with Christianity, bringing the thought of Ancient Greece into the Middle Ages. Scholars such as Boethius, Peter Abelard, and John Buridan worked on Aristotelian logic.
     −
随着中世纪早期拉丁美洲对古希腊文研究的缺失,Aristotle在公元600年到公元1100年期间几乎不为人所知,除了通过对波伊提乌斯Boethius《工具论》的拉丁文翻译。在12世纪和13世纪,人们对亚里士多德重新有了兴趣,拉丁基督徒也有译本,既有阿拉伯译本,如克雷莫纳的杰拉德,也有原希腊译本,如威尼斯的雅各和莫尔比克的威廉。在经院哲学家Thomas Aquinas 根据莫尔贝克Moerbeke的译本写了《神学年鉴》后,人们对Aristotle作品的需求增加了,希腊手稿也回到了西方,刺激了Aristotle主义在欧洲的复兴,并持续到文艺复兴时期。这些思想家将亚里士多德哲学与基督教相结合,将古希腊思想带入中世纪。Boethius、彼得 · 阿贝拉尔Peter Abelard和约翰 · 布里丹John Buridan等学者致力于亚里士多德逻辑学。
+
"That most enduring of romantic images, Aristotle tutoring the future conqueror Alexander". Illustration by , 1866
    +
“最经久不衰的浪漫主义形象,是Aristotle教导未来的征服者亚历山大”。插图: 1866
   −
The medieval English poet [[Geoffrey Chaucer|Chaucer]] describes his student as being happy by having
+
During the 20th century, Aristotle's work was widely criticized. The philosopher [[Bertrand Russell]]argued that "almost every serious intellectual advance has had to begin with an attack on some Aristotelian doctrine". Russell called Aristotle's ethics "repulsive", and labelled his logic "as definitely antiquated as Ptolemaic astronomy". Russell stated that these errors made it difficult to do historical justice to Aristotle, until one remembered what an advance he made upon all of his predecessors.{{sfn|Russell|1972}}
   −
The medieval English poet Chaucer describes his student as being happy by having
+
During the 20th century, Aristotle's work was widely criticized. The philosopher Bertrand Russell argued that "almost every serious intellectual advance has had to begin with an attack on some Aristotelian doctrine". Russell called Aristotle's ethics "repulsive", and labelled his logic "as definitely antiquated as Ptolemaic astronomy". Russell stated that these errors made it difficult to do historical justice to Aristotle, until one remembered what an advance he made upon all of his predecessors.
   −
中世纪英国诗人乔叟这样描述他的学生: 因为拥有他而感到快乐
+
在20世纪,Aristotle的著作受到广泛的批评。哲学家伯特兰·罗素Bertrand Russell认为,“几乎每一次重大的知识进步都必须从攻击Aristotle的某些学说开始”。Aristotle的伦理学是“令人厌恶”的 ,并称他的逻辑学“和托勒密Ptolemaic的天文学一样过时”。Russell指出,这些错误使得人们很难公正地看待Aristotle,直到人们想起他对他所有的前辈所做的进步。
    +
The Dutch historian of science [[Eduard Jan Dijksterhuis]] wrote that Aristotle and his predecessors showed the difficulty of science by "proceed[ing] so readily to frame a theory of such a general character" on limited evidence from their senses.{{sfn|Dijksterhuis|1969|p=72}} In 1985, the biologist [[Peter Medawar]] could still state in "pure seventeenth century"{{sfn|Leroi|2015|p=353}} tones that Aristotle had assembled "a strange and generally speaking rather tiresome farrago of hearsay, imperfect observation, wishful thinking and credulity amounting to downright gullibility".{{sfn|Leroi|2015|p=353}}{{sfn|Medawar|Medawar|1984|p=28}}
    +
The Dutch historian of science Eduard Jan Dijksterhuis wrote that Aristotle and his predecessors showed the difficulty of science by "proceed[ing] so readily to frame a theory of such a general character" on limited evidence from their senses. In 1985, the biologist Peter Medawar could still state in "pure seventeenth century" tones that Aristotle had assembled "a strange and generally speaking rather tiresome farrago of hearsay, imperfect observation, wishful thinking and credulity amounting to downright gullibility".
   −
{{quote | <poem>at his beddes heed
+
荷兰科学史家迪克斯特休伊斯爱德华·简 Eduard Jan Dijksterhuis写道,Aristotle和他的前辈们通过 "如此轻易地根据他们的感官提供的有限证据来构筑这样一种一般性的理论",显示了科学的困难。1985年,生物学家彼得•梅达瓦Peter Medawar仍然可以用 "纯正的十七世纪 "的语气说,Aristotle集合了 "一种奇怪的、一般说来相当令人厌烦的传闻、不完善的观察、一厢情愿的想法和相当于完全轻信的可信度"。
Twenty bookes, clad in blak or reed,
  −
{{quote | <poem>at his beddes heed
  −
Of aristotle and his philosophie,</poem>}}
     −
他宁可在他的床头前
+
By the start of the 21st century, however, Aristotle was taken more seriously: Kukkonen noted that "In the best 20th-century scholarship Aristotle comes alive as a thinker wrestling with the full weight of the Greek philosophical tradition."{{sfn|Kukkonen|2010|pp=70–77}} [[Alasdair MacIntyre]] has attempted to reform what he calls the Aristotelian tradition in a way that is anti-elitist and capable of disputing the claims of both liberals and Nietzscheans.{{sfn|Knight|2007|pp=''passim''}} Kukkonen observed, too, that "that most enduring of romantic images, Aristotle tutoring the future conqueror Alexander" remained current, as in the 2004 film ''[[Alexander (2004 film)|Alexander]]'', while the "firm rules" of Aristotle's theory of drama have ensured a role for the ''Poetics'' in [[Cinema of the United States|Hollywood]].{{sfn|Kukkonen|2010|pp=70–77}}
摆上二十本书,黑的或红的封面,
  −
那是亚里士多德和他的哲学
     −
A [[The tale of Phyllis and Aristotle|cautionary medieval tale]] held that Aristotle advised his pupil Alexander to avoid the king's seductive mistress, Phyllis, but was himself captivated by her, and allowed her to ride him. Phyllis had secretly told Alexander what to expect, and he witnessed Phyllis proving that a woman's charms could overcome even the greatest philosopher's male intellect. Artists such as [[Hans Baldung]] produced a series of illustrations of the popular theme.{{sfn| Aristotle Phyllis}}{{sfn|Phyllis and Aristotle}}
+
By the start of the 21st century, however, Aristotle was taken more seriously: Kukkonen noted that "In the best 20th-century scholarship Aristotle comes alive as a thinker wrestling with the full weight of the Greek philosophical tradition." Alasdair MacIntyre has attempted to reform what he calls the Aristotelian tradition in a way that is anti-elitist and capable of disputing the claims of both liberals and Nietzscheans. Kukkonen observed, too, that "that most enduring of romantic images, Aristotle tutoring the future conqueror Alexander" remained current, as in the 2004 film Alexander, while the "firm rules" of Aristotle's theory of drama have ensured a role for the Poetics in Hollywood.
   −
A cautionary medieval tale held that Aristotle advised his pupil Alexander to avoid the king's seductive mistress, Phyllis, but was himself captivated by her, and allowed her to ride him. Phyllis had secretly told Alexander what to expect, and he witnessed Phyllis proving that a woman's charms could overcome even the greatest philosopher's male intellect. Artists such as Hans Baldung produced a series of illustrations of the popular theme.
+
然而,到了21世纪初,Aristotle受到了更多的重视。Kukkonen指出,"在20世纪最好的学术研究中,Aristotle作为一个思想家与希腊哲学传统的全部重量相抗衡,活灵活现。" 阿拉斯戴尔•麦金泰尔Alasdair MacIntyre试图以一种反精英主义的方式改革他所谓的亚里士多德传统,并能够与自由主义者和尼采主义者的主张相争 。Kukkonen 还指出,“Aristotle对未来的征服者亚历山大的指导,是最经久不衰的浪漫主义形象” ,正如2004年的电影《亚历山大》一样,而Aristotle戏剧理论的“坚定规则”确保了《诗学》在好莱坞的地位。
   −
在一个中世纪的警世故事中,Aristotle建议他的学生亚历山大避开国王的情妇菲利斯,但他自己却被她迷住了,允许她骑在他身上。菲利斯Phyllis秘密地告诉亚历山大接下来会发生什么,他目睹了Phyllis证明了一个女人的魅力可以战胜哪怕是最伟大的哲学家的男性智慧。艺术家如汉斯•巴尔顿Hans Baldung创作了一系列插图的流行主题。
+
Biologists continue to be interested in Aristotle's thinking. [[Armand Marie Leroi]] has reconstructed Aristotle's biology,{{sfn|Leroi|2015}} while [[Tinbergen's four questions|Niko Tinbergen's four questions]], based on Aristotle's four causes, are used to analyse [[animal behaviour]]; they examine [[function (biology)|function]], [[phylogeny]], [[mechanism (biology)|mechanism]], and [[ontogeny]].{{sfn|MacDougall-Shackleton|2011|pp=2076–85}}{{sfn|Hladký|Havlíček|2013}}
   −
The Italian poet Dante says of Aristotle in ''[[The Divine Comedy]]'':
+
Biologists continue to be interested in Aristotle's thinking. Armand Marie Leroi has reconstructed Aristotle's biology, while Niko Tinbergen's four questions, based on Aristotle's four causes, are used to analyse animal behaviour; they examine function, phylogeny, mechanism, and ontogeny.
   −
The Italian poet Dante says of Aristotle in The Divine Comedy:
+
生物学家继续对Aristotle的思想感兴趣。阿曼德 · 玛丽 · 莱罗伊Armand Marie Leroi重建了Aristotle的生物学,而尼科 · 廷伯根Niko Tinbergen根据Aristotle的四个原因提出的四个问题,被用来分析动物行为; 他们研究功能、系统发育、机制和个体发育。
   −
意大利诗人但丁在《神曲》中这样评价Aristotle:
         +
==Surviving works==
 +
幸存的作品
   −
{| class="wikitable" style="font-size: 85%;"
+
===Corpus Aristotelicum===
 +
亚里士多德文集
 +
{{main | Corpus Aristotelicum}}
   −
{ | class = “ wikable” style = “ font-size: 85% ; ”
+
[[File:Aristotelis De Moribus ad Nicomachum.jpg | thumb | upright | First page of a 1566 edition of the ''[[Nicomachean Ethics]]'' in Greek and Latin]]
   −
|+
+
First page of a 1566 edition of the [[Nicomachean Ethics in Greek and Latin]]
   −
|+
+
1566年版《希腊文和拉丁文的尼科马奇伦理》的首页
   −
{| class="wikitable" style="font-size: 85%;"
+
The works of Aristotle that have survived from antiquity through medieval manuscript transmission are collected in the Corpus Aristotelicum. These texts, as opposed to Aristotle's lost works, are technical philosophical treatises from within Aristotle's school. Reference to them is made according to the organization of [[Immanuel Bekker]]'s Royal Prussian Academy edition (''Aristotelis Opera edidit Academia Regia Borussica'', Berlin, 1831–1870), which in turn is based on ancient classifications of these works.{{sfn| Aristotelis Opera}}
   −
! Dante<br>L'Inferno, Canto IV. 131–135 !! Translation<br>Hell
+
The works of Aristotle that have survived from antiquity through medieval manuscript transmission are collected in the Corpus Aristotelicum. These texts, as opposed to Aristotle's lost works, are technical philosophical treatises from within Aristotle's school. Reference to them is made according to the organization of Immanuel Bekker's Royal Prussian Academy edition (Aristotelis Opera edidit Academia Regia Borussica, Berlin, 1831–1870), which in turn is based on ancient classifications of these works.
   −
!但丁《地狱篇》 ,第四章。131–135 !!地狱
+
Aristotle的著作是通过中世纪手稿传播而从古代流传下来的,现收藏在亚里士多德文集中。这些文本,相对于Aristotle失传的著作,是Aristotle派内部的技术性哲学论著。参考他们是根据伊曼纽尔贝克的普鲁士皇家学院版(Aristotle的歌剧编辑委员会学术区,柏林,1831-1870年)的编排 ,而这一编排又是基于古代对这些著作的分类来进行的。
   −
|+
     −
|-
+
===Loss and preservation===
 +
损失和保存
 +
{{see | Recovery of Aristotle}}
   −
|-
+
Aristotle wrote his works on papyrus scrolls, the common writing medium of that era.{{efn-ua | "When the Roman dictator Sulla invaded Athens in 86 BC, he brought back to Rome a fantastic prize – Aristotle's library. Books then were papyrus rolls, from 10 to 20 feet long, and since Aristotle's death in 322 BC, worms and damp had done their worst. The rolls needed repairing, and the texts clarifying and copying on to new papyrus (imported from Egypt – Moses' bulrushes). The man in Rome who put Aristotle's library in order was a Greek scholar, Tyrannio."{{sfn| When libraries were | 2001}}}} His writings are divisible into two groups: the "[[exoteric]]", intended for the public, and the "[[esoteric]]", for use within the [[Lyceum (Classical)|Lyceum]] school.{{sfn| Barnes | 1995 | p=12}}{{efn-ua | 1=Aristotle: ''Nicomachean Ethics'' 1102a26–27. Aristotle himself never uses the term "esoteric" or "acroamatic". For other passages where Aristotle speaks of ''exōterikoi logoi'', see [[W.D. Ross]], ''Aristotle's Metaphysics'' (1953), vol. 2 pp= 408–10. Ross defends an interpretation according to which the phrase, at least in Aristotle's own works, usually refers generally to "discussions not peculiar to the [[Peripatetic school]]", rather than to specific works of Aristotle's own.}}{{sfn| House | 1956 | page=35}} Aristotle's "lost" works stray considerably in characterization from the surviving Aristotelian corpus. Whereas the lost works appear to have been originally written with a view to subsequent publication, the surviving works mostly resemble lecture notes not intended for publication.{{sfn| Irwin | Fine | 1996 | pp= xi–xii }}{{sfn| Barnes | 1995 | p=12}} [[Cicero]]'s description of Aristotle's literary style as "a river of gold" must have applied to the published works, not the surviving notes.{{efn-ua | "''veniet flumen orationis aureum fundens Aristoteles''", (Google translation: "Aristotle will come pouring forth a golden stream of eloquence").{{sfn| Cicero | 1874}}}} A major question in the history of Aristotle's works is how the exoteric writings were all lost, and how the ones we now possess came to us.{{sfn| Barnes | Griffin | 1999 | pages=1–69}} The consensus is that Andronicus of Rhodes collected the esoteric works of Aristotle's school which existed in the form of smaller, separate works, distinguished them from those of Theophrastus and other Peripatetics, edited them, and finally compiled them into the more cohesive, larger works as they are known today.{{sfn| Anagnostopoulos | 2013 | page=16}}{{sfn| Barnes | 1995 | pp=10–15}}
   −
! [[Dante Alighieri|Dante]]<br>''L'Inferno'', Canto IV. 131–135 !! Translation<br>''Hell''
+
Aristotle wrote his works on papyrus scrolls, the common writing medium of that era.}His writings are divisible into two groups: the "exoteric", intended for the public, and the "esoteric", for use within the Lyceum school. Aristotle's "lost" works stray considerably in characterization from the surviving Aristotelian corpus. Whereas the lost works appear to have been originally written with a view to subsequent publication, the surviving works mostly resemble lecture notes not intended for publication. Cicero's description of Aristotle's literary style as "a river of gold" must have applied to the published works, not the surviving notes.A major question in the history of Aristotle's works is how the exoteric writings were all lost, and how the ones we now possess came to us. The consensus is that Andronicus of Rhodes collected the esoteric works of Aristotle's school which existed in the form of smaller, separate works, distinguished them from those of Theophrastus and other Peripatetics, edited them, and finally compiled them into the more cohesive, larger works as they are known today.
   −
|<poem>vidi 'l maestro di color che sanno
+
Aristotle把他的作品写在纸莎草纸卷上,这是当时常见的书写媒介。他的著作可分为两类: 面向公众的“通俗”著作,以及在吕克昂学院内部使用的“深奥”著作。Aristotle的 "遗失 "的作品在表征上与现存的亚里士多德文集大相径庭。遗失的作品似乎最初是为了以后的出版而写的,而现存的作品则大多类似于不打算出版的讲义。Aristotle的文学风格描述为“黄金之河” ,这一定适用于已出版的作品,而不是现存的笔记。Aristotle著作史上的一个主要问题是,那些公开的著作是如何全部丢失的,而我们现在拥有的那些著作又是如何来到我们这里的。人们一致认为,罗德岛的Andronicus收集了亚里士多德学派的,以较小的、独立的作品形式存在的深奥作品,将它们与Theophrastus和其他学派的作品区分开来,对它们进行编辑,最后将它们汇编成今天人们所熟知的更具凝聚力的、更大的作品。
   −
|<poem>vidi 'l maestro di color che sanno
     −
|-
+
==Legacy==
 +
遗产
   −
seder tra filosofica famiglia.
+
===Depictions===
 +
叙述
   −
[咒语]。
+
==Paintings==
 +
绘画
   −
|<poem>vidi 'l maestro di color che sanno
+
Aristotle has been depicted by major artists including [[Lucas Cranach the Elder]],{{sfn| Lucas Cranach the Elder}} [[Justus van Gent]], [[Raphael]], [[Paolo Veronese]], [[Jusepe de Ribera]],{{sfn| Lee | Robinson | 2005}} [[Rembrandt]],{{sfn| Aristotle with Bust | 2002}} and [[Francesco Hayez]] over the centuries. Among the best known is Raphael's [[fresco]] ''[[The School of Athens]]'', in the [[Apostolic Palace|Vatican's Apostolic Palace]], where the figures of Plato and Aristotle are central to the image, at the architectural [[vanishing point]], reflecting their importance.{{sfn| Phelan | 2002}} Rembrandt's ''[[Aristotle with a Bust of Homer]]'', too, is a celebrated work, showing the knowing philosopher and the blind Homer from an earlier age: as the art critic [[Jonathan Jones (journalist)|Jonathan Jones]] writes, "this painting will remain one of the greatest and most mysterious in the world, ensnaring us in its musty, glowing, pitch-black, terrible knowledge of time."{{sfn| Held | 1969}}{{sfn| Jones | 2002}}
   −
seder tra filosofica famiglia.
+
<gallery mode="packed" heights="170px">
   −
Tutti lo miran, tutti onor li fanno:
+
“ packed" heights = " 170px" >
   −
quivi vid'ïo Socrate e Platone
+
Aristotle has been depicted by major artists including Lucas Cranach the Elder, Justus van Gent, Raphael, Paolo Veronese, Jusepe de Ribera, Rembrandt, and Francesco Hayez over the centuries. Among the best known is Raphael's fresco The School of Athens, in the Vatican's Apostolic Palace, where the figures of Plato and Aristotle are central to the image, at the architectural vanishing point, reflecting their importance. Rembrandt's Aristotle with a Bust of Homer, too, is a celebrated work, showing the knowing philosopher and the blind Homer from an earlier age: as the art critic Jonathan Jones writes, "this painting will remain one of the greatest and most mysterious in the world, ensnaring us in its musty, glowing, pitch-black, terrible knowledge of time."
   −
che 'nnanzi a li altri più presso li stanno;</poem>||<poem>
+
几个世纪以来,包括老卢卡斯·克拉纳赫Lucas Cranach the Elder,贾斯特斯•范绅士 Justus van Gent,Raphael,保罗·委罗内塞 Paolo Veronese,胡塞佩·德·里贝拉,伦勃朗Rembrandt,和 弗朗西斯科·海兹Francesco Hayez 等主要艺术家都曾描绘过Aristotle的形象。其中最著名的是Raphael在梵蒂冈使徒宫的壁画《雅典学校》 ,Plato和Aristotle的形象是图像的中心,处于建筑的消失点,反映了他们的重要性。Rembrandt的《亚里士多德与荷马半身像》也是一幅著名的作品,展示了早年的知识渊博的哲学家和盲人荷马: 正如艺术评论家乔纳森 · 琼斯 Jonathan Jones所写的,“这幅画仍将是世界上最伟大、最神秘的画作之一,让我们沉浸于发霉、发光、漆黑、可怕的时间知识中"。
I saw the Master there of those who know,
     −
我在那里见到了那位为人所知的大师,
     −
Amid the philosophic family,
+
File:Aristotle in Nuremberg Chronicle.jpg | ''[[Nuremberg Chronicle]]'' [[anachronism|anachronistically]] shows Aristotle in a medieval scholar's clothing. Ink and watercolour on paper, 1493
   −
在哲学家族中,
+
<gallery mode="packed" heights="170px">
   −
By all admired, and by all reverenced;
+
Aristotle in Nuremberg Chronicle.jpg | Nuremberg Chronicle anachronistically shows Aristotle in a medieval scholar's clothing. Ink and watercolour on paper, 1493
   −
受到所有人的敬仰和崇敬;
+
《纽伦堡编年史》不合时宜地展示了Aristotle穿着中世纪学者的服装。水彩画,1493年
   −
There Plato too I saw, and Socrates,
+
File:Gent, Justus van - Aristotle - c. 1476.jpg | ''Aristotle'' by [[Justus van Gent]]. Oil on panel, c. 1476
   −
在那里我也看到了柏拉图和苏格拉底,
+
File:Gent, Justus van - Aristotle - c. 1476.jpg | Aristotle by Justus van Gent. Oil on panel, c. 1476
   −
Who stood beside him closer than the rest.
+
Aristotle(贾斯特斯•范绅士)画板油画,c.1476
   −
站在他身边的人比其他人都近。
+
File:Lucas Cranach d.Ä. - Phyllis und Aristotle (1530).jpg | ''Phyllis and Aristotle'' by [[Lucas Cranach the Elder]]. Oil on panel, 1530
   −
</poem>
+
File:Lucas Cranach d.Ä. - Phyllis und Aristotle (1530).jpg | Phyllis and Aristotle by Lucas Cranach the Elder. Oil on panel, 1530
   −
</诗歌 >
+
Phyllis 和Aristotle( 老卢卡斯·克拉纳赫)画板油画,1530
   −
|}
+
File:Biblioteka Marciana, Aristotel.jpg | ''Aristotle'' by [[Paolo Veronese]], Biblioteka Marciana. Oil on canvas, 1560s
   −
|}
+
File:Biblioteka Marciana, Aristotel.jpg | Aristotle by Paolo Veronese, Biblioteka Marciana. Oil on canvas, 1560s
   −
</poem>
+
Aristotle(保罗·委罗内塞),马丽安娜图书馆帆布油画,16世纪60年代
   −
|}
+
File:Turchi-AristoteIMG 1713.JPG | ''Aristotle and [[Campaspe]]'',{{efn-ua | Compare the medieval tale of Phyllis and Alexander above.}} [[Alessandro Turchi]] (attrib.) Oil on canvas, 1713
    +
File:Turchi-AristoteIMG 1713.JPG | Aristotle and Campaspe, Alessandro Turchi (attrib.) Oil on canvas, 1713
   −
===On Early Modern scientists===
+
Aristotle和坎帕斯佩,亚历山德罗·图尔奇(attrib)布面油画,1713年
论早期现代科学家
     −
[[File:William Harvey ( 1578-1657) Venenbild.jpg | thumb | [[William Harvey]]'s ''[[Exercitatio Anatomica de Motu Cordis et Sanguinis in Animalibus|De Motu Cordis]]'', 1628, showed that the [[circulation of the blood|blood circulated]], contrary to classical era thinking.]]
+
File:Aristotle by Jusepe de Ribera.jpg | ''[[Aristotle (Ribera painting)|Aristotle]]'' by [[Jusepe de Ribera]]. Oil on canvas, 1637
   −
[[William Harvey's De Motu Cordis, 1628, showed that the blood circulated, contrary to classical era thinking.]]
+
File:Aristotle by Jusepe de Ribera.jpg | Aristotle by Jusepe de Ribera. Oil on canvas, 1637
   −
[威廉 · 哈维(William Harvey)的于1628年出版的《De Motu Cordis》表明,血液循环与古典时代的思想相反。
+
Aristotle(胡塞佩·德·里贝拉),帆布油画,1637年
   −
In the [[Early Modern]] period, scientists such as [[William Harvey]] in England and [[Galileo Galilei]] in Italy reacted against the theories of Aristotle and other classical era thinkers like [[Galen]], establishing new theories based to some degree on observation and experiment. Harvey demonstrated the [[circulation of the blood]], establishing that the heart functioned as a pump rather than being the seat of the soul and the controller of the body's heat, as Aristotle thought.{{sfn| Aird | 2011 | pp=118–29}} Galileo used more doubtful arguments to displace Aristotle's physics, proposing that bodies all fall at the same speed whatever their weight.{{sfn| Machamer | 2017}}
+
File:Rembrandt - Aristotle with a Bust of Homer - WGA19232.jpg | ''Aristotle with a Bust of [[Homer]]'' by [[Rembrandt]]. Oil on canvas, 1653
   −
In the Early Modern period, scientists such as William Harvey in England and Galileo Galilei in Italy reacted against the theories of Aristotle and other classical era thinkers like Galen, establishing new theories based to some degree on observation and experiment. Harvey demonstrated the circulation of the blood, establishing that the heart functioned as a pump rather than being the seat of the soul and the controller of the body's heat, as Aristotle thought. Galileo used more doubtful arguments to displace Aristotle's physics, proposing that bodies all fall at the same speed whatever their weight.
+
File:Rembrandt - Aristotle with a Bust of Homer - WGA19232.jpg | Aristotle with a Bust of Homer by Rembrandt. Oil on canvas, 1653
   −
在近代早期,英国的威廉 · 哈维William Harvey和意大利的伽利略 · 伽利雷Galileo Galilei等科学家反对Aristotle和其他古典时代思想家如盖伦的理论,一定程度上建立了以观察和实验为基础的新理论。哈维证明了血液循环,证明了心脏作为一个泵的功能,而不是像Aristotle认为的那样,是灵魂的所在地和身体热量的控制器。伽利略用更多值得怀疑的论点来取代Aristotle的物理学,他提出物体不论重量大小,下落的速度都是一样的。
+
Aristotle与伦勃朗荷马半身像。帆布油画,1653年
    +
File:Johann Jakob Dorner d Ä (attr) Aristoteles.jpg | ''Aristotle'' by [[Johann Jakob Dorner the Elder]]. Oil on canvas, by 1813
   −
===On 19th-century thinkers===
+
File:Johann Jakob Dorner d Ä (attr) Aristoteles.jpg | Aristotle by Johann Jakob Dorner the Elder. Oil on canvas, by 1813
关于19世纪思想家
     −
The 19th-century German philosopher [[Friedrich Nietzsche]] has been said to have taken nearly all of his political philosophy from Aristotle.{{sfn| Durant | 2006 | p=86}} Aristotle rigidly separated action from production, and argued for the deserved subservience of some people ("natural slaves"), and the natural superiority (virtue, ''arete'') of others. It was [[Martin Heidegger]], not Nietzsche, who elaborated a new interpretation of Aristotle, intended to warrant his deconstruction of scholastic and philosophical tradition.{{sfn| Sikka | 1997 | page=265}}
+
Aristotle(老约翰·雅各布·多尔纳)帆布油画,1813年
   −
