更改

跳到导航 跳到搜索
添加2,404字节 、 2021年1月23日 (六) 19:58
无编辑摘要
第309行: 第309行:  
Based on AdS/CFT correspondence, Mark Van Raamsdonk suggested that spacetime arises as an emergent phenomenon of the quantum degrees of freedom that are entangled and live in the boundary of the space-time. Induced gravity can emerge from the entanglement first law.
 
Based on AdS/CFT correspondence, Mark Van Raamsdonk suggested that spacetime arises as an emergent phenomenon of the quantum degrees of freedom that are entangled and live in the boundary of the space-time. Induced gravity can emerge from the entanglement first law.
   −
基于 AdS/CFT对偶的理论,Mark Van Raamsdonk 提出时空是作为量子自由度的一种涌现现象而产生的,这种量子自由度是纠缠在一起的,生活在时空的边界上。诱导引力可以产生于纠缠第一定律。
+
基于AdS/CFT对应关系, Mark Van Raamsdonk提出时空是量子自由度的一种涌现现象,量子自由度纠缠在时空的边界上。诱导引力可以从纠缠第一定律中产生。
    
The paradox is that a measurement made on either of the particles apparently collapses the state of the entire entangled system—and does so instantaneously, before any information about the measurement result could have been communicated to the other particle (assuming that information cannot travel [[faster than light]]) and hence assured the "proper" outcome of the measurement of the other part of the entangled pair. In the [[Copenhagen interpretation]], the result of a spin measurement on one of the particles is a collapse into a state in which each particle has a definite spin (either up or down) along the axis of measurement. The outcome is taken to be random, with each possibility having a probability of 50%. However, if both spins are measured along the same axis, they are found to be anti-correlated. This means that the random outcome of the measurement made on one particle seems to have been transmitted to the other, so that it can make the "right choice" when it too is measured.<ref>{{cite book|last1=Rupert W.|first1=Anderson|title=The Cosmic Compendium: Interstellar Travel|date=28 March 2015|publisher=The Cosmic Compendium|isbn=9781329022027|page=100|edition=First|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=JxauCQAAQBAJ&pg=PA100&lpg=PA100&dq=The+outcome+is+taken+to+be+random,+with+each+possibility+having+a+probability+of+50%25.+However,+if+both+spins+are+measured+along+the+same+axis,+they+are+found+to+be+anti-correlated.+This+means+that+the+random+outcome+of+the+measurement+made+on+one+particle+seems+to+have+been+transmitted+to+the+other,+so+that+it+can+make+the+%22right+choice%22+when+it+too+is+measured#v=onepage}}</ref>
 
The paradox is that a measurement made on either of the particles apparently collapses the state of the entire entangled system—and does so instantaneously, before any information about the measurement result could have been communicated to the other particle (assuming that information cannot travel [[faster than light]]) and hence assured the "proper" outcome of the measurement of the other part of the entangled pair. In the [[Copenhagen interpretation]], the result of a spin measurement on one of the particles is a collapse into a state in which each particle has a definite spin (either up or down) along the axis of measurement. The outcome is taken to be random, with each possibility having a probability of 50%. However, if both spins are measured along the same axis, they are found to be anti-correlated. This means that the random outcome of the measurement made on one particle seems to have been transmitted to the other, so that it can make the "right choice" when it too is measured.<ref>{{cite book|last1=Rupert W.|first1=Anderson|title=The Cosmic Compendium: Interstellar Travel|date=28 March 2015|publisher=The Cosmic Compendium|isbn=9781329022027|page=100|edition=First|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=JxauCQAAQBAJ&pg=PA100&lpg=PA100&dq=The+outcome+is+taken+to+be+random,+with+each+possibility+having+a+probability+of+50%25.+However,+if+both+spins+are+measured+along+the+same+axis,+they+are+found+to+be+anti-correlated.+This+means+that+the+random+outcome+of+the+measurement+made+on+one+particle+seems+to+have+been+transmitted+to+the+other,+so+that+it+can+make+the+%22right+choice%22+when+it+too+is+measured#v=onepage}}</ref>
 
+
矛盾之处在于,对任一粒子的测量显然会使整个纠缠系统的状态崩溃,而且会瞬间崩溃,在关于测量结果的任何信息可以被传送到另一个粒子之前(假设信息不能传播[[比光更快]]),从而确保纠缠对的另一部分的测量的“正确”结果。在[[哥本哈根解释]]中,其中一个粒子的自旋测量结果是坍缩成一种状态,在这种状态下,每个粒子沿测量轴都有一个确定的自旋(向上或向下)。结果是随机的,每种可能性的概率为50%。然而,如果两个自旋沿同一轴测量,就会发现它们是反相关的。这意味着,对一个粒子进行测量的随机结果似乎已经传递给了另一个粒子,因此当它也被测量时,它可以做出“正确的选择”。
       