The 19th-century German philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche has been said to have taken nearly all of his political philosophy from Aristotle. Aristotle rigidly separated action from production, and argued for the deserved subservience of some people ("natural slaves"), and the natural superiority (virtue, arete) of others. It was Martin Heidegger, not Nietzsche, who elaborated a new interpretation of Aristotle, intended to warrant his deconstruction of scholastic and philosophical tradition.
+
File:Francesco Hayez 001.jpg | ''Aristotle'' by [[Francesco Hayez]]. Oil on canvas, 1811
   −
据说19世纪德国哲学家弗里德里希·尼采Friedrich Nietzsche的政治哲学几乎全部来自于Aristotle。Aristotle严格地将行动与生产分离开来,并主张某些人(“自然奴隶”)应得的服从,而另一些人的自然优越感(美德,受到尊重)。是马丁·海德格尔Martin Heidegger而不是Nietzsche,阐述了对Aristotle的新诠释,意图证明他对学术和哲学传统的解构。
+
File:Francesco Hayez 001.jpg | Aristotle by Francesco Hayez. Oil on canvas, 1811
   −
The English mathematician [[George Boole]] fully accepted Aristotle's logic, but decided "to go under, over, and beyond" it with his system of [[Boolean algebra|algebraic logic]] in his 1854 book ''[[The Laws of Thought]]''. This gives logic a mathematical foundation with equations, enables it to solve equations as well as check [[Validity (logic)|validity]], and allows it to handle a wider class of problems by expanding propositions of any number of terms, not just two.{{sfn| Boole | 2003}}
+
亚里士多德 (弗朗西斯科·海兹)。帆布油画,1811年
   −
The English mathematician George Boole fully accepted Aristotle's logic, but decided "to go under, over, and beyond" it with his system of algebraic logic in his 1854 book The Laws of Thought. This gives logic a mathematical foundation with equations, enables it to solve equations as well as check validity, and allows it to handle a wider class of problems by expanding propositions of any number of terms, not just two.
+
==Sculptures==
 +
雕塑作品
   −
英国数学家乔治 · 布尔George Boole 完全接受Aristotle的逻辑学,但在他1854年出版的著作《思想法则》中,他决定用他的代数逻辑系统“超越”它。这就使逻辑学有了方程的数学基础,使它既能解方程,又能检验有效性,并使它能处理更广泛的一类问题,将任意数项的命题扩大,而不仅仅是两个命题。
+
File:Aristoteles Louvre.jpg|Roman copy of 1st or 2nd century from original bronze by [[Lysippos]]. [[Louvre Museum]]
    +
File:Aristoteles Louvre.jpg|Roman copy of 1st or 2nd century from original bronze by Lysippos. Louvre Museum
   −
===Modern rejection and rehabilitation===
+
1世纪或2世纪的罗马复制品,出自 利西波斯 的青铜原件。卢浮宫博物馆
现代的废弃和复原
  −
[[File:Alexander and Aristotle.jpg | thumb|upright=1.2 | left | "That most enduring of romantic images, Aristotle tutoring the future conqueror Alexander".{{sfn|Kukkonen|2010|pages=70–77}} Illustration by {{interlanguage link|Charles Laplante|fr}}, 1866]]
      +
File:DSC00218 - Aristotele - Copia romana del 117-138 dC. - Foto di G. Dall'Orto.jpg|Roman copy of 117-138 AD of Greek original. Palermo Regional Archeology Museum
   −
"That most enduring of romantic images, Aristotle tutoring the future conqueror Alexander". Illustration by , 1866
+
File:DSC00218 - Aristotele - Copia romana del 117-138 dC. - Foto di G. Dall'Orto.jpg|Roman copy of 117-138 AD of Greek original. Palermo Regional Archeology Museum
   −
“最经久不衰的浪漫主义形象,是Aristotle教导未来的征服者亚历山大”。插图: 1866
+
117-138 dC.- Foto di g. Dall‘ Orto.jpg | 公元117-138年希腊原版的罗马复制品。巴勒莫地区考古博物馆
   −
During the 20th century, Aristotle's work was widely criticized. The philosopher [[Bertrand Russell]]argued that "almost every serious intellectual advance has had to begin with an attack on some Aristotelian doctrine". Russell called Aristotle's ethics "repulsive", and labelled his logic "as definitely antiquated as Ptolemaic astronomy". Russell stated that these errors made it difficult to do historical justice to Aristotle, until one remembered what an advance he made upon all of his predecessors.{{sfn|Russell|1972}}
+
File:Formella 21, platone e aristotele o la filosofia, luca della robbia, 1437-1439.JPG|Relief of Aristotle and Plato by [[Luca della Robbia]], [[Florence Cathedral]], 1437-1439
   −
During the 20th century, Aristotle's work was widely criticized. The philosopher Bertrand Russell argued that "almost every serious intellectual advance has had to begin with an attack on some Aristotelian doctrine". Russell called Aristotle's ethics "repulsive", and labelled his logic "as definitely antiquated as Ptolemaic astronomy". Russell stated that these errors made it difficult to do historical justice to Aristotle, until one remembered what an advance he made upon all of his predecessors.
+
File:Formella 21, platone e aristotele o la filosofia, luca della robbia, 1437-1439.JPG|Relief of Aristotle and Plato by Luca della Robbia, Florence Cathedral, 1437-1439
   −
在20世纪,Aristotle的著作受到广泛的批评。哲学家伯特兰·罗素Bertrand Russell认为,“几乎每一次重大的知识进步都必须从攻击Aristotle的某些学说开始”。Aristotle的伦理学是“令人厌恶”的 ,并称他的逻辑学“和托勒密Ptolemaic的天文学一样过时”。Russell指出,这些错误使得人们很难公正地看待Aristotle,直到人们想起他对他所有的前辈所做的进步。
+
Aristotle和Plato的救赎,卢卡·德拉·罗比亚,佛罗伦萨大教堂,1437-1439
   −
The Dutch historian of science [[Eduard Jan Dijksterhuis]] wrote that Aristotle and his predecessors showed the difficulty of science by "proceed[ing] so readily to frame a theory of such a general character" on limited evidence from their senses.{{sfn|Dijksterhuis|1969|p=72}} In 1985, the biologist [[Peter Medawar]] could still state in "pure seventeenth century"{{sfn|Leroi|2015|p=353}} tones that Aristotle had assembled "a strange and generally speaking rather tiresome farrago of hearsay, imperfect observation, wishful thinking and credulity amounting to downright gullibility".{{sfn|Leroi|2015|p=353}}{{sfn|Medawar|Medawar|1984|p=28}}
+
File:Llyfrgell Sant Deiniol and Gladstone's Library Hawarden Penarlâg 05.JPG|Stone statue in niche, [[Gladstone's Library]], [[Hawarden]], Wales, 1899
   −
The Dutch historian of science Eduard Jan Dijksterhuis wrote that Aristotle and his predecessors showed the difficulty of science by "proceed[ing] so readily to frame a theory of such a general character" on limited evidence from their senses. In 1985, the biologist Peter Medawar could still state in "pure seventeenth century" tones that Aristotle had assembled "a strange and generally speaking rather tiresome farrago of hearsay, imperfect observation, wishful thinking and credulity amounting to downright gullibility".
+
File:Llyfrgell Sant Deiniol and Gladstone's Library Hawarden Penarlâg 05.JPG|Stone statue in niche, Gladstone's Library, Hawarden, Wales, 1899
   −
荷兰科学史家迪克斯特休伊斯爱德华·简 Eduard Jan Dijksterhuis写道,Aristotle和他的前辈们通过 "如此轻易地根据他们的感官提供的有限证据来构筑这样一种一般性的理论",显示了科学的困难。1985年,生物学家彼得•梅达瓦Peter Medawar仍然可以用 "纯正的十七世纪 "的语气说,Aristotle集合了 "一种奇怪的、一般说来相当令人厌烦的传闻、不完善的观察、一厢情愿的想法和相当于完全轻信的可信度"。
+
利基的石像,格拉斯通图书馆,威尔士哈沃登,1899年
   −
By the start of the 21st century, however, Aristotle was taken more seriously: Kukkonen noted that "In the best 20th-century scholarship Aristotle comes alive as a thinker wrestling with the full weight of the Greek philosophical tradition."{{sfn|Kukkonen|2010|pp=70–77}} [[Alasdair MacIntyre]] has attempted to reform what he calls the Aristotelian tradition in a way that is anti-elitist and capable of disputing the claims of both liberals and Nietzscheans.{{sfn|Knight|2007|pp=''passim''}} Kukkonen observed, too, that "that most enduring of romantic images, Aristotle tutoring the future conqueror Alexander" remained current, as in the 2004 film ''[[Alexander (2004 film)|Alexander]]'', while the "firm rules" of Aristotle's theory of drama have ensured a role for the ''Poetics'' in [[Cinema of the United States|Hollywood]].{{sfn|Kukkonen|2010|pp=70–77}}
+
File:Uni Freiburg - Philosophen 4.jpg|Bronze statue, [[University of Freiburg]], Germany, 1915
   −
By the start of the 21st century, however, Aristotle was taken more seriously: Kukkonen noted that "In the best 20th-century scholarship Aristotle comes alive as a thinker wrestling with the full weight of the Greek philosophical tradition." Alasdair MacIntyre has attempted to reform what he calls the Aristotelian tradition in a way that is anti-elitist and capable of disputing the claims of both liberals and Nietzscheans. Kukkonen observed, too, that "that most enduring of romantic images, Aristotle tutoring the future conqueror Alexander" remained current, as in the 2004 film Alexander, while the "firm rules" of Aristotle's theory of drama have ensured a role for the Poetics in Hollywood.
+
File:Uni Freiburg - Philosophen 4.jpg|Bronze statue, University of Freiburg, Germany, 1915
   −
然而,到了21世纪初,Aristotle受到了更多的重视。Kukkonen指出,"在20世纪最好的学术研究中,Aristotle作为一个思想家与希腊哲学传统的全部重量相抗衡,活灵活现。" 阿拉斯戴尔•麦金泰尔Alasdair MacIntyre试图以一种反精英主义的方式改革他所谓的亚里士多德传统,并能够与自由主义者和尼采主义者的主张相争 。Kukkonen 还指出,“Aristotle对未来的征服者亚历山大的指导,是最经久不衰的浪漫主义形象” ,正如2004年的电影《亚历山大》一样,而Aristotle戏剧理论的“坚定规则”确保了《诗学》在好莱坞的地位。
+
青铜雕像,弗赖堡大学,德国,1915年
   −
Biologists continue to be interested in Aristotle's thinking. [[Armand Marie Leroi]] has reconstructed Aristotle's biology,{{sfn|Leroi|2015}} while [[Tinbergen's four questions|Niko Tinbergen's four questions]], based on Aristotle's four causes, are used to analyse [[animal behaviour]]; they examine [[function (biology)|function]], [[phylogeny]], [[mechanism (biology)|mechanism]], and [[ontogeny]].{{sfn|MacDougall-Shackleton|2011|pp=2076–85}}{{sfn|Hladký|Havlíček|2013}}
+
===Eponyms===
 +
名字被用于命名地方
   −
Biologists continue to be interested in Aristotle's thinking. Armand Marie Leroi has reconstructed Aristotle's biology, while Niko Tinbergen's four questions, based on Aristotle's four causes, are used to analyse animal behaviour; they examine function, phylogeny, mechanism, and ontogeny.
+
The [[Aristotle Mountains]] in [[Antarctica]] are named after Aristotle. He was the first person known to conjecture, in his book ''[[Meteorology (Aristotle)|Meteorology]]'', the existence of a landmass in the southern high-latitude region and called it ''Antarctica''.{{sfn| Aristotle Mountains}} [[Aristoteles (crater)|Aristoteles]] is a crater on the Moon bearing the classical form of Aristotle's name.{{sfn| Aristoteles}}
   −
生物学家继续对Aristotle的思想感兴趣。阿曼德 · 玛丽 · 莱罗伊Armand Marie Leroi重建了Aristotle的生物学,而尼科 · 廷伯根Niko Tinbergen根据Aristotle的四个原因提出的四个问题,被用来分析动物行为; 他们研究功能、系统发育、机制和个体发育。
+
The Aristotle Mountains in Antarctica are named after Aristotle. He was the first person known to conjecture, in his book Meteorology, the existence of a landmass in the southern high-latitude region and called it Antarctica. Aristoteles is a crater on the Moon bearing the classical form of Aristotle's name.
    +
南极洲的亚里士多德山是以Aristotle的名字命名的。他是第一个在他的《气象学》一书中推测出南半球高纬度地区存在一个地块并将其称为南极洲的人。亚里士多德是月球上的一个陨石坑,是Aristotle名字的经典形式。
      −
==Surviving works==
  −
幸存的作品
     −
===Corpus Aristotelicum===
+
==See also==
亚里士多德文集
+
另请参见
{{main | Corpus Aristotelicum}}
+
* [[Aristotelian Society]]亚里士多德学会
   −
[[File:Aristotelis De Moribus ad Nicomachum.jpg | thumb | upright | First page of a 1566 edition of the ''[[Nicomachean Ethics]]'' in Greek and Latin]]
+
* [[Conimbricenses]]孔布拉派
   −
First page of a 1566 edition of the [[Nicomachean Ethics in Greek and Latin]]
+
* [[Perfectionism (philosophy)|Perfectionism]] 完美主义
   −
1566年版《希腊文和拉丁文的尼科马奇伦理》的首页
     −
The works of Aristotle that have survived from antiquity through medieval manuscript transmission are collected in the Corpus Aristotelicum. These texts, as opposed to Aristotle's lost works, are technical philosophical treatises from within Aristotle's school. Reference to them is made according to the organization of [[Immanuel Bekker]]'s Royal Prussian Academy edition (''Aristotelis Opera edidit Academia Regia Borussica'', Berlin, 1831–1870), which in turn is based on ancient classifications of these works.{{sfn| Aristotelis Opera}}
     −
The works of Aristotle that have survived from antiquity through medieval manuscript transmission are collected in the Corpus Aristotelicum. These texts, as opposed to Aristotle's lost works, are technical philosophical treatises from within Aristotle's school. Reference to them is made according to the organization of Immanuel Bekker's Royal Prussian Academy edition (Aristotelis Opera edidit Academia Regia Borussica, Berlin, 1831–1870), which in turn is based on ancient classifications of these works.
+
==References==
   −
Aristotle的著作是通过中世纪手稿传播而从古代流传下来的,现收藏在亚里士多德文集中。这些文本,相对于Aristotle失传的著作,是Aristotle派内部的技术性哲学论著。参考他们是根据伊曼纽尔贝克的普鲁士皇家学院版(Aristotle的歌剧编辑委员会学术区,柏林,1831-1870年)的编排 ,而这一编排又是基于古代对这些著作的分类来进行的。
        −
===Loss and preservation===
+
===Notes===
损失和保存
  −
{{see | Recovery of Aristotle}}
     −
Aristotle wrote his works on papyrus scrolls, the common writing medium of that era.{{efn-ua | "When the Roman dictator Sulla invaded Athens in 86 BC, he brought back to Rome a fantastic prize – Aristotle's library. Books then were papyrus rolls, from 10 to 20 feet long, and since Aristotle's death in 322 BC, worms and damp had done their worst. The rolls needed repairing, and the texts clarifying and copying on to new papyrus (imported from Egypt – Moses' bulrushes). The man in Rome who put Aristotle's library in order was a Greek scholar, Tyrannio."{{sfn| When libraries were | 2001}}}} His writings are divisible into two groups: the "[[exoteric]]", intended for the public, and the "[[esoteric]]", for use within the [[Lyceum (Classical)|Lyceum]] school.{{sfn| Barnes | 1995 | p=12}}{{efn-ua | 1=Aristotle: ''Nicomachean Ethics'' 1102a26–27. Aristotle himself never uses the term "esoteric" or "acroamatic". For other passages where Aristotle speaks of ''exōterikoi logoi'', see [[W.D. Ross]], ''Aristotle's Metaphysics'' (1953), vol. 2 pp= 408–10. Ross defends an interpretation according to which the phrase, at least in Aristotle's own works, usually refers generally to "discussions not peculiar to the [[Peripatetic school]]", rather than to specific works of Aristotle's own.}}{{sfn| House | 1956 | page=35}} Aristotle's "lost" works stray considerably in characterization from the surviving Aristotelian corpus. Whereas the lost works appear to have been originally written with a view to subsequent publication, the surviving works mostly resemble lecture notes not intended for publication.{{sfn| Irwin | Fine | 1996 | pp= xi–xii }}{{sfn| Barnes | 1995 | p=12}} [[Cicero]]'s description of Aristotle's literary style as "a river of gold" must have applied to the published works, not the surviving notes.{{efn-ua | "''veniet flumen orationis aureum fundens Aristoteles''", (Google translation: "Aristotle will come pouring forth a golden stream of eloquence").{{sfn| Cicero | 1874}}}} A major question in the history of Aristotle's works is how the exoteric writings were all lost, and how the ones we now possess came to us.{{sfn| Barnes | Griffin | 1999 | pages=1–69}} The consensus is that Andronicus of Rhodes collected the esoteric works of Aristotle's school which existed in the form of smaller, separate works, distinguished them from those of Theophrastus and other Peripatetics, edited them, and finally compiled them into the more cohesive, larger works as they are known today.{{sfn| Anagnostopoulos | 2013 | page=16}}{{sfn| Barnes | 1995 | pp=10–15}}
+
{{notelist-ua | 30em}}
   −
Aristotle wrote his works on papyrus scrolls, the common writing medium of that era.}His writings are divisible into two groups: the "exoteric", intended for the public, and the "esoteric", for use within the Lyceum school. Aristotle's "lost" works stray considerably in characterization from the surviving Aristotelian corpus. Whereas the lost works appear to have been originally written with a view to subsequent publication, the surviving works mostly resemble lecture notes not intended for publication. Cicero's description of Aristotle's literary style as "a river of gold" must have applied to the published works, not the surviving notes.A major question in the history of Aristotle's works is how the exoteric writings were all lost, and how the ones we now possess came to us. The consensus is that Andronicus of Rhodes collected the esoteric works of Aristotle's school which existed in the form of smaller, separate works, distinguished them from those of Theophrastus and other Peripatetics, edited them, and finally compiled them into the more cohesive, larger works as they are known today.
     −
Aristotle把他的作品写在纸莎草纸卷上,这是当时常见的书写媒介。他的著作可分为两类: 面向公众的“通俗”著作,以及在吕克昂学院内部使用的“深奥”著作。Aristotle的 "遗失 "的作品在表征上与现存的亚里士多德文集大相径庭。遗失的作品似乎最初是为了以后的出版而写的,而现存的作品则大多类似于不打算出版的讲义。Aristotle的文学风格描述为“黄金之河” ,这一定适用于已出版的作品,而不是现存的笔记。Aristotle著作史上的一个主要问题是,那些公开的著作是如何全部丢失的,而我们现在拥有的那些著作又是如何来到我们这里的。人们一致认为,罗德岛的Andronicus收集了亚里士多德学派的,以较小的、独立的作品形式存在的深奥作品,将它们与Theophrastus和其他学派的作品区分开来,对它们进行编辑,最后将它们汇编成今天人们所熟知的更具凝聚力的、更大的作品。
      +
===Citations===
   −
==Legacy==
+
{{Reflist | colwidth=25em}}
遗产
     −
===Depictions===
  −
叙述
     −
==Paintings==
  −
绘画
     −
Aristotle has been depicted by major artists including [[Lucas Cranach the Elder]],{{sfn| Lucas Cranach the Elder}} [[Justus van Gent]], [[Raphael]], [[Paolo Veronese]], [[Jusepe de Ribera]],{{sfn| Lee | Robinson | 2005}} [[Rembrandt]],{{sfn| Aristotle with Bust | 2002}} and [[Francesco Hayez]] over the centuries. Among the best known is Raphael's [[fresco]] ''[[The School of Athens]]'', in the [[Apostolic Palace|Vatican's Apostolic Palace]], where the figures of Plato and Aristotle are central to the image, at the architectural [[vanishing point]], reflecting their importance.{{sfn| Phelan | 2002}} Rembrandt's ''[[Aristotle with a Bust of Homer]]'', too, is a celebrated work, showing the knowing philosopher and the blind Homer from an earlier age: as the art critic [[Jonathan Jones (journalist)|Jonathan Jones]] writes, "this painting will remain one of the greatest and most mysterious in the world, ensnaring us in its musty, glowing, pitch-black, terrible knowledge of time."{{sfn| Held | 1969}}{{sfn| Jones | 2002}}
+
===Sources===
   −
<gallery mode="packed" heights="170px">
     −
“ packed" heights = " 170px" >
     −
Aristotle has been depicted by major artists including Lucas Cranach the Elder, Justus van Gent, Raphael, Paolo Veronese, Jusepe de Ribera, Rembrandt, and Francesco Hayez over the centuries. Among the best known is Raphael's fresco The School of Athens, in the Vatican's Apostolic Palace, where the figures of Plato and Aristotle are central to the image, at the architectural vanishing point, reflecting their importance. Rembrandt's Aristotle with a Bust of Homer, too, is a celebrated work, showing the knowing philosopher and the blind Homer from an earlier age: as the art critic Jonathan Jones writes, "this painting will remain one of the greatest and most mysterious in the world, ensnaring us in its musty, glowing, pitch-black, terrible knowledge of time."
+
{{refbegin|36em}}
   −
几个世纪以来,包括老卢卡斯·克拉纳赫Lucas Cranach the Elder,贾斯特斯•范绅士 Justus van Gent,Raphael,保罗·委罗内塞 Paolo Veronese,胡塞佩·德·里贝拉,伦勃朗Rembrandt,和 弗朗西斯科·海兹Francesco Hayez 等主要艺术家都曾描绘过Aristotle的形象。其中最著名的是Raphael在梵蒂冈使徒宫的壁画《雅典学校》 ,Plato和Aristotle的形象是图像的中心,处于建筑的消失点,反映了他们的重要性。Rembrandt的《亚里士多德与荷马半身像》也是一幅著名的作品,展示了早年的知识渊博的哲学家和盲人荷马: 正如艺术评论家乔纳森 · 琼斯 Jonathan Jones所写的,“这幅画仍将是世界上最伟大、最神秘的画作之一,让我们沉浸于发霉、发光、漆黑、可怕的时间知识中"。
+
* {{cite book |author=Aesop |author-link=Aesop |title=The Complete Fables By Aesop |date=1998 | translator-last=Temple | translator-first=Olivia | translator-last2=Temple | translator-first2=Robert |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ZB-rVxPvtPEC&pg=PR3 |publisher=Penguin Classics |isbn=978-0-14-044649-4}}
    +
* {{cite journal |last=Aird |first=W. C. |title=Discovery of the cardiovascular system: from Galen to William Harvey |year=2011 |pages=118–29 |journal=Journal of Thrombosis and Haemostasis |volume=9 |doi=10.1111/j.1538-7836.2011.04312.x |pmid=21781247 |s2cid=12092592}}
   −
File:Aristotle in Nuremberg Chronicle.jpg | ''[[Nuremberg Chronicle]]'' [[anachronism|anachronistically]] shows Aristotle in a medieval scholar's clothing. Ink and watercolour on paper, 1493
+
* {{cite journal |last1=Allain |first1=Rhett |title=I'm So Totally Over Newton's Laws of Motion |journal=Wired |date=21 March 2016 |url=https://www.wired.com/2016/03/im-totally-newtons-laws-motion/ |access-date=11 May 2018}}
   −
<gallery mode="packed" heights="170px">
+
* {{cite book |last1=Allen |first1=Mark |last2=Fisher |first2=John H. |title=The Complete Poetry and Prose of Geoffrey Chaucer |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=eMSUXumf6psC&pg=PA17 |date=2011 |publisher=Cengage Learning |isbn=978-0-15-506041-8}}
   −
Aristotle in Nuremberg Chronicle.jpg | Nuremberg Chronicle anachronistically shows Aristotle in a medieval scholar's clothing. Ink and watercolour on paper, 1493
+
* {{cite book |last=Anagnostopoulos |first=Georgios |title=A Companion to Aristotle |year=2013 |publisher=Wiley-Blackwell |isbn=978-1-118-59243-4}}
   −
《纽伦堡编年史》不合时宜地展示了Aristotle穿着中世纪学者的服装。水彩画,1493年
+
* {{cite book |last=Annas |first=Julia |title=Classical Greek Philosophy |date=2001 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-285357-8}}
   −
File:Gent, Justus van - Aristotle - c. 1476.jpg | ''Aristotle'' by [[Justus van Gent]]. Oil on panel, c. 1476
+
* {{cite book |last=Aquinas |first=Thomas |author-link=Thomas Aquinas |title=Summa Theologica |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=YiJCBAAAQBAJ |date=20 August 2013 |publisher=e-artnow |isbn=978-80-7484-292-4}}
   −
File:Gent, Justus van - Aristotle - c. 1476.jpg | Aristotle by Justus van Gent. Oil on panel, c. 1476
+
* {{cite web | editor-first=Immanuel | editor-last=Bekker | orig-year=1831 |url=http://archive.org/details/bub_gb_jMz9zVYu9Q0C |title=Aristotelis Opera edidit Academia Regia Borussica Aristoteles graece |last=Aristoteles |date=31 January 2019 |publisher=apud Georgium Reimerum |access-date=31 January 2019 |via=Internet Archive |ref=CITEREFAristotelis Opera}}
   −
Aristotle(贾斯特斯•范绅士)画板油画,c.1476
+
* {{cite web |title=Aristoteles |url=https://planetarynames.wr.usgs.gov/nomenclature/SearchResults;jsessionid=BE8F9834B709207DDD5D36EFA5506C7F |website=Gazetteer of Planetary Nomenclature. United States Geological Survey |access-date=19 March 2018 |ref=CITEREFAristoteles}}
   −
File:Lucas Cranach d.Ä. - Phyllis und Aristotle (1530).jpg | ''Phyllis and Aristotle'' by [[Lucas Cranach the Elder]]. Oil on panel, 1530
+
* {{cite web |title=Aristoteles-Park in Stagira |url=http://www.dimosaristoteli.gr/en/sights/aristotle-park |publisher=Dimos Aristoteli |access-date=20 March 2018 |ref=CITEREFAristoteles-Park in Stagira}}
   −
File:Lucas Cranach d.Ä. - Phyllis und Aristotle (1530).jpg | Phyllis and Aristotle by Lucas Cranach the Elder. Oil on panel, 1530
+
* {{cite IEP |title=Aristotle (384–322 B.C.E.) |date=2009 | url-id=aristotl |issn=2161-0002 |ref=CITEREFAristotle (384–322 B.C.E.)}}
   −
Phyllis 和Aristotle( 老卢卡斯·克拉纳赫)画板油画,1530
+
* {{cite web |title=Aristotle (Greek philosopher) |publisher=Britannica Online Encyclopedia |url=http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/34560/Aristotle |website=Britannica.com |access-date=26 April 2009 |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20090422103155/http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/34560/Aristotle |archivedate=22 April 2009 | url-status=live |ref=CITEREFAristotle (Greek philosopher)}}
   −
File:Biblioteka Marciana, Aristotel.jpg | ''Aristotle'' by [[Paolo Veronese]], Biblioteka Marciana. Oil on canvas, 1560s
+
* {{cite web |url=http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/metaphysics.html |publisher=The Internet Classics Archive |title=Metaphysics |last=Aristotle |website=classics.mit.edu |access-date=30 January 2019 |ref=CITEREFMetaphysics}}
   −
File:Biblioteka Marciana, Aristotel.jpg | Aristotle by Paolo Veronese, Biblioteka Marciana. Oil on canvas, 1560s
+
* {{cite web |url=http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/meteorology.html |publisher=The Internet Classics Archive |title=Meteorology |last=Aristotle |website=classics.mit.edu |access-date=30 January 2019 |ref=CITEREFMeteorology}}
   −
Aristotle(保罗·委罗内塞),马丽安娜图书馆帆布油画,16世纪60年代
+
* {{cite web |url=http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/nicomachaen.html |publisher=The Internet Classics Archive |title=Nicomachean Ethics |author=Aristotle |website=classics.mit.edu |ref=CITEREFNicomachean Ethics}}
   −
File:Turchi-AristoteIMG 1713.JPG | ''Aristotle and [[Campaspe]]'',{{efn-ua | Compare the medieval tale of Phyllis and Alexander above.}} [[Alessandro Turchi]] (attrib.) Oil on canvas, 1713
+
* {{cite web |url=http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/soul.html |publisher=The Internet Classics Archive |title=On the Soul |last=Aristotle |website=classics.mit.edu |access-date=30 January 2019 |ref=CITEREFOn the Soul}}
   −
File:Turchi-AristoteIMG 1713.JPG | Aristotle and Campaspe, Alessandro Turchi (attrib.) Oil on canvas, 1713
+
* {{cite web |url=http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/physics.html |publisher=The Internet Classics Archive |title=Physics |author=Aristotle |website=classics.mit.edu |access-date=31 January 2019 |ref=CITEREFPhysics}}
   −
Aristotle和坎帕斯佩,亚历山德罗·图尔奇(attrib)布面油画,1713年
+
* {{cite web |url=http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/poetics.html |publisher=The Internet Classics Archive |title=Poetics |last=Aristotle |website=classics.mit.edu |access-date=30 January 2019 |ref=CITEREFPoetics}}
   −
File:Aristotle by Jusepe de Ribera.jpg | ''[[Aristotle (Ribera painting)|Aristotle]]'' by [[Jusepe de Ribera]]. Oil on canvas, 1637
+
* {{cite web |url=http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/politics.html |publisher=The Internet Classics Archive |title=Politics |last=Aristotle |website=classics.mit.edu |access-date=30 January 2019 |ref=CITEREFPolitics}}
   −
File:Aristotle by Jusepe de Ribera.jpg | Aristotle by Jusepe de Ribera. Oil on canvas, 1637
+
* {{cite web |url=http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/prior.html |publisher=The Internet Classics Archive |title=Prior Analytics |last=Aristotle |website=classics.mit.edu |ref=CITEREFPrior Analytics}}
   −
Aristotle(胡塞佩·德·里贝拉),帆布油画,1637年
+
* {{cite web |author=Aristotle |title=Rhetoric | translator-first=W. Rhys | translator-last=Roberts |url=http://rhetoric.eserver.org/aristotle/rhet1-5.html |archivedate=13 February 2015  |ref=CITEREFRhetoric| archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150213075039/http://rhetoric.eserver.org/aristotle/rhet1-5.html}}
   −
File:Rembrandt - Aristotle with a Bust of Homer - WGA19232.jpg | ''Aristotle with a Bust of [[Homer]]'' by [[Rembrandt]]. Oil on canvas, 1653
+
* {{cite web |title=Aristotle Mountains |url=https://data.aad.gov.au/aadc/gaz/scar/display_name.cfm?gaz_id=137410 |work=[[Scientific Committee on Antarctic Research|SCAR]] [[Composite Antarctic Gazetteer]] |publisher=[[Programma Nazionale di Ricerche in Antartide]] |agency=[[Department of the Environment and Energy]], [[Australian Antarctic Division]], [[Australian Government]] | access-date=1 March 2018 |ref=CITEREFAristotle Mountains}}
   −
File:Rembrandt - Aristotle with a Bust of Homer - WGA19232.jpg | Aristotle with a Bust of Homer by Rembrandt. Oil on canvas, 1653
+
* {{cite book |author=Aristotle |title=Politics-Ethics, In Early Economic Thought: Selections from Economic Literature Prior to Adam Smith |date=1948 |editor=Monroe, Arthur E. |publisher=Harvard University Press}}
   −
Aristotle与伦勃朗荷马半身像。帆布油画,1653年
+
* {{cite book |author=Aristotle |title=The Politics |url=https://archive.org/details/politics0000aris |url-access=registration |date=1984 |editor=Lord, Carnes |publisher=University of Chicago Press |isbn=978-0-226-92184-6}}
   −
File:Johann Jakob Dorner d Ä (attr) Aristoteles.jpg | ''Aristotle'' by [[Johann Jakob Dorner the Elder]]. Oil on canvas, by 1813
+
* {{cite book |author=Aristotle |title=Politics |date=2009 |others=Translated by Ernest Barker and revised with introduction and notes by R.F. Stalley |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-953873-7 |edition=1st |origyear=1995}}
   −
File:Johann Jakob Dorner d Ä (attr) Aristoteles.jpg | Aristotle by Johann Jakob Dorner the Elder. Oil on canvas, by 1813
+
* {{cite book |author=Aristotle | translator-last1=Sachs | translator-first1=Joe |title=Aristotle's ''Metaphysics'' |year=1999 |publisher=Green Lion Press}}
   −
Aristotle(老约翰·雅各布·多尔纳)帆布油画,1813年
+
* {{cite web |title=Aristotle and Phyllis |url=http://www.artic.edu/aic/collections/artwork/20121 |publisher=Art Institute Chicago |access-date=22 March 2018 |ref=CITEREFAristotle Phyllis}}
   −
File:Francesco Hayez 001.jpg | ''Aristotle'' by [[Francesco Hayez]]. Oil on canvas, 1811
+
* {{cite web |url=https://www.collinsdictionary.com/dictionary/english/aristotle |title=Aristotle definition and meaning |publisher=Collins English Dictionary |website=www.collinsdictionary.com |ref=CITEREFCollins English Dictionary}}
   −
File:Francesco Hayez 001.jpg | Aristotle by Francesco Hayez. Oil on canvas, 1811
+
* {{cite news |title=Aristotle with a Bust of Homer, Rembrandt (1653) |date=27 July 2002 |url=https://www.theguardian.com/culture/2002/jul/27/art.homer |newspaper=[[The Guardian]] |access-date=23 March 2018 |ref=CITEREFAristotle with Bust2002}}
   −
亚里士多德 (弗朗西斯科·海兹)。帆布油画,1811年
+
* {{cite book |last=Averroes |title=Commentarium Magnum in Aristotelis De Anima Libros|editor-last=Crawford|editor-first=F. Stuart |publisher=Mediaeval Academy of America |oclc=611422373 |date=1953}}
   −
==Sculptures==
+
* {{cite book |last1=Barnes |first1=Jonathan |title=Aristotle: A Very Short Introduction |date=1982 |author-link=Jonathan Barnes |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-285408-7}}
雕塑作品
     −
File:Aristoteles Louvre.jpg|Roman copy of 1st or 2nd century from original bronze by [[Lysippos]]. [[Louvre Museum]]
+
* {{cite book |last=Barnes |first=Jonathan |chapter=Life and Work |title=The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle |date=1995 |author-link=Jonathan Barnes |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0-521-42294-9 | chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=WBqQOqM5dfsC}}
   −
File:Aristoteles Louvre.jpg|Roman copy of 1st or 2nd century from original bronze by Lysippos. Louvre Museum
+
* {{cite book |last1=Barnes |first1=Jonathan |author-link=Jonathan Barnes |last2=Griffin |first2=Miriam Tamara |title=Philosophia Togata: Plato and Aristotle at Rome. II |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=r18BAAAACAAJ |year=1999 |publisher=Clarendon Press |isbn=978-0-19-815222-4}}
   −
1世纪或2世纪的罗马复制品,出自 利西波斯 的青铜原件。卢浮宫博物馆
+
* {{cite book |last1=Bergstrom |first1=Carl T. |last2=Dugatkin |first2=Lee Alan |title=Evolution |date=2012 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=SeaEZwEACAAJ |publisher=Norton |isbn=978-0-393-92592-0}}
   −
File:DSC00218 - Aristotele - Copia romana del 117-138 dC. - Foto di G. Dall'Orto.jpg|Roman copy of 117-138 AD of Greek original. Palermo Regional Archeology Museum
+
* {{cite journal |last=Blits |first=Kathleen C. |title=Aristotle: Form, function, and comparative anatomy |date=15 April 1999 |pages=58–63 |journal=The Anatomical Record |volume=257 |issue=2 |doi=10.1002/(SICI)1097-0185(19990415)257:2<58::AID-AR6>3.0.CO;2-I |pmid=10321433}}
   −
File:DSC00218 - Aristotele - Copia romana del 117-138 dC. - Foto di G. Dall'Orto.jpg|Roman copy of 117-138 AD of Greek original. Palermo Regional Archeology Museum
+
* {{cite book |last=Bloch |first=David |title=Aristotle on Memory and Recollection |date=2007 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=QwTHng_5RqAC&q=Aristotle+on+Memory+and+Recollection&pg=PR9 |isbn=978-90-04-16046-0}}
   −
117-138 dC.- Foto di g. Dall‘ Orto.jpg | 公元117-138年希腊原版的罗马复制品。巴勒莫地区考古博物馆
+
* {{cite book | chapter-url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/logic-ancient/ |title=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |first=Susanne |last=Bobzien |chapter=Ancient Logic | editor-first=Edward N. | editor-last=Zalta |date=2015 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |via=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy}}
   −
File:Formella 21, platone e aristotele o la filosofia, luca della robbia, 1437-1439.JPG|Relief of Aristotle and Plato by [[Luca della Robbia]], [[Florence Cathedral]], 1437-1439
+
* {{cite book |last=Boole |first=George |author-link=George Boole |title=The Laws of Thought |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=nUEQAQAAIAAJ |year=2003 | orig-year=1854 |publisher=Prometheus Books |isbn=978-1-59102-089-9}}
   −
File:Formella 21, platone e aristotele o la filosofia, luca della robbia, 1437-1439.JPG|Relief of Aristotle and Plato by Luca della Robbia, Florence Cathedral, 1437-1439
+
* {{cite web |last=Campbell |first=Michael |title=Behind the Name: Meaning, Origin and History of the Name "Aristotle" |url=http://www.behindthename.com/name/aristotle |website=Behind the Name |access-date=6 April 2012}}
   −
Aristotle和Plato的救赎,卢卡·德拉·罗比亚,佛罗伦萨大教堂,1437-1439
+
* {{cite book |last=Carruthers |first=Mary |title=The Book of Memory: A Study of Memory in Medieval Culture |date=2007 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=dntrAnqfIasC&q=The+book+of+memory:+the+study+of+memory+in+medieval+times&pg=PR8 |isbn=978-0-521-42973-3}}
   −
File:Llyfrgell Sant Deiniol and Gladstone's Library Hawarden Penarlâg 05.JPG|Stone statue in niche, [[Gladstone's Library]], [[Hawarden]], Wales, 1899
+
* {{cite book |last1=Carteron |first1=Henri |title=Notion de Force dans le Systeme d'Aristote |date=1923 |publisher=J. Vrin |language=French}}
   −
File:Llyfrgell Sant Deiniol and Gladstone's Library Hawarden Penarlâg 05.JPG|Stone statue in niche, Gladstone's Library, Hawarden, Wales, 1899
+
* {{cite book |last=Cicero |first=Marcus Tullius |author-link=Cicero |chapter=Book II, chapter XXXVIII, §119 |title=The Academica of Cicero 106–43 BC |date=1874 | editor-first=James S. | editor-last=Reid |publisher=Macmillan}}
   −
利基的石像,格拉斯通图书馆,威尔士哈沃登,1899年
+
* {{cite web |last1=Cohen |first1=S. Marc |title=Aristotle's Metaphysics |date=8 October 2000 |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-metaphysics/ |website=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=The Metaphysics Research Lab Center for the Study of Language and Information |access-date=14 November 2018}}
   −
File:Uni Freiburg - Philosophen 4.jpg|Bronze statue, [[University of Freiburg]], Germany, 1915
+
* {{cite SEP |last=Cohen |first=S. Marc |title=Aristotle's Metaphysics |date=2016 | url-id=aristotle-metaphysics/#ActuPote}}
   −
File:Uni Freiburg - Philosophen 4.jpg|Bronze statue, University of Freiburg, Germany, 1915
+
* {{cite SEP |last=Cohen |first=S. Marc |title=Aristotle's Metaphysics: Substance and Definition |date=2016 | url-id=aristotle-metaphysics/#SubsDefi}}
   −
青铜雕像,弗赖堡大学,德国,1915年
+
* {{cite SEP |last=Cohen |first=S. Marc |title=Aristotle's Metaphysics: Substances and Universals |date=2016 | url-id=aristotle-metaphysics/#SubsUniv}}
   −
===Eponyms===
+
* {{cite journal |last=Corcoran |first=John |title=Aristotle's Demonstrative Logic |date=2009 |pages=1–20 |journal=History and Philosophy of Logic |volume=30|doi=10.1080/01445340802228362 |citeseerx=10.1.1.650.463|s2cid=8514675 }}
名字被用于命名地方
     −
The [[Aristotle Mountains]] in [[Antarctica]] are named after Aristotle. He was the first person known to conjecture, in his book ''[[Meteorology (Aristotle)|Meteorology]]'', the existence of a landmass in the southern high-latitude region and called it ''Antarctica''.{{sfn| Aristotle Mountains}} [[Aristoteles (crater)|Aristoteles]] is a crater on the Moon bearing the classical form of Aristotle's name.{{sfn| Aristoteles}}
+
* {{cite journal |last1=Day |first1=J. |title=Botany meets archaeology: people and plants in the past |year=2013 |pages=5805–16 |journal=Journal of Experimental Botany |volume=64 |issue=18 |doi=10.1093/jxb/ert068 |pmid=23669575|doi-access=free }}
   −
The Aristotle Mountains in Antarctica are named after Aristotle. He was the first person known to conjecture, in his book Meteorology, the existence of a landmass in the southern high-latitude region and called it Antarctica. Aristoteles is a crater on the Moon bearing the classical form of Aristotle's name.
+
* {{cite journal |last=Degnan |first=Michael |title=Recent Work in Aristotle's Logic |date=1994 |pages=81–89 |journal=Philosophical Books |volume=35 |issue=2 (April 1994)|doi=10.1111/j.1468-0149.1994.tb02858.x}}
   −
南极洲的亚里士多德山是以Aristotle的名字命名的。他是第一个在他的《气象学》一书中推测出南半球高纬度地区存在一个地块并将其称为南极洲的人。亚里士多德是月球上的一个陨石坑,是Aristotle名字的经典形式。
+
* {{cite book |last1=Deslauriers |first1=Marguerite |last2=Destrée |first2=Pierre |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=haCyAAAAQBAJ&pg=PA162 |title=The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle's Politics |date=2013 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |pages=157–162 |isbn=978-1107004689}}
    +
* {{cite book |last1=Dijksterhuis |first1=Eduard Jan |title=The Mechanization of the World Picture |date=1969 |translator=C. Dikshoorn |publisher=Princeton University Press}}
    +
* {{cite journal |last1=Drabkin |first1=Israel E. |title=Notes on the Laws of Motion in Aristotle |date=1938 |pages=60–84 |journal=The American Journal of Philology |volume=59 |issue=1 |jstor=90584|doi=10.2307/290584}}
   −
==See also==
+
* {{cite book |last=Durant |first=Will |title=The Story of Philosophy |date=2006 |author-link=Will Durant |origyear=1926 |publisher=Simon & Schuster |isbn=978-0-671-73916-4 | title-link=The Story of Philosophy}}
另请参见
  −
* [[Aristotelian Society]]亚里士多德学会
     −
* [[Conimbricenses]]孔布拉派
+
* {{cite book |last=Düring |first=Ingemar |title=Aristotle in the Ancient Biographical Tradition. By Ingemar Düring |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=MnKAQwAACAAJ |year=1957 |publisher=Almqvist & Wiksell in Komm.}}
   −
* [[Perfectionism (philosophy)|Perfectionism]] 完美主义
+
* {{cite book |last1=Ebenstein |first1=Alan |first2=William |last2=Ebenstein |title=Introduction to Political Thinkers |date=2002 | author-link=Alan O. Ebenstein |publisher=Wadsworth Group}}
    +
* {{cite journal |last=Evans |first=Nancy |s2cid=143750010 |date=2006 |title=Diotima and Demeter as Mystagogues in Plato's Symposium |journal=Hypatia |volume=21 |issue=2 |pages=1–27 |doi=10.1111/j.1527-2001.2006.tb01091.x |issn=1527-2001}}
    +
* {{cite journal |last=Filonik |first=Jakub |title=Athenian impiety trials: a reappraisal |date=2013 |pages=72–73 |journal=Dike |issue=16 |doi=10.13130/1128-8221/4290 | doi-access=free}}
   −
==References==
+
* {{cite book |last=Freeland |first=Cynthia A. |title=Feminist Interpretations of Aristotle |date=1998 |publisher=Penn State University Press |isbn=978-0-271-01730-3}}
    +
* {{cite book |last1=Garver |first1=Eugene |title=Aristotle's Rhetoric: An Art of Character |date=1994 |publisher=University of Chicago Press |isbn=978-0-226-28425-5 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=J2ldWwIQhHwC&q=Aristotle+ethos+pathos+logos}}
    +
* {{cite book |last=Gigon |first=Olof |title=Vita Aristotelis Marciana |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=a3ldDwAAQBAJ |date=2017 | orig-year=1965 |publisher=Walter de Gruyter |isbn=978-3-11-082017-1}}
   −
===Notes===
+
* {{cite book |last=Green |first=Peter |title=Alexander of Macedon |url=https://archive.org/details/alexanderofmaced0000gree |url-access=registration |date=1991 |publisher=University of California Press |isbn=978-0-520-27586-7}}
   −
{{notelist-ua | 30em}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Grimaldi |first=William M. A. |chapter=Studies in the Philosophy of Aristotle's ''Rhetoric'' |title=Landmark Essays on Aristotelian Rhetoric |date=1998 |page=71 |series=Landmark Essays |volume=14 | editor1-last=Enos | editor1-first=Richard Leo | editor2-last=Agnew | editor2-first=Lois Peters |publisher=Lawrence Erlbaum Associates |isbn=978-1-880393-32-1 | chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=sMihW5GdDzoC&q=Aristotle+paradeigma+and+enthymeme&pg=PA71}}
    +
* {{cite book |last=Guthrie |first=W. |title=A History of Greek Philosophy Vol. 1 |date=2010 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0-521-29420-1}}
    +
* {{cite book |last=Guthrie |first=W.K.C. |title=A history of Greek philosophy |volume=6: Aristotle: An Encounter |date=1990 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=8EG0yV0cGoEC |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0-521-38760-6}}
   −
===Citations===
+
* {{cite book |last=Haase |first=Wolfgang |title=Philosophie, Wissenschaften, Technik. Philosophie (Doxographica &#91;Forts. &#93;) |year=1992 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ifqGuiHo6eQC&pg=PA3862 |publisher=Walter de Gruyter |isbn=978-3-11-013699-9}}
   −
{{Reflist | colwidth=25em}}
+
* {{cite book |last1=Hall |first1=Edith |title=Aristotle's Way: How Ancient Wisdom Can Change Your Life |date=2018 |publisher=[[The Bodley Head]] |isbn=978-1-84792-407-0}}
    +
* {{cite book |last1=Halliwell |first1=Stephen |chapter=Inside and Outside the Work of Art |title=The Aesthetics of Mimesis: Ancient Texts and Modern Problems |date=2002 |pages=152–59 |author-link=Stephen Halliwell (academic) |publisher=Princeton University Press |isbn=978-0-691-09258-4 | chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=R8wctGFg12MC&q=Aristotle+mimesis}}
    +
* {{cite book |last=Hankinson |first=R.J. |title=Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought |date=1998 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-823745-7 |doi=10.1093/0199246564.001.0001}}
   −
===Sources===
+
* {{cite SEP |last=Hasse |first=Dag Nikolaus |title=Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on the Latin West |date=2014 | url-id=arabic-islamic-influence}}
    +
* {{cite book |last=Held |first=Julius |title=Rembrandt's Aristotle and Other Rembrandt Studies |url=https://archive.org/details/rembrandtsaristo0000held | url-access=registration |year=1969 |author-link=Julius S. Held |publisher=Princeton University Press}}
    +
* {{cite journal |last1=Hladký |first1=V. |last2=Havlíček |first2=J |year=2013 |url=http://ishe.org/wp-content/uploads/2015/04/HEB_2013_28_4_3-11.pdf |title=Was Tinbergen an Aristotelian? Comparison of Tinbergen's Four Whys and Aristotle's Four Causes |journal=Human Ethology Bulletin |volume=28 |issue=4 |pages=3–11}}
   −
{{refbegin|36em}}
+
* {{cite journal |last1=Holowchak |first1=Mark |title=Aristotle on Dreaming: What Goes on in Sleep when the 'Big Fire' goes out |date=1996 |pages=405–23 |journal=Ancient Philosophy |volume=16 |issue=2 |url=http://www.pdcnet.org/ancientphil/Ancient-Philosophy |doi=10.5840/ancientphil199616244}}
   −
* {{cite book |author=Aesop |author-link=Aesop |title=The Complete Fables By Aesop |date=1998 | translator-last=Temple | translator-first=Olivia | translator-last2=Temple | translator-first2=Robert |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ZB-rVxPvtPEC&pg=PR3 |publisher=Penguin Classics |isbn=978-0-14-044649-4}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Hooker |first=Sir William Jackson |author-link=William Jackson Hooker |title=The British Flora: Comprising the Phaenogamous, Or Flowering Plants, and the Ferns |year=1831 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=v-IYAAAAYAAJ&pg=PA219 |publisher=Longman |oclc=17317293}}
   −
* {{cite journal |last=Aird |first=W. C. |title=Discovery of the cardiovascular system: from Galen to William Harvey |year=2011 |pages=118–29 |journal=Journal of Thrombosis and Haemostasis |volume=9 |doi=10.1111/j.1538-7836.2011.04312.x |pmid=21781247 |s2cid=12092592}}
+
* {{cite book |last=House |first=Humphry |title=Aristotle's Poetics |date=1956 |url=https://archive.org/details/aristotlespoetic032945mbp |publisher=Rupert Hart-Davis}}
   −
* {{cite journal |last1=Allain |first1=Rhett |title=I'm So Totally Over Newton's Laws of Motion |journal=Wired |date=21 March 2016 |url=https://www.wired.com/2016/03/im-totally-newtons-laws-motion/ |access-date=11 May 2018}}
+
* {{cite web |last1=Hutchinson |first1=D. S. |last2=Johnson |first2=Monte Ransome |title=Exhortation to Philosophy |date=2015 |page=22 |url=http://www.protrepticus.info/protr2017x20.pdf |website=Protrepticus}}
   −
* {{cite book |last1=Allen |first1=Mark |last2=Fisher |first2=John H. |title=The Complete Poetry and Prose of Geoffrey Chaucer |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=eMSUXumf6psC&pg=PA17 |date=2011 |publisher=Cengage Learning |isbn=978-0-15-506041-8}}
+
* {{cite book |title=Aristotle: Introductory Readings | editor-first1=Terence | editor-last1=Irwin | editor-first2=Gail | editor-last2=Fine |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Tx8zjmHZ2NMC |year=1996 |publisher=Hackett Pub. |isbn=978-0-87220-339-6}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Anagnostopoulos |first=Georgios |title=A Companion to Aristotle |year=2013 |publisher=Wiley-Blackwell |isbn=978-1-118-59243-4}}
+