The distance and timing of the measurements can be chosen so as to make the interval between the two measurements [[spacelike]], hence, any causal effect connecting the events would have to travel faster than light. According to the principles of [[special relativity]], it is not possible for any information to travel between two such measuring events. It is not even possible to say which of the measurements came first. For two spacelike separated events {{math|''x''<sub>1</sub>}} and {{math|''x''<sub>2</sub>}} there are [[inertial frame]]s in which {{math|''x''<sub>1</sub>}} is first and others in which {{math|''x''<sub>2</sub>}} is first. Therefore, the correlation between the two measurements cannot be explained as one measurement determining the other: different observers would disagree about the role of cause and effect.
 
The distance and timing of the measurements can be chosen so as to make the interval between the two measurements [[spacelike]], hence, any causal effect connecting the events would have to travel faster than light. According to the principles of [[special relativity]], it is not possible for any information to travel between two such measuring events. It is not even possible to say which of the measurements came first. For two spacelike separated events {{math|''x''<sub>1</sub>}} and {{math|''x''<sub>2</sub>}} there are [[inertial frame]]s in which {{math|''x''<sub>1</sub>}} is first and others in which {{math|''x''<sub>2</sub>}} is first. Therefore, the correlation between the two measurements cannot be explained as one measurement determining the other: different observers would disagree about the role of cause and effect.
 +
可以选择测量的距离和时间,以便使两次测量之间的间隔[[类太空]],因此,任何与事件相关的因果效应都必须比光传播得更快。根据[[狭义相对论]]的原理,任何信息不可能在两个这样的测量事件之间传递。甚至不可能说哪个测量值是第一个。对于两个类空分离事件{{math |''x'<sub>1</sub>}和{math |''x'<sub>2</sub>}存在[[惯性系]],其中{{math |''x'<sub>1</sub>}是第一个,而其他事件中{math |''x'<sub>2</sub>}是第一个。因此,这两种测量之间的相关性不能解释为一种测量决定另一种测量:不同的观察者会对因果关系的作用产生分歧。
    
In the media and popular science, quantum non-locality is often portrayed as being equivalent to entanglement. While this is true for pure bipartite quantum states, in general entanglement is only necessary for non-local correlations, but there exist mixed entangled states that do not produce such correlations. A well-known example is the Werner states that are entangled for certain values of <math>p_{sym}</math>, but can always be described using local hidden variables. Moreover, it was shown that, for arbitrary numbers of parties, there exist states that are genuinely entangled but admit a local model.
 
In the media and popular science, quantum non-locality is often portrayed as being equivalent to entanglement. While this is true for pure bipartite quantum states, in general entanglement is only necessary for non-local correlations, but there exist mixed entangled states that do not produce such correlations. A well-known example is the Werner states that are entangled for certain values of <math>p_{sym}</math>, but can always be described using local hidden variables. Moreover, it was shown that, for arbitrary numbers of parties, there exist states that are genuinely entangled but admit a local model.
   −
在媒体和流行科学中,量子非定域性经常被描述为等价于纠缠。虽然这对于纯二体量子态来说是正确的,但是一般来说纠缠只对于非局域关联是必要的,但是存在混合纠缠态,不产生这样的关联。一个众所周知的例子是 Werner 状态,它纠缠于 < math > p _ { sym } </math > 的某些值,但总是可以使用局部隐变量来描述。此外,研究还表明,对于任意数目的当事人,存在真正纠缠但承认局部模型的状态。
+
在媒体和大众科学中,量子非定域性常常被描述为与纠缠等价。虽然这对于纯二部量子态是正确的,但一般来说纠缠只对非局域关联是必要的,但是存在不产生这种关联的混合纠缠态。一个著名的例子是沃纳态,它纠缠在<math>p{sym}</math>的某些值上,但总是可以用局部隐藏变量来描述。此外,研究还表明,对于任意数目的当事方,存在真正纠缠但允许局部模型的态。
      第325行: 第326行:  
The mentioned proofs about the existence of local models assume that there is only one copy of the quantum state available at a time. If the parties are allowed to perform local measurements on many copies of such states, then many apparently local states (e.g., the qubit Werner states) can no longer be described by a local model. This is, in particular, true for all distillable states. However, it remains an open question whether all entangled states become non-local given sufficiently many copies.
 