* {{cite news |last1=Jones |first1=Jonathan |title=Aristotle with a Bust of Homer, Rembrandt (1653) |date=27 July 2002 |url=https://www.theguardian.com/culture/2002/jul/27/art.homer |access-date=23 March 2018 |work=[[The Guardian]]}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Annas |first=Julia |title=Classical Greek Philosophy |date=2001 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-285357-8}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Jones |first=W. T. |title=The Classical Mind: A History of Western Philosophy |date=1980 |publisher=Harcourt Brace Jovanovich |isbn=978-0-15-538312-8}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Aquinas |first=Thomas |author-link=Thomas Aquinas |title=Summa Theologica |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=YiJCBAAAQBAJ |date=20 August 2013 |publisher=e-artnow |isbn=978-80-7484-292-4}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Kant |first=Immanuel |author-link=Immanuel Kant |title=Critique of Pure Reason |date=1787 |edition=Second |oclc=2323615}}
   −
* {{cite web | editor-first=Immanuel | editor-last=Bekker | orig-year=1831 |url=http://archive.org/details/bub_gb_jMz9zVYu9Q0C |title=Aristotelis Opera edidit Academia Regia Borussica Aristoteles graece |last=Aristoteles |date=31 January 2019 |publisher=apud Georgium Reimerum |access-date=31 January 2019 |via=Internet Archive |ref=CITEREFAristotelis Opera}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Kantor |first=J. R. |title=The Scientific Evolution of Psychology, Volume I |year=1963 |publisher=Principia Press |isbn=978-0-911188-25-7}}
   −
* {{cite web |title=Aristoteles |url=https://planetarynames.wr.usgs.gov/nomenclature/SearchResults;jsessionid=BE8F9834B709207DDD5D36EFA5506C7F |website=Gazetteer of Planetary Nomenclature. United States Geological Survey |access-date=19 March 2018 |ref=CITEREFAristoteles}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Kaufmann |first=Walter Arnold |title=Tragedy and Philosophy |date=1968 |publisher=Princeton University Press |isbn=978-0-691-02005-1 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=NTk9-180NbsC&q=Aristotle+Oedipus+the+King}}
   −
* {{cite web |title=Aristoteles-Park in Stagira |url=http://www.dimosaristoteli.gr/en/sights/aristotle-park |publisher=Dimos Aristoteli |access-date=20 March 2018 |ref=CITEREFAristoteles-Park in Stagira}}
+
* {{cite book |last1=Kennedy-Day |first1=Kiki |chapter=Aristotelianism in Islamic philosophy |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |date=1998 |publisher=Taylor and Francis |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-H002-1 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6}}
   −
* {{cite IEP |title=Aristotle (384–322 B.C.E.) |date=2009 | url-id=aristotl |issn=2161-0002 |ref=CITEREFAristotle (384–322 B.C.E.)}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Knight |first=Kelvin |title=Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics & Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre |date=2007 |publisher=Polity Press |isbn=978-0-7456-1977-4}}
   −
* {{cite web |title=Aristotle (Greek philosopher) |publisher=Britannica Online Encyclopedia |url=http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/34560/Aristotle |website=Britannica.com |access-date=26 April 2009 |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20090422103155/http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/34560/Aristotle |archivedate=22 April 2009 | url-status=live |ref=CITEREFAristotle (Greek philosopher)}}
+
* {{cite encyclopedia |last1=Kraut |first1=Richard |title=Aristotle's Ethics |date=1 May 2001 |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-ethics/ |encyclopedia=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |accessdate=19 March 2018}}
   −
* {{cite web |url=http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/metaphysics.html |publisher=The Internet Classics Archive |title=Metaphysics |last=Aristotle |website=classics.mit.edu |access-date=30 January 2019 |ref=CITEREFMetaphysics}}
+
* {{cite SEP |last=Kuhn |first=Heinrich |title=Aristotelianism in the Renaissance |date=2018 | url-id=aristotelianism-renaissance}}
   −
* {{cite web |url=http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/meteorology.html |publisher=The Internet Classics Archive |title=Meteorology |last=Aristotle |website=classics.mit.edu |access-date=30 January 2019 |ref=CITEREFMeteorology}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Kukkonen |first=Taneli |title=The classical tradition |year=2010 | editor-last=Grafton | editor-first=Anthony | display-editors=etal |publisher=Belknap Press of Harvard University Press |isbn=978-0-674-03572-0}}
   −
* {{cite web |url=http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/nicomachaen.html |publisher=The Internet Classics Archive |title=Nicomachean Ethics |author=Aristotle |website=classics.mit.edu |ref=CITEREFNicomachean Ethics}}
+
* {{cite SEP |last=Lagerlund |first=Henrik |title=Medieval Theories of the Syllogism |date=2016 | url-id=medieval-syllogism}}
   −
* {{cite web |url=http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/soul.html |publisher=The Internet Classics Archive |title=On the Soul |last=Aristotle |website=classics.mit.edu |access-date=30 January 2019 |ref=CITEREFOn the Soul}}
+
* {{cite SEP |last=Lagerlund |first=Henrik |title=Medieval Theories of the Syllogism | url-id=medieval-syllogism}}
   −
* {{cite web |url=http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/physics.html |publisher=The Internet Classics Archive |title=Physics |author=Aristotle |website=classics.mit.edu |access-date=31 January 2019 |ref=CITEREFPhysics}}
+
* {{cite web |last=Lahanas |first=Michael |title=Optics and ancient Greeks |url=http://www.mlahanas.de/Greeks/Optics.htm |website=Mlahanas.de |access-date=26 April 2009 |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20090411051535/http://www.mlahanas.de/Greeks/Optics.htm |archivedate=11 April 2009 | url-status=dead}}
   −
* {{cite web |url=http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/poetics.html |publisher=The Internet Classics Archive |title=Poetics |last=Aristotle |website=classics.mit.edu |access-date=30 January 2019 |ref=CITEREFPoetics}}
+
* {{cite book |last1=Lee |first1=Ellen Wardwell |last2=Robinson |first2=Anne |title=Indianapolis Museum of Art: Highlights of the Collection |year=2005 |publisher=[[Indianapolis Museum of Art]] |isbn=978-0-936260-77-8}}
   −
* {{cite web |url=http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/politics.html |publisher=The Internet Classics Archive |title=Politics |last=Aristotle |website=classics.mit.edu |access-date=30 January 2019 |ref=CITEREFPolitics}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Leroi |first=Armand Marie |title=The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science |date=2015 |author-link=Armand Marie Leroi |titlelink=Aristotle's Lagoon |publisher=Bloomsbury |isbn=978-1-4088-3622-4}}
   −
* {{cite web |url=http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/prior.html |publisher=The Internet Classics Archive |title=Prior Analytics |last=Aristotle |website=classics.mit.edu |ref=CITEREFPrior Analytics}}
+
* {{cite web |last1=Leroi |first1=Armand Marie (Presenter) |author-link=Armand Marie Leroi |title=Aristotle's Lagoon: Embryo Inside a Chicken's Egg |date=3 May 2011 |url=http://www.bbc.co.uk/programmes/p00gqlyy |publisher=BBC |access-date=17 November 2016}}
   −
* {{cite web |author=Aristotle |title=Rhetoric | translator-first=W. Rhys | translator-last=Roberts |url=http://rhetoric.eserver.org/aristotle/rhet1-5.html |archivedate=13 February 2015  |ref=CITEREFRhetoric| archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150213075039/http://rhetoric.eserver.org/aristotle/rhet1-5.html}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Lindberg |first=David |title=The Beginnings of Western Science |url=https://archive.org/details/beginningsofwest00lind | url-access=registration |date=1992 |publisher=University of Chicago Press |isbn=978-0-226-48205-7}}
   −
* {{cite web |title=Aristotle Mountains |url=https://data.aad.gov.au/aadc/gaz/scar/display_name.cfm?gaz_id=137410 |work=[[Scientific Committee on Antarctic Research|SCAR]] [[Composite Antarctic Gazetteer]] |publisher=[[Programma Nazionale di Ricerche in Antartide]] |agency=[[Department of the Environment and Energy]], [[Australian Antarctic Division]], [[Australian Government]] | access-date=1 March 2018 |ref=CITEREFAristotle Mountains}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Lloyd |first=G. E. R. |title=The critic of Plato |date=1968 |author-link=G. E. R. Lloyd |work=Aristotle: The Growth and Structure of His Thought |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0-521-09456-6}}
   −
* {{cite book |author=Aristotle |title=Politics-Ethics, In Early Economic Thought: Selections from Economic Literature Prior to Adam Smith |date=1948 |editor=Monroe, Arthur E. |publisher=Harvard University Press}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Lloyd |first=G. E. R. |title=Causes and correlations |date=1996 | author-link=G. E. R. Lloyd |work=Adversaries and Authorities: Investigations into ancient Greek and Chinese science |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0-521-55695-8}}
   −
* {{cite book |author=Aristotle |title=The Politics |url=https://archive.org/details/politics0000aris |url-access=registration |date=1984 |editor=Lord, Carnes |publisher=University of Chicago Press |isbn=978-0-226-92184-6}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Lovejoy |first=Arthur O. |title=The Great Chain of Being: A Study of the History of an Idea |date=31 January 1976 |author-link=Arthur O. Lovejoy |publisher=Harvard University Press |isbn=978-0-674-36153-9}}
   −
* {{cite book |author=Aristotle |title=Politics |date=2009 |others=Translated by Ernest Barker and revised with introduction and notes by R.F. Stalley |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-953873-7 |edition=1st |origyear=1995}}
+
* {{cite web |title=Lucas Cranach the Elder{{!}} Phyllis and Aristotle | url=http://www.sothebys.com/en/auctions/ecatalogue/2008/important-old-master-paintings-including-european-works-of-art-n08404/lot.78.html | publisher=[[Sotheby's]] | access-date=23 March 2018 | date=2008 | ref=CITEREFLucas Cranach the Elder}}
   −
* {{cite book |author=Aristotle | translator-last1=Sachs | translator-first1=Joe |title=Aristotle's ''Metaphysics'' |year=1999 |publisher=Green Lion Press}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Lyell |first=Charles |title=Principles of Geology |date=1832 |author-link=Charles Lyell |url=https://archive.org/details/principlesgeolo01unkngoog |oclc=609586345|publisher=J. Murray, 1832}}
   −
* {{cite web |title=Aristotle and Phyllis |url=http://www.artic.edu/aic/collections/artwork/20121 |publisher=Art Institute Chicago |access-date=22 March 2018 |ref=CITEREFAristotle Phyllis}}
+
* {{cite journal |last=MacDougall-Shackleton |first=Scott A. |title=The levels of analysis revisited |date=27 July 2011 |pages=2076–85 |journal=Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences |volume=366 |issue=1574 |doi=10.1098/rstb.2010.0363 |pmc=3130367 |pmid=21690126}}
   −
* {{cite web |url=https://www.collinsdictionary.com/dictionary/english/aristotle |title=Aristotle definition and meaning |publisher=Collins English Dictionary |website=www.collinsdictionary.com |ref=CITEREFCollins English Dictionary}}
+
* {{cite SEP |last=Machamer |first=Peter |title=Galileo Galilei |date=2017 | url-id=galileo}}
   −
* {{cite news |title=Aristotle with a Bust of Homer, Rembrandt (1653) |date=27 July 2002 |url=https://www.theguardian.com/culture/2002/jul/27/art.homer |newspaper=[[The Guardian]] |access-date=23 March 2018 |ref=CITEREFAristotle with Bust2002}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Magee |first=Bryan |title=The Story of Philosophy |date=2010 |author-link=Bryan Magee |publisher=Dorling Kindersley |isbn=978-0-241-24126-4}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Averroes |title=Commentarium Magnum in Aristotelis De Anima Libros|editor-last=Crawford|editor-first=F. Stuart |publisher=Mediaeval Academy of America |oclc=611422373 |date=1953}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Mason |first=Stephen F. |title=A History of the Sciences |date=1979 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=PLlMAAAAMAAJ |publisher=Collier Books |isbn=978-0-02-093400-4 |oclc=924760574}}
   −
* {{cite book |last1=Barnes |first1=Jonathan |title=Aristotle: A Very Short Introduction |date=1982 |author-link=Jonathan Barnes |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-285408-7}}
+
* {{cite web |last1=Mayhew |first1=Robert |title=Aristotle For Objectivists |url=https://estore.aynrand.org/p/692/aristotle-for-objectivists-mp3-download |publisher=The Ayn Rand Institute |access-date=29 March 2018}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Barnes |first=Jonathan |chapter=Life and Work |title=The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle |date=1995 |author-link=Jonathan Barnes |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0-521-42294-9 | chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=WBqQOqM5dfsC}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Mayr |first=Ernst |author-link=Ernst Mayr |title=The Growth of Biological Thought |url=https://archive.org/details/growthofbiologic00mayr | url-access=registration |date=1982 |publisher=Belknap Press |isbn=978-0-674-36446-2}}
   −
* {{cite book |last1=Barnes |first1=Jonathan |author-link=Jonathan Barnes |last2=Griffin |first2=Miriam Tamara |title=Philosophia Togata: Plato and Aristotle at Rome. II |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=r18BAAAACAAJ |year=1999 |publisher=Clarendon Press |isbn=978-0-19-815222-4}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Mayr |first=Ernst |author-link=Ernst Mayr |title=The Growth of Biological Thought |date=1985 |publisher=Harvard University Press |isbn=978-0-674-36446-2}}
   −
* {{cite book |last1=Bergstrom |first1=Carl T. |last2=Dugatkin |first2=Lee Alan |title=Evolution |date=2012 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=SeaEZwEACAAJ |publisher=Norton |isbn=978-0-393-92592-0}}
+
* {{cite book |last=McLeisch |first=Kenneth Cole |title=Aristotle: The Great Philosophers |date=1999 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-0-415-92392-7|url=https://archive.org/details/aristotle00mcle}}
   −
* {{cite journal |last=Blits |first=Kathleen C. |title=Aristotle: Form, function, and comparative anatomy |date=15 April 1999 |pages=58–63 |journal=The Anatomical Record |volume=257 |issue=2 |doi=10.1002/(SICI)1097-0185(19990415)257:2<58::AID-AR6>3.0.CO;2-I |pmid=10321433}}
+
* {{cite book |title=Aristotle to Zoos: a philosophical dictionary of biology |year=1984 |last1=Medawar |first1=Peter B. |author-link=Peter Medawar |last2=Medawar |first2=J. S. |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-283043-2}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Bloch |first=David |title=Aristotle on Memory and Recollection |date=2007 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=QwTHng_5RqAC&q=Aristotle+on+Memory+and+Recollection&pg=PR9 |isbn=978-90-04-16046-0}}
+
* {{cite journal |last1=Miller |first1=Willard M. |title=Aristotle on Necessity, Chance, and Spontaneity |year=1973 |pages=204–13 |journal=New Scholasticism |volume=47 |issue=2 |doi=10.5840/newscholas197347237}}
   −
* {{cite book | chapter-url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/logic-ancient/ |title=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |first=Susanne |last=Bobzien |chapter=Ancient Logic | editor-first=Edward N. | editor-last=Zalta |date=2015 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |via=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy}}
+
* {{cite journal |last1=Modrak |first1=Deborah |title=Dreams and Method in Aristotle |date=2009 |pages=169–81 |journal=Skepsis: A Journal for Philosophy and Interdisciplinary Research |volume=20}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Boole |first=George |author-link=George Boole |title=The Laws of Thought |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=nUEQAQAAIAAJ |year=2003 | orig-year=1854 |publisher=Prometheus Books |isbn=978-1-59102-089-9}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Moore |first=Ruth |title=The Earth We Live On |url=https://archive.org/details/earthweliveonsto00moor | url-access=registration |year=1956 |publisher=Alfred A. Knopf |oclc=1024467091}}
   −
* {{cite web |last=Campbell |first=Michael |title=Behind the Name: Meaning, Origin and History of the Name "Aristotle" |url=http://www.behindthename.com/name/aristotle |website=Behind the Name |access-date=6 April 2012}}
+
* {{cite journal |last=Morsink |first=Johannes |title=Was Aristotle's Biology Sexist? |date=Spring 1979 |pages=83–112 |jstor=4330727 |journal=Journal of the History of Biology |volume=12 |issue=1 |doi=10.1007/bf00128136 |pmid=11615776 |s2cid=6090923}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Carruthers |first=Mary |title=The Book of Memory: A Study of Memory in Medieval Culture |date=2007 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=dntrAnqfIasC&q=The+book+of+memory:+the+study+of+memory+in+medieval+times&pg=PR8 |isbn=978-0-521-42973-3}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Nasr |first=Seyyed Hossein |title=The Islamic Intellectual Tradition in Persia |date=1996 |publisher=Curzon Press |isbn=978-0-7007-0314-2}}
   −
* {{cite book |last1=Carteron |first1=Henri |title=Notion de Force dans le Systeme d'Aristote |date=1923 |publisher=J. Vrin |language=French}}
+
* {{cite web |last1=Phelan |first1=Joseph |title=The Philosopher as Hero: Raphael's The School of Athens |date=September 2002 |url=http://www.artcyclopedia.com/feature-2002-09.html |publisher=ArtCyclopedia |access-date=23 March 2018}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Cicero |first=Marcus Tullius |author-link=Cicero |chapter=Book II, chapter XXXVIII, §119 |title=The Academica of Cicero 106–43 BC |date=1874 | editor-first=James S. | editor-last=Reid |publisher=Macmillan}}
+
* {{cite web |url=https://www.louvre.fr/en/oeuvre-notices/phyllis-and-aristotle |title=Phyllis and Aristotle |date=1 February 2019 |via=Musee du Louvre |ref=CITEREFPhyllis and Aristotle}}
   −
* {{cite web |last1=Cohen |first1=S. Marc |title=Aristotle's Metaphysics |date=8 October 2000 |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-metaphysics/ |website=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=The Metaphysics Research Lab Center for the Study of Language and Information |access-date=14 November 2018}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Pickover |first=Clifford A. |title=The Math Book: From Pythagoras to the 57th Dimension, 250 Milestones in the History of Mathematics |year=2009 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=JrslMKTgSZwC&pg=PA52 |publisher=Sterling |isbn=978-1-4027-5796-9}}
   −
* {{cite SEP |last=Cohen |first=S. Marc |title=Aristotle's Metaphysics |date=2016 | url-id=aristotle-metaphysics/#ActuPote}}
+
* {{cite web |url=http://penelope.uchicago.edu/Thayer/e/roman/texts/plutarch/lives/alexander*/3.html |title=Plutarch &ndash; Life of Alexander (Part 1 of 7) |date=1919 |publisher=Loeb Classical Library |website=penelope.uchicago.edu |access-date=31 January 2019 |ref=CITEREFPlutarch1919}}
   −
* {{cite SEP |last=Cohen |first=S. Marc |title=Aristotle's Metaphysics: Substance and Definition |date=2016 | url-id=aristotle-metaphysics/#SubsDefi}}
+
* {{cite web |title=Predicate Logic |url=https://www.cs.utexas.edu/~schrum2/cs301k/lec/topic04-predicateLogic.pdf |publisher=University of Texas |access-date=29 March 2018 |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20180329221535/https://www.cs.utexas.edu/~schrum2/cs301k/lec/topic04-predicateLogic.pdf |archivedate=29 March 2018 | url-status=live |ref=CITEREFPredicate Logic}}
   −
* {{cite SEP |last=Cohen |first=S. Marc |title=Aristotle's Metaphysics: Substances and Universals |date=2016 | url-id=aristotle-metaphysics/#SubsUniv}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Rhodes |first=Frank Harold Trevor |title=Evolution |date=1974 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=EWGt0bff8agC |publisher=Golden Press |isbn=978-0-307-64360-5}}
   −
* {{cite journal |last=Corcoran |first=John |title=Aristotle's Demonstrative Logic |date=2009 |pages=1–20 |journal=History and Philosophy of Logic |volume=30|doi=10.1080/01445340802228362 |citeseerx=10.1.1.650.463|s2cid=8514675 }}
+
* {{cite book |last=Robbins |first=Lionel |title=A History of Economic Thought: The LSE Lectures |date=2000 |editor1=Medema, Steven G. |editor2=Samuels, Warren J. |publisher=Princeton University Press}}
   −
* {{cite journal |last1=Day |first1=J. |title=Botany meets archaeology: people and plants in the past |year=2013 |pages=5805–16 |journal=Journal of Experimental Botany |volume=64 |issue=18 |doi=10.1093/jxb/ert068 |pmid=23669575|doi-access=free }}
+
* {{cite book |last1=Rorty |first1=Amélie Oksenberg |chapter=Structuring Rhetoric |date=1996 |title=Essays on Aristotle's ''Rhetoric'' | editor-last=Rorty | editor-first=Amélie Oksenberg |publisher=University of California Press |isbn=978-0-520-20227-6 | chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=vd7fEb1wOmYC&q=Aristotle+deliberative+forensic+and+epideictic&pg=PA6| url-access=registration |url=https://archive.org/details/essaysonaristotl0000unse}}
   −
* {{cite journal |last=Degnan |first=Michael |title=Recent Work in Aristotle's Logic |date=1994 |pages=81–89 |journal=Philosophical Books |volume=35 |issue=2 (April 1994)|doi=10.1111/j.1468-0149.1994.tb02858.x}}
+
* {{cite journal |last1=Rovelli |first1=Carlo |author-link=Carlo Rovelli |title=Aristotle's Physics: A Physicist's Look |year=2015 |pages=23–40 |journal=Journal of the American Philosophical Association |volume=1 |issue=1 |doi=10.1017/apa.2014.11 |arxiv=1312.4057 |s2cid=44193681}}
   −
* {{cite book |last1=Deslauriers |first1=Marguerite |last2=Destrée |first2=Pierre |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=haCyAAAAQBAJ&pg=PA162 |title=The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle's Politics |date=2013 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |pages=157–162 |isbn=978-1107004689}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Russell |first=Bertrand |title=A history of western philosophy |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=RZc3AAAAIAAJ |year=1972 |publisher=Simon and Schuster |isbn=978-0-671-31400-2}}
   −
* {{cite book |last1=Dijksterhuis |first1=Eduard Jan |title=The Mechanization of the World Picture |date=1969 |translator=C. Dikshoorn |publisher=Princeton University Press}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Sedley |first=David |title=Creationism and Its Critics in Antiquity |year=2007 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=SgRuJEfzUG8C |publisher=University of California Press |isbn=978-0-520-25364-3}}
   −
* {{cite journal |last1=Drabkin |first1=Israel E. |title=Notes on the Laws of Motion in Aristotle |date=1938 |pages=60–84 |journal=The American Journal of Philology |volume=59 |issue=1 |jstor=90584|doi=10.2307/290584}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Shields |first=Christopher |title=The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=vTVsrl0mnH4C |date=2012 |publisher=OUP USA |isbn=978-0-19-518748-9}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Durant |first=Will |title=The Story of Philosophy |date=2006 |author-link=Will Durant |origyear=1926 |publisher=Simon & Schuster |isbn=978-0-671-73916-4 | title-link=The Story of Philosophy}}
+
* {{cite SEP |last=Shields |first=Christopher |title=Aristotle's Psychology |date=2016 |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/aristotle/ |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University | editor-last=Zalta | editor-first=Edward N. |edition=Winter 2016}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Düring |first=Ingemar |title=Aristotle in the Ancient Biographical Tradition. By Ingemar Düring |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=MnKAQwAACAAJ |year=1957 |publisher=Almqvist & Wiksell in Komm.}}
+
* {{cite book |last1=Shute |first1=Clarence |title=The Psychology of Aristotle: An Analysis of the Living Being |date=1941 |publisher=Columbia University Press |oclc=936606202}}
   −
* {{cite book |last1=Ebenstein |first1=Alan |first2=William |last2=Ebenstein |title=Introduction to Political Thinkers |date=2002 | author-link=Alan O. Ebenstein |publisher=Wadsworth Group}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Sikka |first=Sonya |title=Forms of Transcendence: Heidegger and Medieval Mystical Theology |year=1997 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=UNYIDrA0zrYC&pg=PA265 |publisher=SUNY Press |isbn=978-0-7914-3345-4}}
   −
* {{cite journal |last=Evans |first=Nancy |s2cid=143750010 |date=2006 |title=Diotima and Demeter as Mystagogues in Plato's Symposium |journal=Hypatia |volume=21 |issue=2 |pages=1–27 |doi=10.1111/j.1527-2001.2006.tb01091.x |issn=1527-2001}}
+
* {{cite SEP |last=Smith |first=Robin |title=Aristotle's Logic |date=2017 | url-id=aristotle-logic}}
   −
* {{cite journal |last=Filonik |first=Jakub |title=Athenian impiety trials: a reappraisal |date=2013 |pages=72–73 |journal=Dike |issue=16 |doi=10.13130/1128-8221/4290 | doi-access=free}}
+
* {{cite book |url=http://archive.org/details/dictionarygreek09smitgoog |title=Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology |last=Smith |first=William George | orig-year=1869 |year=2007 |publisher=J. Walton |access-date=30 January 2019 |via=Internet Archive}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Freeland |first=Cynthia A. |title=Feminist Interpretations of Aristotle |date=1998 |publisher=Penn State University Press |isbn=978-0-271-01730-3}}
+
* {{cite book |last1=Sorabji |first1=R. |title=Aristotle on Memory |date=2006 |publisher=University of Chicago Press |location=Chicago |page=54 |edition=2nd |quote=And this is exactly why we hunt for the successor, starting in our thoughts from the present or from something else, and from something similar, or opposite, or neighbouring. By this means recollection occurs...}}
   −
* {{cite book |last1=Garver |first1=Eugene |title=Aristotle's Rhetoric: An Art of Character |date=1994 |publisher=University of Chicago Press |isbn=978-0-226-28425-5 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=J2ldWwIQhHwC&q=Aristotle+ethos+pathos+logos}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Sorabji |first=Richard |title=Aristotle Transformed |date=1990 |author-link=Richard Sorabji |publisher=Duckworth |isbn=978-0-7156-2254-4}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Gigon |first=Olof |title=Vita Aristotelis Marciana |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=a3ldDwAAQBAJ |date=2017 | orig-year=1965 |publisher=Walter de Gruyter |isbn=978-3-11-082017-1}}
+
* {{cite journal |last1=Staley |first1=Kevin |title=Al-Kindi on Creation: Aristotle's Challenge to Islam |journal=Journal of the History of Ideas |date=1989 |volume=50 |issue=3 |pages=355–370 |jstor=2709566|doi=10.2307/2709566}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Green |first=Peter |title=Alexander of Macedon |url=https://archive.org/details/alexanderofmaced0000gree |url-access=registration |date=1991 |publisher=University of California Press |isbn=978-0-520-27586-7}}
+
* {{cite web |last1=Susskind |first1=Leonard |title=Classical Mechanics, Lectures 2, 3 |date=3 October 2011 |authorlink1=Leonard Susskind |url=http://theoreticalminimum.com/courses/classical-mechanics/2011/fall/lecture-2 |website=The Theoretical Minimum |access-date=11 May 2018}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Grimaldi |first=William M. A. |chapter=Studies in the Philosophy of Aristotle's ''Rhetoric'' |title=Landmark Essays on Aristotelian Rhetoric |date=1998 |page=71 |series=Landmark Essays |volume=14 | editor1-last=Enos | editor1-first=Richard Leo | editor2-last=Agnew | editor2-first=Lois Peters |publisher=Lawrence Erlbaum Associates |isbn=978-1-880393-32-1 | chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=sMihW5GdDzoC&q=Aristotle+paradeigma+and+enthymeme&pg=PA71}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Taylor |first=Henry Osborn |chapter=Chapter 3: Aristotle's Biology |title=Greek Biology and Medicine |date=1922 |author-link=Henry Osborn Taylor |archivedate=27 March 2006 | chapter-url=http://www.ancientlibrary.com/medicine/0051.html |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20060327222953/http://www.ancientlibrary.com/medicine/0051.html | url-status=dead |access-date=3 January 2017}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Guthrie |first=W. |title=A History of Greek Philosophy Vol. 1 |date=2010 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0-521-29420-1}}
+
* {{cite web |title=The School of Athens by Raphael |url=http://www.visual-arts-cork.com/famous-paintings/school-of-athens.htm |publisher=Visual Arts Cork |access-date=22 March 2018 |ref=CITEREFSchool of Athens}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Guthrie |first=W.K.C. |title=A history of Greek philosophy |volume=6: Aristotle: An Encounter |date=1990 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=8EG0yV0cGoEC |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0-521-38760-6}}
+
* {{cite web |last=Stewart |first=Jessica |title=The Story Behind Raphael's Masterpiece 'The School of Athens' |url=https://mymodernmet.com/school-of-athens-raphael/ |quote=Plato's gesture toward the sky is thought to indicate his Theory of Forms. ... Conversely, Aristotle's hand is a visual representation of his belief that knowledge comes from experience. Empiricism, as it is known, theorizes that humans must have concrete evidence to support their ideas |website=My Modern Met |year=2019 |access-date=29 March 2019}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Haase |first=Wolfgang |title=Philosophie, Wissenschaften, Technik. Philosophie (Doxographica &#91;Forts. &#93;) |year=1992 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ifqGuiHo6eQC&pg=PA3862 |publisher=Walter de Gruyter |isbn=978-3-11-013699-9}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Thompson |first=D'Arcy |author-link=D'Arcy Wentworth Thompson |title=Historia animalium |date=1910 |work=The works of Aristotle translated into English |editor1=Ross, W. D. |editor2=Smith, J. A. |publisher=Clarendon Press |url=https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/history/index.html |oclc=39273217}}
   −
* {{cite book |last1=Hall |first1=Edith |title=Aristotle's Way: How Ancient Wisdom Can Change Your Life |date=2018 |publisher=[[The Bodley Head]] |isbn=978-1-84792-407-0}}
+
* {{cite book |last=Warren |first=Howard C. |title=A History of the Association of Psychology |date=1921 |author-link=Howard C. Warren |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=D4IXAAAAYAAJ&q=The+history+of+the+association+of+psychology&pg=PA3 |oclc=21010604 <!--dlc-->}}
   −
* {{cite book |last1=Halliwell |first1=Stephen |chapter=Inside and Outside the Work of Art |title=The Aesthetics of Mimesis: Ancient Texts and Modern Problems |date=2002 |pages=152–59 |author-link=Stephen Halliwell (academic) |publisher=Princeton University Press |isbn=978-0-691-09258-4 | chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=R8wctGFg12MC&q=Aristotle+mimesis}}
+
* {{cite book |last1=Webb |first1=Wilse |title=Dreamtime and dreamwork: Decoding the language of the night |date=1990 |publisher=Jeremy P. Tarcher |isbn=978-0-87477-594-5|url=https://archive.org/details/dreamtimedreamwo00kriprich}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Hankinson |first=R.J. |title=Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought |date=1998 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-823745-7 |doi=10.1093/0199246564.001.0001}}
+
* {{cite news |title=When libraries were on a roll |date=19 May 2001 |url=https://www.telegraph.co.uk/culture/4723624/When-libraries-were-on-a-roll.html |publisher=Telegraph Media Group |access-date=29 June 2017 |ref=CITEREFWhen libraries were2001}}
   −
* {{cite SEP |last=Hasse |first=Dag Nikolaus |title=Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on the Latin West |date=2014 | url-id=arabic-islamic-influence}}
+
* {{cite SEP |last=Wildberg | first Christian |title=John Philoponus |date=2016 | url-id=philoponus}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Held |first=Julius |title=Rembrandt's Aristotle and Other Rembrandt Studies |url=https://archive.org/details/rembrandtsaristo0000held | url-access=registration |year=1969 |author-link=Julius S. Held |publisher=Princeton University Press}}
+
* {{cite SEP |title=Aristotle's Influence |date=2018 | url-id=aristotle-influence |edition=Spring 2018 |ref=CITEREFAristotle's Influence2018}}
   −
* {{cite journal |last1=Hladký |first1=V. |last2=Havlíček |first2=J |year=2013 |url=http://ishe.org/wp-content/uploads/2015/04/HEB_2013_28_4_3-11.pdf |title=Was Tinbergen an Aristotelian? Comparison of Tinbergen's Four Whys and Aristotle's Four Causes |journal=Human Ethology Bulletin |volume=28 |issue=4 |pages=3–11}}
+
{{refend}}
   −
* {{cite journal |last1=Holowchak |first1=Mark |title=Aristotle on Dreaming: What Goes on in Sleep when the 'Big Fire' goes out |date=1996 |pages=405–23 |journal=Ancient Philosophy |volume=16 |issue=2 |url=http://www.pdcnet.org/ancientphil/Ancient-Philosophy |doi=10.5840/ancientphil199616244}}
     −
* {{cite book |last=Hooker |first=Sir William Jackson |author-link=William Jackson Hooker |title=The British Flora: Comprising the Phaenogamous, Or Flowering Plants, and the Ferns |year=1831 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=v-IYAAAAYAAJ&pg=PA219 |publisher=Longman |oclc=17317293}}
     −
* {{cite book |last=House |first=Humphry |title=Aristotle's Poetics |date=1956 |url=https://archive.org/details/aristotlespoetic032945mbp |publisher=Rupert Hart-Davis}}
+
The secondary literature on Aristotle is vast. The following is only a small selection.
   −
* {{cite web |last1=Hutchinson |first1=D. S. |last2=Johnson |first2=Monte Ransome |title=Exhortation to Philosophy |date=2015 |page=22 |url=http://www.protrepticus.info/protr2017x20.pdf |website=Protrepticus}}
+
关于亚里士多德的二手文献很多。以下只是一小部分选择。
   −
* {{cite book |title=Aristotle: Introductory Readings | editor-first1=Terence | editor-last1=Irwin | editor-first2=Gail | editor-last2=Fine |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Tx8zjmHZ2NMC |year=1996 |publisher=Hackett Pub. |isbn=978-0-87220-339-6}}
+
==Further reading==
   −
* {{cite news |last1=Jones |first1=Jonathan |title=Aristotle with a Bust of Homer, Rembrandt (1653) |date=27 July 2002 |url=https://www.theguardian.com/culture/2002/jul/27/art.homer |access-date=23 March 2018 |work=[[The Guardian]]}}
+
The secondary literature on Aristotle is vast. The following is only a small selection.
   −
* {{cite book |last=Jones |first=W. T. |title=The Classical Mind: A History of Western Philosophy |date=1980 |publisher=Harcourt Brace Jovanovich |isbn=978-0-15-538312-8}}
+
{{refbegin | 30em}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Kant |first=Immanuel |author-link=Immanuel Kant |title=Critique of Pure Reason |date=1787 |edition=Second |oclc=2323615}}
+
* [[J. L. Ackrill|Ackrill, J. L.]] (1997). ''Essays on Plato and Aristotle'', Oxford University Press.
   −
* {{cite book |last=Kantor |first=J. R. |title=The Scientific Evolution of Psychology, Volume I |year=1963 |publisher=Principia Press |isbn=978-0-911188-25-7}}
+
*{{cite book |last=Ackrill |first=J.L. |title=Aristotle the Philosopher |publisher=Oxford University Press |date=1981}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Kaufmann |first=Walter Arnold |title=Tragedy and Philosophy |date=1968 |publisher=Princeton University Press |isbn=978-0-691-02005-1 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=NTk9-180NbsC&q=Aristotle+Oedipus+the+King}}
+
*{{Cite book |last=Adler |first=Mortimer J. |author-link=Mortimer Adler |title=Aristotle for Everybody |publisher=Macmillan |date=1978 | title-link=Aristotle for Everybody}}
   −
* {{cite book |last1=Kennedy-Day |first1=Kiki |chapter=Aristotelianism in Islamic philosophy |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |date=1998 |publisher=Taylor and Francis |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-H002-1 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6}}
+
*{{cite book |last=Ammonius | editor1-last=Cohen | editor1-first=S. Marc | editor2-last=Matthews | editor2-first=Gareth B |title=On Aristotle's Categories |publisher=Cornell University Press |date=1991 |isbn=978-0-8014-2688-9}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Knight |first=Kelvin |title=Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics & Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre |date=2007 |publisher=Polity Press |isbn=978-0-7456-1977-4}}
+
*{{cite book |last=Aristotle |title=The Works of Aristotle Translated into English Under the Editorship of W.D. Ross, 12 vols |publisher=[[Clarendon Press]] |date=1908–1952}} These translations are available in several places online; see External links.
   −
* {{cite encyclopedia |last1=Kraut |first1=Richard |title=Aristotle's Ethics |date=1 May 2001 |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-ethics/ |encyclopedia=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |accessdate=19 March 2018}}
+
* Bakalis, Nikolaos. (2005). ''Handbook of Greek Philosophy: From Thales to the Stoics Analysis and Fragments'', Trafford Publishing{{ISBN | 978-1412048439}}
   −
* {{cite SEP |last=Kuhn |first=Heinrich |title=Aristotelianism in the Renaissance |date=2018 | url-id=aristotelianism-renaissance}}
+
*{{Cite book |last=Bocheński |first=I. M. |title=Ancient Formal Logic |publisher=North-Holland |date=1951}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Kukkonen |first=Taneli |title=The classical tradition |year=2010 | editor-last=Grafton | editor-first=Anthony | display-editors=etal |publisher=Belknap Press of Harvard University Press |isbn=978-0-674-03572-0}}
+
* Bolotin, David (1998). ''An Approach to Aristotle's Physics: With Particular Attention to the Role of His Manner of Writing.'' Albany: SUNY Press. A contribution to our understanding of how to read Aristotle's scientific works.
   −
* {{cite SEP |last=Lagerlund |first=Henrik |title=Medieval Theories of the Syllogism |date=2016 | url-id=medieval-syllogism}}
+
* [[Myles Burnyeat|Burnyeat, Myles F.]] ''et al.'' (1979). ''Notes on Book Zeta of Aristotle's Metaphysics''. Oxford: Sub-faculty of Philosophy.
   −
* {{cite SEP |last=Lagerlund |first=Henrik |title=Medieval Theories of the Syllogism | url-id=medieval-syllogism}}
+
*{{cite book | editor1-last=Cantor | editor1-first=Norman F. | editor2-first=Peter L. | editor2-last=Klein |title=Ancient Thought: Plato and Aristotle |volume=1 |series=Monuments of Western Thought |publisher=Blaisdell |date=1969}}
   −
* {{cite web |last=Lahanas |first=Michael |title=Optics and ancient Greeks |url=http://www.mlahanas.de/Greeks/Optics.htm |website=Mlahanas.de |access-date=26 April 2009 |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20090411051535/http://www.mlahanas.de/Greeks/Optics.htm |archivedate=11 April 2009 | url-status=dead}}
+
*{{cite journal |last1=Chappell |first1=V. |year=1973 |title=Aristotle's Conception of Matter |url= |journal=Journal of Philosophy |volume=70 |issue=19 |pages=679–96 |doi=10.2307/2025076 |jstor=2025076}}
   −
* {{cite book |last1=Lee |first1=Ellen Wardwell |last2=Robinson |first2=Anne |title=Indianapolis Museum of Art: Highlights of the Collection |year=2005 |publisher=[[Indianapolis Museum of Art]] |isbn=978-0-936260-77-8}}
+
* Code, Alan (1995). Potentiality in Aristotle's Science and Metaphysics, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 76.
   −
* {{cite book |last=Leroi |first=Armand Marie |title=The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science |date=2015 |author-link=Armand Marie Leroi |titlelink=Aristotle's Lagoon |publisher=Bloomsbury |isbn=978-1-4088-3622-4}}
+
*{{cite book |last=Ferguson |first=John |title=Aristotle |url=https://archive.org/details/aristotle0000ferg |url-access=registration |publisher=Twayne Publishers |date=1972 }}
   −
* {{cite web |last1=Leroi |first1=Armand Marie (Presenter) |author-link=Armand Marie Leroi |title=Aristotle's Lagoon: Embryo Inside a Chicken's Egg |date=3 May 2011 |url=http://www.bbc.co.uk/programmes/p00gqlyy |publisher=BBC |access-date=17 November 2016}}
+
* De Groot, Jean (2014). ''Aristotle's Empiricism: Experience and Mechanics in the 4th century BC'', Parmenides Publishing,{{ISBN | 978-1930972834}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Lindberg |first=David |title=The Beginnings of Western Science |url=https://archive.org/details/beginningsofwest00lind | url-access=registration |date=1992 |publisher=University of Chicago Press |isbn=978-0-226-48205-7}}
+
* Frede, Michael (1987). ''Essays in Ancient Philosophy''. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
   −
* {{cite book |last=Lloyd |first=G. E. R. |title=The critic of Plato |date=1968 |author-link=G. E. R. Lloyd |work=Aristotle: The Growth and Structure of His Thought |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0-521-09456-6}}
+
*{{cite book |last=Fuller |first=B.A.G. |author-link=Benjamin_Apthorp_Gould_Fuller |series=History of Greek Philosophy |volume=3 |title=Aristotle |publisher=Cape |date=1923}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Lloyd |first=G. E. R. |title=Causes and correlations |date=1996 | author-link=G. E. R. Lloyd |work=Adversaries and Authorities: Investigations into ancient Greek and Chinese science |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0-521-55695-8}}
+
* [[Eugene Gendlin|Gendlin, Eugene T.]] (2012). ''[http://www.focusing.org/aristotle/ Line by Line Commentary on Aristotle's De Anima] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170327012857/http://www.focusing.org/aristotle/ |date=27 March 2017 }}'', Volume 1: Books I & II; Volume 2: Book III. The Focusing Institute.
   −
* {{cite book |last=Lovejoy |first=Arthur O. |title=The Great Chain of Being: A Study of the History of an Idea |date=31 January 1976 |author-link=Arthur O. Lovejoy |publisher=Harvard University Press |isbn=978-0-674-36153-9}}
+
* Gill, Mary Louise (1989). ''Aristotle on Substance: The Paradox of Unity''. Princeton University Press.
   −
* {{cite web |title=Lucas Cranach the Elder{{!}} Phyllis and Aristotle | url=http://www.sothebys.com/en/auctions/ecatalogue/2008/important-old-master-paintings-including-european-works-of-art-n08404/lot.78.html | publisher=[[Sotheby's]] | access-date=23 March 2018 | date=2008 | ref=CITEREFLucas Cranach the Elder}}
+
*{{Cite book |last=Guthrie |first=W.K.C. |title=A History of Greek Philosophy |volume=6 |publisher=[[Cambridge University Press]] |date=1981}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Lyell |first=Charles |title=Principles of Geology |date=1832 |author-link=Charles Lyell |url=https://archive.org/details/principlesgeolo01unkngoog |oclc=609586345|publisher=J. Murray, 1832}}
+
* Halper, Edward C. (2009). ''One and Many in Aristotle's Metaphysics, Volume 1: Books Alpha – Delta'', Parmenides Publishing,{{ISBN | 978-1930972216}}.
   −
* {{cite journal |last=MacDougall-Shackleton |first=Scott A. |title=The levels of analysis revisited |date=27 July 2011 |pages=2076–85 |journal=Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences |volume=366 |issue=1574 |doi=10.1098/rstb.2010.0363 |pmc=3130367 |pmid=21690126}}
+
* Halper, Edward C. (2005). ''One and Many in Aristotle's Metaphysics, Volume 2: The Central Books'', Parmenides Publishing,{{ISBN | 978-1930972056}}.
   −
* {{cite SEP |last=Machamer |first=Peter |title=Galileo Galilei |date=2017 | url-id=galileo}}
+
* [[Terence Irwin|Irwin, Terence H.]] (1988). [http://www.cyjack.com/cognition/Aristotle%27s%20first%20principles.pdf ''Aristotle's First Principles'']. Oxford: Clarendon Press,{{ISBN | 0198242905}}.
   −
* {{cite book |last=Magee |first=Bryan |title=The Story of Philosophy |date=2010 |author-link=Bryan Magee |publisher=Dorling Kindersley |isbn=978-0-241-24126-4}}
+
*{{cite book |last=Jaeger |first=Werner |title=Aristotle: Fundamentals of the History of His Development | editor-first=Richard | editor-last=Robinson |edition=2nd |publisher=Clarendon Press |date=1948}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Mason |first=Stephen F. |title=A History of the Sciences |date=1979 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=PLlMAAAAMAAJ |publisher=Collier Books |isbn=978-0-02-093400-4 |oclc=924760574}}