The mentioned proofs about the existence of local models assume that there is only one copy of the quantum state available at a time. If the parties are allowed to perform local measurements on many copies of such states, then many apparently local states (e.g., the qubit Werner states) can no longer be described by a local model. This is, in particular, true for all distillable states. However, it remains an open question whether all entangled states become non-local given sufficiently many copies.
   −
上述关于局域模型存在性的证明假设一次只有一个量子态的副本可用。如果允许各方对这些状态的许多副本进行局部测量,那么许多表面上的局部状态(例如,量子位维尔纳状态)就不能再用局部模型来描述。对于所有的可提取态来说,情况尤其如此。然而,如果给定足够多的副本,是否所有纠缠态都成为非局域态,这仍然是一个有待解决的问题。
+
上述关于局部模型存在性的证明假设一次只有一个量子态的副本可用。如果允许当事方对这些态的许多副本进行局部测量,那么许多明显的局部态(例如量子比特-沃纳态)就不能再由局部模型来描述。这尤其适用于所有蒸馏态。然而,当有足够多的拷贝时,所有的纠缠态是否都变成非局域态仍是一个悬而未决的问题。
    
(In fact similar paradoxes can arise even without entanglement: the position of a single particle is spread out over space, and two widely separated detectors attempting to detect the particle in two different places must instantaneously attain appropriate correlation, so that they do not both detect the particle.)
 
(In fact similar paradoxes can arise even without entanglement: the position of a single particle is spread out over space, and two widely separated detectors attempting to detect the particle in two different places must instantaneously attain appropriate correlation, so that they do not both detect the particle.)
 
+
(事实上,即使没有纠缠,也会出现类似的悖论:单个粒子的位置分布在空间上,两个试图在两个不同位置检测粒子的大范围分离的探测器必须立即获得适当的相关性,这样它们就不会同时检测到粒子。)
       
In short, entanglement of a state shared by two parties is necessary but not sufficient for that state to be non-local. It is important to recognize that entanglement is more commonly viewed as an algebraic concept, noted for being a prerequisite to non-locality as well as to quantum teleportation and to superdense coding, whereas non-locality is defined according to experimental statistics and is much more involved with the foundations and interpretations of quantum mechanics.
 
In short, entanglement of a state shared by two parties is necessary but not sufficient for that state to be non-local. It is important to recognize that entanglement is more commonly viewed as an algebraic concept, noted for being a prerequisite to non-locality as well as to quantum teleportation and to superdense coding, whereas non-locality is defined according to experimental statistics and is much more involved with the foundations and interpretations of quantum mechanics.
   −
简而言之,双方共享的态的纠缠是必要的,但不足以使该态成为非局域态。重要的是要认识到纠缠通常被看作是一个代数概念,因为它是非定域性以及量子遥传和超密编码的先决条件,而非定域性是根据实验统计数据定义的,更多地涉及到基础和量子力学诠释。
+
简言之,双方共享的一个状态的纠缠是必要的,但不足以使该状态成为非局部的。必须认识到,纠缠更普遍地被视为一个代数概念,因为它是非定域性、量子隐形传态和超密集编码的先决条件,而非定域性是根据实验统计定义的,它更多地涉及到量子力学的基础和解释。
   −
=== Hidden variables theory ===
+
=== Hidden variables theory 隐藏变量理论===
    
A possible resolution to the paradox is to assume that quantum theory is incomplete, and the result of measurements depends on predetermined "hidden variables".<ref>{{Cite news|url=https://www.scientificamerican.com/article/cosmic-test-bolsters-einsteins-ldquo-spooky-action-at-a-distance-rdquo/?WT.mc_id=SA_FB_PHYS_NEWS|title=Cosmic Test Bolsters Einstein's "Spooky Action at a Distance"|last=magazine|first=Elizabeth Gibney, Nature|newspaper=Scientific American|language=en|access-date=2017-02-04}}</ref>  The state of the particles being measured contains some [[hidden-variable theory|hidden variables]], whose values effectively determine, right from the moment of separation, what the outcomes of the spin measurements are going to be. This would mean that each particle carries all the required information with it, and nothing needs to be transmitted from one particle to the other at the time of measurement. Einstein and others (see the previous section) originally believed  this was the only way out of the paradox, and the accepted quantum mechanical description (with a random measurement outcome) must be incomplete.
 