+
* [[Alberto Jori|Jori, Alberto]] (2003). ''Aristotele'', Bruno Mondadori (Prize 2003 of the "[[International Academy of the History of Science]]"){{ISBN | 978-8842497370}}.
   −
* {{cite web |last1=Mayhew |first1=Robert |title=Aristotle For Objectivists |url=https://estore.aynrand.org/p/692/aristotle-for-objectivists-mp3-download |publisher=The Ayn Rand Institute |access-date=29 March 2018}}
+
*{{cite book | editor-last=Kiernan | editor-first=Thomas P. |title=Aristotle Dictionary |publisher=Philosophical Library |date=1962}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Mayr |first=Ernst |author-link=Ernst Mayr |title=The Growth of Biological Thought |url=https://archive.org/details/growthofbiologic00mayr | url-access=registration |date=1982 |publisher=Belknap Press |isbn=978-0-674-36446-2}}
+
* Knight, Kelvin (2007). ''Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics and Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre'', Polity Press.
   −
* {{cite book |last=Mayr |first=Ernst |author-link=Ernst Mayr |title=The Growth of Biological Thought |date=1985 |publisher=Harvard University Press |isbn=978-0-674-36446-2}}
+
* Lewis, Frank A. (1991). ''Substance and Predication in Aristotle''. Cambridge University Press.
   −
* {{cite book |last=McLeisch |first=Kenneth Cole |title=Aristotle: The Great Philosophers |date=1999 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-0-415-92392-7|url=https://archive.org/details/aristotle00mcle}}
+
* Lord, Carnes (1984). ''Introduction to ''The Politics'', by Aristotle''. Chicago University Press.
   −
* {{cite book |title=Aristotle to Zoos: a philosophical dictionary of biology |year=1984 |last1=Medawar |first1=Peter B. |author-link=Peter Medawar |last2=Medawar |first2=J. S. |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-283043-2}}
+
* Loux, Michael J. (1991). Primary Ousia: An Essay on Aristotle's Metaphysics Ζ and Η. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
   −
* {{cite journal |last1=Miller |first1=Willard M. |title=Aristotle on Necessity, Chance, and Spontaneity |year=1973 |pages=204–13 |journal=New Scholasticism |volume=47 |issue=2 |doi=10.5840/newscholas197347237}}
+
* Maso, Stefano (Ed.), Natali, Carlo (Ed.), Seel, Gerhard (Ed.) (2012) ''Reading Aristotle: Physics'' VII. 3: ''What is Alteration?'' ''Proceedings of the International ESAP-HYELE Conference'', Parmenides Publishing.{{ISBN | 978-1930972735}}
   −
* {{cite journal |last1=Modrak |first1=Deborah |title=Dreams and Method in Aristotle |date=2009 |pages=169–81 |journal=Skepsis: A Journal for Philosophy and Interdisciplinary Research |volume=20}}
+
*{{cite book |last=McKeon |first=Richard |title=Introduction to Aristotle |edition=2nd |publisher=University of Chicago Press |date=1973}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Moore |first=Ruth |title=The Earth We Live On |url=https://archive.org/details/earthweliveonsto00moor | url-access=registration |year=1956 |publisher=Alfred A. Knopf |oclc=1024467091}}
+
*{{cite journal |last=Owen |first=G. E. L. |year=1965c |title=The Platonism of Aristotle |journal=Proceedings of the British Academy |volume=50 |pages=125–50}} [Reprinted in J. Barnes, M. Schofield, and R.R.K. Sorabji, eds.(1975). ''Articles on Aristotle'' Vol 1. Science. London: Duckworth 14–34.]
   −
* {{cite journal |last=Morsink |first=Johannes |title=Was Aristotle's Biology Sexist? |date=Spring 1979 |pages=83–112 |jstor=4330727 |journal=Journal of the History of Biology |volume=12 |issue=1 |doi=10.1007/bf00128136 |pmid=11615776 |s2cid=6090923}}
+
* {{cite book |doi=10.1017/CBO9780511498282 |title=Aristotle and the Philosophy of Friendship |year=2002 |last1=Pangle |first1=Lorraine Smith |isbn=9780511498282}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Nasr |first=Seyyed Hossein |title=The Islamic Intellectual Tradition in Persia |date=1996 |publisher=Curzon Press |isbn=978-0-7007-0314-2}}
+
*{{cite book |last=Plato |author-link=Plato |title=The Worlds of Plato and Aristotle | editor1-first=Harold Joseph | editor1-last=Allen | editor2-first=James B | editor2-last=Wilbur |publisher=Prometheus Books |date=1979}}
   −
* {{cite web |last1=Phelan |first1=Joseph |title=The Philosopher as Hero: Raphael's The School of Athens |date=September 2002 |url=http://www.artcyclopedia.com/feature-2002-09.html |publisher=ArtCyclopedia |access-date=23 March 2018}}
+
* Reeve, C. D. C. (2000). ''Substantial Knowledge: Aristotle's Metaphysics''. Hackett.
   −
* {{cite web |url=https://www.louvre.fr/en/oeuvre-notices/phyllis-and-aristotle |title=Phyllis and Aristotle |date=1 February 2019 |via=Musee du Louvre |ref=CITEREFPhyllis and Aristotle}}
+
*{{Cite book |last=Rose |first=Lynn E. |title=Aristotle's Syllogistic |publisher=Charles C Thomas |date=1968}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Pickover |first=Clifford A. |title=The Math Book: From Pythagoras to the 57th Dimension, 250 Milestones in the History of Mathematics |year=2009 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=JrslMKTgSZwC&pg=PA52 |publisher=Sterling |isbn=978-1-4027-5796-9}}
+
*{{Cite book |last=Ross |first=Sir David |author-link=W. D. Ross |title=Aristotle |publisher=Routledge |edition=6th |date=1995}}
   −
* {{cite web |url=http://penelope.uchicago.edu/Thayer/e/roman/texts/plutarch/lives/alexander*/3.html |title=Plutarch &ndash; Life of Alexander (Part 1 of 7) |date=1919 |publisher=Loeb Classical Library |website=penelope.uchicago.edu |access-date=31 January 2019 |ref=CITEREFPlutarch1919}}
+
* Scaltsas, T. (1994). ''Substances and Universals in Aristotle's Metaphysics''. Cornell University Press.
   −
* {{cite web |title=Predicate Logic |url=https://www.cs.utexas.edu/~schrum2/cs301k/lec/topic04-predicateLogic.pdf |publisher=University of Texas |access-date=29 March 2018 |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20180329221535/https://www.cs.utexas.edu/~schrum2/cs301k/lec/topic04-predicateLogic.pdf |archivedate=29 March 2018 | url-status=live |ref=CITEREFPredicate Logic}}
+
* Strauss, Leo (1964). "On Aristotle's ''Politics''", in ''The City and Man'', Rand McNally.
   −
* {{cite book |last=Rhodes |first=Frank Harold Trevor |title=Evolution |date=1974 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=EWGt0bff8agC |publisher=Golden Press |isbn=978-0-307-64360-5}}
+
*{{Cite book |last=Swanson |first=Judith |title=The Public and the Private in Aristotle's Political Philosophy |url=https://archive.org/details/publicprivateina00swan |url-access=registration |publisher=Cornell University Press |date=1992 }}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Robbins |first=Lionel |title=A History of Economic Thought: The LSE Lectures |date=2000 |editor1=Medema, Steven G. |editor2=Samuels, Warren J. |publisher=Princeton University Press}}
+
*{{Cite book |last=Veatch |first=Henry B. |author-link=Henry Babcock Veatch |title=Aristotle: A Contemporary Appreciation |publisher=Indiana University Press |date=1974}}
   −
* {{cite book |last1=Rorty |first1=Amélie Oksenberg |chapter=Structuring Rhetoric |date=1996 |title=Essays on Aristotle's ''Rhetoric'' | editor-last=Rorty | editor-first=Amélie Oksenberg |publisher=University of California Press |isbn=978-0-520-20227-6 | chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=vd7fEb1wOmYC&q=Aristotle+deliberative+forensic+and+epideictic&pg=PA6| url-access=registration |url=https://archive.org/details/essaysonaristotl0000unse}}
+
*{{cite book |last=Woods |first=M. J. |year=1991b |chapter=Universals and Particular Forms in Aristotle's Metaphysics |series=[[Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy]] |title=Aristotle and the Later Tradition |volume=Suppl |pages=41–56}}
   −
* {{cite journal |last1=Rovelli |first1=Carlo |author-link=Carlo Rovelli |title=Aristotle's Physics: A Physicist's Look |year=2015 |pages=23–40 |journal=Journal of the American Philosophical Association |volume=1 |issue=1 |doi=10.1017/apa.2014.11 |arxiv=1312.4057 |s2cid=44193681}}
+
{{refend}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Russell |first=Bertrand |title=A history of western philosophy |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=RZc3AAAAIAAJ |year=1972 |publisher=Simon and Schuster |isbn=978-0-671-31400-2}}
     −
* {{cite book |last=Sedley |first=David |title=Creationism and Its Critics in Antiquity |year=2007 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=SgRuJEfzUG8C |publisher=University of California Press |isbn=978-0-520-25364-3}}
     −
* {{cite book |last=Shields |first=Christopher |title=The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=vTVsrl0mnH4C |date=2012 |publisher=OUP USA |isbn=978-0-19-518748-9}}
+
==External links==
   −
* {{cite SEP |last=Shields |first=Christopher |title=Aristotle's Psychology |date=2016 |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/aristotle/ |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University | editor-last=Zalta | editor-first=Edward N. |edition=Winter 2016}}
+
{{Sister project links | b=no | n=no | s=Author:Aristotle}}
   −
* {{cite book |last1=Shute |first1=Clarence |title=The Psychology of Aristotle: An Analysis of the Living Being |date=1941 |publisher=Columbia University Press |oclc=936606202}}
+
{{Library resources box | by=yes | onlinebooks=yes | others=yes | about=yes | label=Aristotle
   −
* {{cite book |last=Sikka |first=Sonya |title=Forms of Transcendence: Heidegger and Medieval Mystical Theology |year=1997 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=UNYIDrA0zrYC&pg=PA265 |publisher=SUNY Press |isbn=978-0-7914-3345-4}}
+
{{图书馆资源框 | by = yes | online books = yes | others = yes | about = yes | label = Aristotle
   −
* {{cite SEP |last=Smith |first=Robin |title=Aristotle's Logic |date=2017 | url-id=aristotle-logic}}
+
{{Wikisourcelang | el | Αριστοτέλης | Ἀριστοτέλης}}
   −
* {{cite book |url=http://archive.org/details/dictionarygreek09smitgoog |title=Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology |last=Smith |first=William George | orig-year=1869 |year=2007 |publisher=J. Walton |access-date=30 January 2019 |via=Internet Archive}}
+
  | viaf= | lccn= | lcheading= | wikititle= }}
   −
* {{cite book |last1=Sorabji |first1=R. |title=Aristotle on Memory |date=2006 |publisher=University of Chicago Press |location=Chicago |page=54 |edition=2nd |quote=And this is exactly why we hunt for the successor, starting in our thoughts from the present or from something else, and from something similar, or opposite, or neighbouring. By this means recollection occurs...}}
+
2012年10月12日,星期五,星期五,星期五,星期五,星期五,星期五,星期五,星期五,星期五,星期六,星期五,星期六,星期五,星期六,星期六,星期五,星期六,星期六,星期六,星期六,
   −
* {{cite book |last=Sorabji |first=Richard |title=Aristotle Transformed |date=1990 |author-link=Richard Sorabji |publisher=Duckworth |isbn=978-0-7156-2254-4}}
+
{{Library resources box | by=yes | onlinebooks=yes | others=yes | about=yes | label=Aristotle
   −
* {{cite journal |last1=Staley |first1=Kevin |title=Al-Kindi on Creation: Aristotle's Challenge to Islam |journal=Journal of the History of Ideas |date=1989 |volume=50 |issue=3 |pages=355–370 |jstor=2709566|doi=10.2307/2709566}}
+
  | viaf= | lccn= | lcheading= | wikititle= }}
   −
* {{cite web |last1=Susskind |first1=Leonard |title=Classical Mechanics, Lectures 2, 3 |date=3 October 2011 |authorlink1=Leonard Susskind |url=http://theoreticalminimum.com/courses/classical-mechanics/2011/fall/lecture-2 |website=The Theoretical Minimum |access-date=11 May 2018}}
+
*{{Britannica |id=34560}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Taylor |first=Henry Osborn |chapter=Chapter 3: Aristotle's Biology |title=Greek Biology and Medicine |date=1922 |author-link=Henry Osborn Taylor |archivedate=27 March 2006 | chapter-url=http://www.ancientlibrary.com/medicine/0051.html |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20060327222953/http://www.ancientlibrary.com/medicine/0051.html | url-status=dead |access-date=3 January 2017}}
+
*{{PhilPapers|category|aristotle}}
   −
* {{cite web |title=The School of Athens by Raphael |url=http://www.visual-arts-cork.com/famous-paintings/school-of-athens.htm |publisher=Visual Arts Cork |access-date=22 March 2018 |ref=CITEREFSchool of Athens}}
+
*{{InPho | thinker | 2553}}
   −
* {{cite web |last=Stewart |first=Jessica |title=The Story Behind Raphael's Masterpiece 'The School of Athens' |url=https://mymodernmet.com/school-of-athens-raphael/ |quote=Plato's gesture toward the sky is thought to indicate his Theory of Forms. ... Conversely, Aristotle's hand is a visual representation of his belief that knowledge comes from experience. Empiricism, as it is known, theorizes that humans must have concrete evidence to support their ideas |website=My Modern Met |year=2019 |access-date=29 March 2019}}
+
* At the [[Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]:
   −
* {{cite book |last=Thompson |first=D'Arcy |author-link=D'Arcy Wentworth Thompson |title=Historia animalium |date=1910 |work=The works of Aristotle translated into English |editor1=Ross, W. D. |editor2=Smith, J. A. |publisher=Clarendon Press |url=https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/history/index.html |oclc=39273217}}
+
*:{{hlist | [https://www.iep.utm.edu/aristotl/ Aristotle (general article)] | [https://www.iep.utm.edu/aris-bio/ Biology] | [https://www.iep.utm.edu/aris-eth/ Ethics] | [https://www.iep.utm.edu/aris-log/ Logic] | [https://www.iep.utm.edu/aris-met/ Metaphysics] | [https://www.iep.utm.edu/aris-mot/ Motion and its Place in Nature] | [https://www.iep.utm.edu/aris-poe/ Poetics] | [https://www.iep.utm.edu/aris-pol/ Politics]}}
   −
* {{cite book |last=Warren |first=Howard C. |title=A History of the Association of Psychology |date=1921 |author-link=Howard C. Warren |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=D4IXAAAAYAAJ&q=The+history+of+the+association+of+psychology&pg=PA3 |oclc=21010604 <!--dlc-->}}
+
* At the [http://classics.mit.edu/Browse/index.html Internet Classics Archive]
   −
* {{cite book |last1=Webb |first1=Wilse |title=Dreamtime and dreamwork: Decoding the language of the night |date=1990 |publisher=Jeremy P. Tarcher |isbn=978-0-87477-594-5|url=https://archive.org/details/dreamtimedreamwo00kriprich}}
+
* From the [[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]:
   −
* {{cite news |title=When libraries were on a roll |date=19 May 2001 |url=https://www.telegraph.co.uk/culture/4723624/When-libraries-were-on-a-roll.html |publisher=Telegraph Media Group |access-date=29 June 2017 |ref=CITEREFWhen libraries were2001}}
+
*:{{hlist | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle Aristotle (general article)] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotelianism-renaissance/ Aristotle in the Renaissance] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-biology/ Biology] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-causality/ Causality] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-commentators/ Commentators on Aristotle] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-ethics/ Ethics] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-logic/ Logic] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-mathematics/ Mathematics] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-metaphysics/ Metaphysics] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-natphil/ Natural philosophy] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-noncontradiction/ Non-contradiction] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-politics/ Political theory] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-psychology/ Psychology] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-rhetoric/ Rhetoric]}}
   −
* {{cite SEP |last=Wildberg | first Christian |title=John Philoponus |date=2016 | url-id=philoponus}}
+
*{{cite CE1913 | first=William | last=Turner | wstitle=Aristotle | volume=1 | short=x}}
   −
* {{cite SEP |title=Aristotle's Influence |date=2018 | url-id=aristotle-influence |edition=Spring 2018 |ref=CITEREFAristotle's Influence2018}}
+
*{{cite LotEP |chapter=Aristotle}}
   −
{{refend}}
+
Collections of works
    +
收藏作品
      −
The secondary literature on Aristotle is vast. The following is only a small selection.
     −
关于亚里士多德的二手文献很多。以下只是一小部分选择。
+
;Collections of works
   −
==Further reading==
+
* At [http://classics.mit.edu/Browse/index-Aristotle.html Massachusetts Institute of Technology]
   −
The secondary literature on Aristotle is vast. The following is only a small selection.
+
*{{Gutenberg author | id=2747}}
   −
{{refbegin | 30em}}
+
*{{Internet Archive author}}
   −
* [[J. L. Ackrill|Ackrill, J. L.]] (1997). ''Essays on Plato and Aristotle'', Oxford University Press.
+
*{{Librivox author | id=602}}
   −
*{{cite book |last=Ackrill |first=J.L. |title=Aristotle the Philosopher |publisher=Oxford University Press |date=1981}}
+
*{{OL author | OL22105A}}
   −
*{{Cite book |last=Adler |first=Mortimer J. |author-link=Mortimer Adler |title=Aristotle for Everybody |publisher=Macmillan |date=1978 | title-link=Aristotle for Everybody}}
+
*{{in lang|en|el}} [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/perscoll?.submit=Change&collection=Any&type=text&lang=Any&lookup=Aristotle Perseus Project] at [[Tufts University]]
   −
*{{cite book |last=Ammonius | editor1-last=Cohen | editor1-first=S. Marc | editor2-last=Matthews | editor2-first=Gareth B |title=On Aristotle's Categories |publisher=Cornell University Press |date=1991 |isbn=978-0-8014-2688-9}}
+
* At the [https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/ University of Adelaide]
   −
*{{cite book |last=Aristotle |title=The Works of Aristotle Translated into English Under the Editorship of W.D. Ross, 12 vols |publisher=[[Clarendon Press]] |date=1908–1952}} These translations are available in several places online; see External links.
+
*{{in lang|el|fr}} [http://remacle.org/bloodwolf/philosophes/Aristote/table.htm P. Remacle]
   −
* Bakalis, Nikolaos. (2005). ''Handbook of Greek Philosophy: From Thales to the Stoics Analysis and Fragments'', Trafford Publishing{{ISBN | 978-1412048439}}
+
* The 11-volume 1837 Bekker edition of ''Aristotle's Works'' in Greek ([http://isnature.org/Files/Aristotle/ PDF]{{dot}}[https://web.archive.org/web/20050816192647/http://grid.ceth.rutgers.edu/ancient/greek/aristotle_greek/ DJVU])
   −
*{{Cite book |last=Bocheński |first=I. M. |title=Ancient Formal Logic |publisher=North-Holland |date=1951}}
+
{{Navboxes|list=
   −
* Bolotin, David (1998). ''An Approach to Aristotle's Physics: With Particular Attention to the Role of His Manner of Writing.'' Albany: SUNY Press. A contribution to our understanding of how to read Aristotle's scientific works.
+
{导航框 | 列表 =
   −
* [[Myles Burnyeat|Burnyeat, Myles F.]] ''et al.'' (1979). ''Notes on Book Zeta of Aristotle's Metaphysics''. Oxford: Sub-faculty of Philosophy.
     −
*{{cite book | editor1-last=Cantor | editor1-first=Norman F. | editor2-first=Peter L. | editor2-last=Klein |title=Ancient Thought: Plato and Aristotle |volume=1 |series=Monuments of Western Thought |publisher=Blaisdell |date=1969}}
     −
*{{cite journal |last1=Chappell |first1=V. |year=1973 |title=Aristotle's Conception of Matter |url= |journal=Journal of Philosophy |volume=70 |issue=19 |pages=679–96 |doi=10.2307/2025076 |jstor=2025076}}
+
{{Navboxes|list=
   −
* Code, Alan (1995). Potentiality in Aristotle's Science and Metaphysics, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 76.
+
{{Peripatetics}}
   −
*{{cite book |last=Ferguson |first=John |title=Aristotle |url=https://archive.org/details/aristotle0000ferg |url-access=registration |publisher=Twayne Publishers |date=1972 }}
+
{{Metaphysics}}
   −
* De Groot, Jean (2014). ''Aristotle's Empiricism: Experience and Mechanics in the 4th century BC'', Parmenides Publishing,{{ISBN | 978-1930972834}}
+
{{Ethics}}
   −
* Frede, Michael (1987). ''Essays in Ancient Philosophy''. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
+
{{Natural history}}
   −
*{{cite book |last=Fuller |first=B.A.G. |author-link=Benjamin_Apthorp_Gould_Fuller |series=History of Greek Philosophy |volume=3 |title=Aristotle |publisher=Cape |date=1923}}
+
{{History of biology}}
   −
* [[Eugene Gendlin|Gendlin, Eugene T.]] (2012). ''[http://www.focusing.org/aristotle/ Line by Line Commentary on Aristotle's De Anima] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170327012857/http://www.focusing.org/aristotle/ |date=27 March 2017 }}'', Volume 1: Books I & II; Volume 2: Book III. The Focusing Institute.
+
{{Philosophy of science}}
   −
* Gill, Mary Louise (1989). ''Aristotle on Substance: The Paradox of Unity''. Princeton University Press.
+
{{Philosophy of language}}
   −
*{{Cite book |last=Guthrie |first=W.K.C. |title=A History of Greek Philosophy |volume=6 |publisher=[[Cambridge University Press]] |date=1981}}
+
{{Jurisprudence}}
   −
* Halper, Edward C. (2009). ''One and Many in Aristotle's Metaphysics, Volume 1: Books Alpha – Delta'', Parmenides Publishing,{{ISBN | 978-1930972216}}.
+
{{Social and political philosophy}}
   −
* Halper, Edward C. (2005). ''One and Many in Aristotle's Metaphysics, Volume 2: The Central Books'', Parmenides Publishing,{{ISBN | 978-1930972056}}.
+
}}
   −
* [[Terence Irwin|Irwin, Terence H.]] (1988). [http://www.cyjack.com/cognition/Aristotle%27s%20first%20principles.pdf ''Aristotle's First Principles'']. Oxford: Clarendon Press,{{ISBN | 0198242905}}.
+
}}
   −
*{{cite book |last=Jaeger |first=Werner |title=Aristotle: Fundamentals of the History of His Development | editor-first=Richard | editor-last=Robinson |edition=2nd |publisher=Clarendon Press |date=1948}}
+
{{Ancient Greece topics}}
   −
* [[Alberto Jori|Jori, Alberto]] (2003). ''Aristotele'', Bruno Mondadori (Prize 2003 of the "[[International Academy of the History of Science]]"){{ISBN | 978-8842497370}}.
+
}}
   −
*{{cite book | editor-last=Kiernan | editor-first=Thomas P. |title=Aristotle Dictionary |publisher=Philosophical Library |date=1962}}
+
{{Aristotelianism}}
   −
* Knight, Kelvin (2007). ''Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics and Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre'', Polity Press.
+
{{Authority control}}
 
  −
* Lewis, Frank A. (1991). ''Substance and Predication in Aristotle''. Cambridge University Press.
  −
 
  −
* Lord, Carnes (1984). ''Introduction to ''The Politics'', by Aristotle''. Chicago University Press.
  −
 
  −
* Loux, Michael J. (1991). Primary Ousia: An Essay on Aristotle's Metaphysics Ζ and Η. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  −
 
  −
* Maso, Stefano (Ed.), Natali, Carlo (Ed.), Seel, Gerhard (Ed.) (2012) ''Reading Aristotle: Physics'' VII. 3: ''What is Alteration?'' ''Proceedings of the International ESAP-HYELE Conference'', Parmenides Publishing.{{ISBN | 978-1930972735}}
  −
 
  −
*{{cite book |last=McKeon |first=Richard |title=Introduction to Aristotle |edition=2nd |publisher=University of Chicago Press |date=1973}}
  −
 
  −
*{{cite journal |last=Owen |first=G. E. L. |year=1965c |title=The Platonism of Aristotle |journal=Proceedings of the British Academy |volume=50 |pages=125–50}} [Reprinted in J. Barnes, M. Schofield, and R.R.K. Sorabji, eds.(1975). ''Articles on Aristotle'' Vol 1. Science. London: Duckworth 14–34.]
  −
 