A possible resolution to the paradox is to assume that quantum theory is incomplete, and the result of measurements depends on predetermined "hidden variables".<ref>{{Cite news|url=https://www.scientificamerican.com/article/cosmic-test-bolsters-einsteins-ldquo-spooky-action-at-a-distance-rdquo/?WT.mc_id=SA_FB_PHYS_NEWS|title=Cosmic Test Bolsters Einstein's "Spooky Action at a Distance"|last=magazine|first=Elizabeth Gibney, Nature|newspaper=Scientific American|language=en|access-date=2017-02-04}}</ref>  The state of the particles being measured contains some [[hidden-variable theory|hidden variables]], whose values effectively determine, right from the moment of separation, what the outcomes of the spin measurements are going to be. This would mean that each particle carries all the required information with it, and nothing needs to be transmitted from one particle to the other at the time of measurement. Einstein and others (see the previous section) originally believed  this was the only way out of the paradox, and the accepted quantum mechanical description (with a random measurement outcome) must be incomplete.
第343行: 第344行:  
The following subsections are for those with a good working knowledge of the formal, mathematical description of quantum mechanics, including familiarity with the formalism and theoretical framework developed in the articles: bra–ket notation and mathematical formulation of quantum mechanics.
 
The following subsections are for those with a good working knowledge of the formal, mathematical description of quantum mechanics, including familiarity with the formalism and theoretical framework developed in the articles: bra–ket notation and mathematical formulation of quantum mechanics.
   −
下面的小节适合那些对量子力学的形式和数学描述有良好工作知识的人,包括对文章中开发的形式主义和理论框架的熟悉: bra-ket 符号和量子力学的数学表述。
+
以下小节是为那些对量子力学的形式化、数学描述有良好工作知识的人准备的,包括熟悉文章中发展的形式主义和理论框架:bra–ket符号和量子力学的数学公式。
   −
=== Violations of Bell's inequality ===
+
=== Violations of Bell's inequality 贝尔不等式的违反===
    
Local hidden variable theories fail, however, when measurements of the spin of entangled particles along different axes are considered. If a large number of pairs of such measurements are made (on a large number of pairs of entangled particles), then statistically, if the [[local realism|local realist]] or hidden variables view were correct, the results would always satisfy [[Bell's inequality]]. A [[Bell test experiments|number of experiments]] have shown in practice that Bell's inequality is not satisfied. However, prior to 2015, all of these had loophole problems that were considered the most important by the community of physicists.<ref>{{citation |author1=I. Gerhardt |author2=Q. Liu |author3=A. Lamas-Linares |author4=J. Skaar |author5=V. Scarani |author6=V. Makarov |author7=C. Kurtsiefer |year=2011 |title=Experimentally faking the violation of Bell's inequalities |journal=Phys. Rev. Lett. |volume=107 |issue=17 |page=170404 |arxiv=1106.3224 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevLett.107.170404 |bibcode=2011PhRvL.107q0404G |pmid=22107491|s2cid=16306493 }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal | last1 = Santos | first1 = E | year = 2004 | title = The failure to perform a loophole-free test of Bell's Inequality supports local realism | url = | journal = Foundations of Physics | volume = 34 | issue = 11| pages = 1643–1673 | doi=10.1007/s10701-004-1308-z|bibcode = 2004FoPh...34.1643S | s2cid = 123642560 }}</ref> When measurements of the entangled particles are made in moving [[special relativity|relativistic]] reference frames, in which each measurement (in its own relativistic time frame) occurs before the other, the measurement results remain correlated.<ref>{{cite journal |author = H. Zbinden |title = Experimental test of nonlocal quantum correlations in relativistic configurations |journal = Phys. Rev. A |volume = 63 |issue = 2 |pages = 22111 |doi = 10.1103/PhysRevA.63.022111|year = 2001|arxiv = quant-ph/0007009 |bibcode = 2001PhRvA..63b2111Z |display-authors = 1 |last2 = Gisin |last3 = Tittel |s2cid = 44611890 |url = http://archive-ouverte.unige.ch/unige:37034 }}</ref><ref name=LG>Some of the history of both referenced Zbinden, et al. experiments is provided in Gilder, L., ''The Age of Entanglement'', Vintage Books, 2008, pp. 321–324.</ref>
 