  −
* {{cite book |doi=10.1017/CBO9780511498282 |title=Aristotle and the Philosophy of Friendship |year=2002 |last1=Pangle |first1=Lorraine Smith |isbn=9780511498282}}
  −
 
  −
*{{cite book |last=Plato |author-link=Plato |title=The Worlds of Plato and Aristotle | editor1-first=Harold Joseph | editor1-last=Allen | editor2-first=James B | editor2-last=Wilbur |publisher=Prometheus Books |date=1979}}
  −
 
  −
* Reeve, C. D. C. (2000). ''Substantial Knowledge: Aristotle's Metaphysics''. Hackett.
  −
 
  −
*{{Cite book |last=Rose |first=Lynn E. |title=Aristotle's Syllogistic |publisher=Charles C Thomas |date=1968}}
  −
 
  −
*{{Cite book |last=Ross |first=Sir David |author-link=W. D. Ross |title=Aristotle |publisher=Routledge |edition=6th |date=1995}}
  −
 
  −
* Scaltsas, T. (1994). ''Substances and Universals in Aristotle's Metaphysics''. Cornell University Press.
  −
 
  −
* Strauss, Leo (1964). "On Aristotle's ''Politics''", in ''The City and Man'', Rand McNally.
  −
 
  −
*{{Cite book |last=Swanson |first=Judith |title=The Public and the Private in Aristotle's Political Philosophy |url=https://archive.org/details/publicprivateina00swan |url-access=registration |publisher=Cornell University Press |date=1992 }}
  −
 
  −
*{{Cite book |last=Veatch |first=Henry B. |author-link=Henry Babcock Veatch |title=Aristotle: A Contemporary Appreciation |publisher=Indiana University Press |date=1974}}
  −
 
  −
*{{cite book |last=Woods |first=M. J. |year=1991b |chapter=Universals and Particular Forms in Aristotle's Metaphysics |series=[[Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy]] |title=Aristotle and the Later Tradition |volume=Suppl |pages=41–56}}
  −
 
  −
{{refend}}
  −
 
  −
 
  −
 
  −
==External links==
  −
 
  −
{{Sister project links | b=no | n=no | s=Author:Aristotle}}
  −
 
  −
{{Library resources box | by=yes | onlinebooks=yes | others=yes | about=yes | label=Aristotle
  −
 
  −
{{图书馆资源框 | by = yes | online books = yes | others = yes | about = yes | label = Aristotle
  −
 
  −
{{Wikisourcelang | el | Αριστοτέλης | Ἀριστοτέλης}}
  −
 
  −
  | viaf= | lccn= | lcheading= | wikititle= }}
  −
 
  −
2012年10月12日,星期五,星期五,星期五,星期五,星期五,星期五,星期五,星期五,星期五,星期六,星期五,星期六,星期五,星期六,星期六,星期五,星期六,星期六,星期六,星期六,
  −
 
  −
{{Library resources box | by=yes | onlinebooks=yes | others=yes | about=yes | label=Aristotle
  −
 
  −
  | viaf= | lccn= | lcheading= | wikititle= }}
  −
 
  −
*{{Britannica |id=34560}}
  −
 
  −
*{{PhilPapers|category|aristotle}}
  −
 
  −
*{{InPho | thinker | 2553}}
  −
 
  −
* At the [[Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]:
  −
 
  −
*:{{hlist | [https://www.iep.utm.edu/aristotl/ Aristotle (general article)] | [https://www.iep.utm.edu/aris-bio/ Biology] | [https://www.iep.utm.edu/aris-eth/ Ethics] | [https://www.iep.utm.edu/aris-log/ Logic] | [https://www.iep.utm.edu/aris-met/ Metaphysics] | [https://www.iep.utm.edu/aris-mot/ Motion and its Place in Nature] | [https://www.iep.utm.edu/aris-poe/ Poetics] | [https://www.iep.utm.edu/aris-pol/ Politics]}}
  −
 
  −
* At the [http://classics.mit.edu/Browse/index.html Internet Classics Archive]
  −
 
  −
* From the [[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]:
  −
 
  −
*:{{hlist | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle Aristotle (general article)] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotelianism-renaissance/ Aristotle in the Renaissance] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-biology/ Biology] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-causality/ Causality] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-commentators/ Commentators on Aristotle] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-ethics/ Ethics] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-logic/ Logic] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-mathematics/ Mathematics] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-metaphysics/ Metaphysics] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-natphil/ Natural philosophy] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-noncontradiction/ Non-contradiction] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-politics/ Political theory] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-psychology/ Psychology] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-rhetoric/ Rhetoric]}}
  −
 
  −
*{{cite CE1913 | first=William | last=Turner | wstitle=Aristotle | volume=1 | short=x}}
  −
 
  −
*{{cite LotEP |chapter=Aristotle}}
  −
 
  −
Collections of works
  −
 
  −
收藏作品
  −
 
  −
 
  −
 
  −
;Collections of works
  −
 
  −
* At [http://classics.mit.edu/Browse/index-Aristotle.html Massachusetts Institute of Technology]
  −
 
  −
*{{Gutenberg author | id=2747}}
  −
 
  −
*{{Internet Archive author}}
  −
 
  −
*{{Librivox author | id=602}}
  −
 
  −
*{{OL author | OL22105A}}
  −
 
  −
*{{in lang|en|el}} [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/perscoll?.submit=Change&collection=Any&type=text&lang=Any&lookup=Aristotle Perseus Project] at [[Tufts University]]
  −
 
  −
* At the [https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/ University of Adelaide]
  −
 
  −
*{{in lang|el|fr}} [http://remacle.org/bloodwolf/philosophes/Aristote/table.htm P. Remacle]
  −
 
  −
* The 11-volume 1837 Bekker edition of ''Aristotle's Works'' in Greek ([http://isnature.org/Files/Aristotle/ PDF]{{dot}}[https://web.archive.org/web/20050816192647/http://grid.ceth.rutgers.edu/ancient/greek/aristotle_greek/ DJVU])
  −
 
  −
{{Navboxes|list=
  −
 
  −
{导航框 | 列表 =
  −
 
  −
 
  −
 
  −
{{Navboxes|list=
  −
 
  −
{{Peripatetics}}
  −
 
  −
{{Metaphysics}}
  −
 
  −
{{Ethics}}
  −
 
  −
{{Natural history}}
  −
 
  −
{{History of biology}}
  −
 
  −
{{Philosophy of science}}
  −
 
  −
{{Philosophy of language}}
  −
 
  −
{{Jurisprudence}}
  −
 
  −
{{Social and political philosophy}}
  −
 
  −
}}
  −
 
  −
}}
  −
 
  −
{{Ancient Greece topics}}
  −
 
  −
}}
  −
 
  −
{{Aristotelianism}}
  −
 
  −
{{Authority control}}
  −
 
  −
 
  −
 
  −
*
  −
 
  −
*
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Aristotle| ]]
  −
 
  −
Category:384 BC births
  −
 
  −
类别: 公元前384年出生
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Aristotelianism|*]]
  −
 
  −
Category:322 BC deaths
  −
 
  −
类别: 公元前322年死亡
  −
 
  −
[[Category:384 BC births]]
  −
 
  −
Category:4th-century BC philosophers
  −
 
  −
范畴: 公元前4世纪的哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:322 BC deaths]]
  −
 
  −
Category:4th-century BC writers
  −
 
  −
类别: 公元前4世纪的作家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:4th-century BC philosophers]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Academic philosophers
  −
 
  −
范畴: 学术哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:4th-century BC writers]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Acting theorists
  −
 
  −
范畴: 代理理论家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Academic philosophers]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Ancient Greek biologists
  −
 
  −
类别: 古希腊生物学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Acting theorists]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Ancient Greek economists
  −
 
  −
类别: 古希腊经济学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Ancient Greek biologists]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Ancient Greek epistemologists
  −
 
  −
类: 古希腊认识论学者
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Ancient Greek economists]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Ancient Greek ethicists
  −
 
  −
类别: 古希腊伦理学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Ancient Greek epistemologists]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Ancient Greek logicians
  −
 
  −
类别: 古希腊逻辑学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Ancient Greek ethicists]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Ancient Greek mathematicians
  −
 
  −
类别: 古希腊数学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Ancient Greek logicians]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Ancient Greek metaphilosophers
  −
 
  −
类别: 古希腊语言哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Ancient Greek mathematicians]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Ancient Greek metaphysicians
  −
 
  −
范畴: 古希腊形而上学者
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Ancient Greek metaphilosophers]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Ancient Greek philosophers
  −
 
  −
范畴: 古希腊哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Ancient Greek metaphysicians]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Ancient Greek philosophers of language
  −
 
  −
范畴: 古希腊语言哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Ancient Greek philosophers]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Ancient Greek philosophers of mind
  −
 
  −
范畴: 古希腊心灵哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Ancient Greek philosophers of language]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Ancient Greek physicists
  −
 
  −
类别: 古希腊物理学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Ancient Greek philosophers of mind]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Ancient Greek political philosophers
  −
 
  −
范畴: 古希腊政治哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Ancient Greek physicists]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Ancient Greeks in Macedon
  −
 
  −
类别: 马其顿的古希腊人
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Ancient Greek political philosophers]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Ancient literary critics
  −
 
  −
类别: 古代文学批评
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Ancient Greeks in Macedon]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Ancient Stagirites
  −
 
  −
类别: 古代舞台人物
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Ancient literary critics]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Aphorists
  −
 
  −
类别: 失语症学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Ancient Stagirites]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Aristotelian philosophers
  −
 
  −
类别: 亚里士多德哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Aphorists]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Attic Greek writers
  −
 
  −
类别: 希腊作家的阁楼
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Aristotelian philosophers]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Cosmologists
  −
 
  −
类别: 宇宙学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Attic Greek writers]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Critical thinking
  −
 
  −
分类: 批判性思维
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Cosmologists]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Cultural critics
  −
 
  −
类别: 文化评论家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Critical thinking]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Epistemologists
  −
 
  −
类别: 认识论专家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Cultural critics]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Ethicists
  −
 
  −
类别: 伦理学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Epistemologists]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Founders of philosophical traditions
  −
 
  −
范畴: 哲学传统的创始人
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Ethicists]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Greek male writers
  −
 
  −
类别: 希腊男性作家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Founders of philosophical traditions]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Greek meteorologists
  −
 
  −
类别: 希腊气象学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Greek male writers]]
  −
 
  −
Category:History of education
  −
 
  −
类别: 教育史
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Greek meteorologists]]
  −
 
  −
Category:History of ideas
  −
 
  −
类别: 思想史
  −
 
  −
[[Category:History of education]]
  −
 
  −
Category:History of logic
  −
 
  −
范畴: 逻辑的历史
  −
 
  −
[[Category:History of ideas]]
  −
 
  −
Category:History of philosophy
  −
 
  −
范畴: 哲学史
  −
 
  −
[[Category:History of logic]]
  −
 
  −
Category:History of science
  −
 
  −
类别: 科学史
  −
 
  −
[[Category:History of philosophy]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Humor researchers
  −
 
  −
分类: 幽默研究者
  −
 
  −
[[Category:History of science]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Irony theorists
  −
 
  −
范畴: 反讽理论家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Humor researchers]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Logicians
  −
 
  −
类别: 逻辑学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Irony theorists]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Metaphilosophers
  −
 
  −
类别: 变音哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Logicians]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Metaphysicians
  −
 
  −
类别: 形而上学者
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Metaphilosophers]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Metic philosophers in Classical Athens
  −
 
  −
范畴: 古典雅典的全神论哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Metaphysicians]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Moral philosophers
  −
 
  −
范畴: 道德哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Metic philosophers in Classical Athens]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Natural philosophers
  −
 
  −
范畴: 自然哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Moral philosophers]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Ontologists
  −
 
  −
范畴: 本体论者
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Natural philosophers]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Peripatetic philosophers
  −
 
  −
范畴: 流浪哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Ontologists]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Philosophers and tutors of Alexander the Great
  −
 
  −
类别: 亚历山大大帝的哲学家和导师
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Peripatetic philosophers]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Philosophers of ancient Chalcidice
  −
 
  −
类别: 古代 Chalcidice 哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Philosophers and tutors of Alexander the Great]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Philosophers of art
  −
 
  −
范畴: 艺术哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Philosophers of ancient Chalcidice]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Philosophers of culture
  −
 
  −
范畴: 文化哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Philosophers of art]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Philosophers of education
  −
 
  −
范畴: 教育哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Philosophers of culture]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Philosophers of ethics and morality
  −
 
  −
范畴: 伦理和道德哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Philosophers of education]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Philosophers of history
  −
 
  −
范畴: 历史哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Philosophers of ethics and morality]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Philosophers of law
  −
 
  −
范畴: 法律哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Philosophers of history]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Philosophers of literature
  −
 
  −
范畴: 文学哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Philosophers of law]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Philosophers of logic
  −
 
  −
范畴: 逻辑哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Philosophers of literature]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Philosophers of love
  −
 
  −
类别: 爱的哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Philosophers of logic]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Philosophers of mind
  −
 
  −
范畴: 心灵哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Philosophers of love]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Philosophers of psychology
  −
 
  −
范畴: 心理学哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Philosophers of mind]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Philosophers of science
  −
 
  −
范畴: 科学哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Philosophers of psychology]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Philosophers of sexuality
  −
 
  −
类别: 性学哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Philosophers of science]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Philosophers of social science
  −
 
  −
范畴: 社会科学哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Philosophers of sexuality]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Philosophers of technology
  −
 
  −
范畴: 技术哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Philosophers of social science]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Philosophical logic
  −
 
  −
范畴: 哲学逻辑
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Philosophers of technology]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Philosophical theists
  −
 
  −
范畴: 哲学有神论者
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Philosophical logic]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Philosophy academics
  −
 
  −
类别: 哲学学者
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Philosophical theists]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Philosophy writers
  −
 
  −
类别: 哲学作家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Philosophy academics]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Political philosophers
  −
 
  −
范畴: 政治哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Philosophy writers]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Rhetoric theorists
  −
 
  −
范畴: 修辞学理论家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Political philosophers]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Social commentators
  −
 
  −
类别: 社会评论员
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Rhetoric theorists]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Social critics
  −
 
  −
类别: 社会批评家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Social commentators]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Social philosophers
  −
 
  −
范畴: 社会哲学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Social critics]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Trope theorists
  −
 
  −
范畴: 修辞学理论家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Social philosophers]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Virtue
  −
 
  −
类别: 美德
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Trope theorists]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Virtue ethicists
  −
 
  −
类别: 美德伦理学家
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Virtue]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Virtue ethics
  −
 
  −
范畴: 美德伦理学
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Virtue ethicists]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Western culture
  −
 
  −
类别: 西方文化
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Virtue ethics]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Western philosophy
  −
 
  −
范畴: 西方哲学
  −
 
  −
[[Category:Western culture]]
  −
 
  −
Category:Zoologists
  −
 
  −
类别: 动物学家
  −
 
  −
<noinclude>
  −
 
  −
<small>This page was moved from [[wikipedia:en:Aristotle]]. Its edit history can be viewed at [[亚里士多德/edithistory]]</small></noinclude>
  −
 
  −
[[Category:待整理页面]]
 
370

个编辑