Local hidden variable theories fail, however, when measurements of the spin of entangled particles along different axes are considered. If a large number of pairs of such measurements are made (on a large number of pairs of entangled particles), then statistically, if the [[local realism|local realist]] or hidden variables view were correct, the results would always satisfy [[Bell's inequality]]. A [[Bell test experiments|number of experiments]] have shown in practice that Bell's inequality is not satisfied. However, prior to 2015, all of these had loophole problems that were considered the most important by the community of physicists.<ref>{{citation |author1=I. Gerhardt |author2=Q. Liu |author3=A. Lamas-Linares |author4=J. Skaar |author5=V. Scarani |author6=V. Makarov |author7=C. Kurtsiefer |year=2011 |title=Experimentally faking the violation of Bell's inequalities |journal=Phys. Rev. Lett. |volume=107 |issue=17 |page=170404 |arxiv=1106.3224 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevLett.107.170404 |bibcode=2011PhRvL.107q0404G |pmid=22107491|s2cid=16306493 }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal | last1 = Santos | first1 = E | year = 2004 | title = The failure to perform a loophole-free test of Bell's Inequality supports local realism | url = | journal = Foundations of Physics | volume = 34 | issue = 11| pages = 1643–1673 | doi=10.1007/s10701-004-1308-z|bibcode = 2004FoPh...34.1643S | s2cid = 123642560 }}</ref> When measurements of the entangled particles are made in moving [[special relativity|relativistic]] reference frames, in which each measurement (in its own relativistic time frame) occurs before the other, the measurement results remain correlated.<ref>{{cite journal |author = H. Zbinden |title = Experimental test of nonlocal quantum correlations in relativistic configurations |journal = Phys. Rev. A |volume = 63 |issue = 2 |pages = 22111 |doi = 10.1103/PhysRevA.63.022111|year = 2001|arxiv = quant-ph/0007009 |bibcode = 2001PhRvA..63b2111Z |display-authors = 1 |last2 = Gisin |last3 = Tittel |s2cid = 44611890 |url = http://archive-ouverte.unige.ch/unige:37034 }}</ref><ref name=LG>Some of the history of both referenced Zbinden, et al. experiments is provided in Gilder, L., ''The Age of Entanglement'', Vintage Books, 2008, pp. 321–324.</ref>
第353行: 第354行:  
Consider two arbitrary quantum systems  and , with respective Hilbert spaces  and . The Hilbert space of the composite system is the tensor product
 
Consider two arbitrary quantum systems  and , with respective Hilbert spaces  and . The Hilbert space of the composite system is the tensor product
   −
考虑两个任意的量子系统和,分别具有希尔伯特空间和。复合系统的 Hilbert 空间是张量积
+
考虑两个任意的量子系统,分别用Hilbert空间和(?)。复合系统的Hilbert空间是张量积
    
The fundamental issue about measuring spin along different axes is that these measurements cannot have definite values at the same time―they are [[Incompatible observables|incompatible]] in the sense that these measurements' maximum simultaneous precision is constrained by the [[uncertainty principle]]. This is contrary to what is found in classical physics, where any number of properties can be measured simultaneously with arbitrary accuracy. It has been proven mathematically that compatible measurements cannot show Bell-inequality-violating correlations,<ref>{{cite journal|last1=Cirel'son|first1=B. S.|title=Quantum generalizations of Bell's inequality|journal=Letters in Mathematical Physics|volume=4|issue=2|pages=93–100| year=1980|doi=10.1007/BF00417500|bibcode=1980LMaPh...4...93C|s2cid=120680226}}</ref> and thus entanglement is a fundamentally non-classical phenomenon.
 
The fundamental issue about measuring spin along different axes is that these measurements cannot have definite values at the same time―they are [[Incompatible observables|incompatible]] in the sense that these measurements' maximum simultaneous precision is constrained by the [[uncertainty principle]]. This is contrary to what is found in classical physics, where any number of properties can be measured simultaneously with arbitrary accuracy. It has been proven mathematically that compatible measurements cannot show Bell-inequality-violating correlations,<ref>{{cite journal|last1=Cirel'son|first1=B. S.|title=Quantum generalizations of Bell's inequality|journal=Letters in Mathematical Physics|volume=4|issue=2|pages=93–100| year=1980|doi=10.1007/BF00417500|bibcode=1980LMaPh...4...93C|s2cid=120680226}}</ref> and thus entanglement is a fundamentally non-classical phenomenon.
第364行: 第365行:     
Entanglement is required to preserve the [[Uncertainty principle]], as seen in the EPR paradox. For example, say that a high energy photon decays into an electron / positron pair, and the position of the electron and the momentum of the positron are then measured. If we don't allow entanglement in the physical description of the pair, the position and momentum of each particle can still be deduced by reference to the conservation of momentum, violating the Uncertainty principle. Alternatively, if we require the uncertainty principle to hold true, and still disallow entanglement in the physical description of the pair, the uncertainty principle would allow violations in the law of conservation of momentum, because strong correlation in both position and momentum would be impossible (i.e., one would not be able to effectively deduce the position and momentum of the electron because they could not be highly correlated with both the position and momentum of the positron).-->
 
Entanglement is required to preserve the [[Uncertainty principle]], as seen in the EPR paradox. For example, say that a high energy photon decays into an electron / positron pair, and the position of the electron and the momentum of the positron are then measured. If we don't allow entanglement in the physical description of the pair, the position and momentum of each particle can still be deduced by reference to the conservation of momentum, violating the Uncertainty principle. Alternatively, if we require the uncertainty principle to hold true, and still disallow entanglement in the physical description of the pair, the uncertainty principle would allow violations in the law of conservation of momentum, because strong correlation in both position and momentum would be impossible (i.e., one would not be able to effectively deduce the position and momentum of the electron because they could not be highly correlated with both the position and momentum of the positron).-->
 
+
纠缠是保持[[不确定性原理]]所必需的,如EPR悖论所示。例如,假设一个高能光子衰变成电子/正电子对,然后测量电子的位置和正电子的动量。如果在对的物理描述中不允许纠缠,那么每个粒子的位置和动量仍然可以通过动量守恒来推导,这违反了测不准原理。或者,如果我们要求测不准原理成立,并且仍然不允许在对的物理描述中纠缠,那么测不准原理将允许违反动量守恒定律,因为位置和动量之间的强相关性是不可能的(即人们无法有效地推断电子的位置和动量,因为它们不能与正电子的位置和动量高度相关。-->
      第371行: 第372行:  
如果第一个系统处于状态 < math > scriptstyle | psi rangle _ a </math > ,而第二个系统处于状态 < math > scriptstyle | phi rangle _ b </math > ,则复合系统的状态为
 
如果第一个系统处于状态 < math > scriptstyle | psi rangle _ a </math > ,而第二个系统处于状态 < math > scriptstyle | phi rangle _ b </math > ,则复合系统的状态为
   −
=== Other types of experiments ===
+
=== Other types of experiments其他类型的试验 ===
    
In experiments in 2012 and 2013, polarization correlation was created between photons that never coexisted in time.<ref name="Xiao-song2012">{{cite journal |author=Xiao-song Ma, Stefan Zotter, Johannes Kofler, Rupert Ursin, Thomas Jennewein, Časlav Brukner & Anton Zeilinger |title=Experimental delayed-choice entanglement swapping |journal=Nature Physics |volume=8 |issue=6 |pages=480–485 |date=26 April 2012 |doi=10.1038/nphys2294|arxiv = 1203.4834 |bibcode = 2012NatPh...8..480M |last2=Zotter |last3=Kofler |last4=Ursin |last5=Jennewein |last6=Brukner |last7=Zeilinger |s2cid=119208488 }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal | last1 = Megidish | first1 = E. | last2 = Halevy | first2 = A. | last3 = Shacham | first3 = T. | last4 = Dvir | first4 = T. | last5 = Dovrat | first5 = L. | last6 = Eisenberg | first6 = H. S. | year = 2013 | title = Entanglement Swapping between Photons that have Never Coexisted | url = | journal = Physical Review Letters | volume = 110 | issue = 21| page = 210403| doi=10.1103/physrevlett.110.210403|arxiv = 1209.4191 |bibcode = 2013PhRvL.110u0403M | pmid=23745845| s2cid = 30063749 }}</ref> The authors claimed that this result was achieved by [[Quantum teleportation#Entanglement swapping|entanglement swapping]] between two pairs of entangled photons after measuring the polarization of one photon of the early pair, and that it proves that quantum non-locality applies not only to space but also to time.
 
In experiments in 2012 and 2013, polarization correlation was created between photons that never coexisted in time.<ref name="Xiao-song2012">{{cite journal |author=Xiao-song Ma, Stefan Zotter, Johannes Kofler, Rupert Ursin, Thomas Jennewein, Časlav Brukner & Anton Zeilinger |title=Experimental delayed-choice entanglement swapping |journal=Nature Physics |volume=8 |issue=6 |pages=480–485 |date=26 April 2012 |doi=10.1038/nphys2294|arxiv = 1203.4834 |bibcode = 2012NatPh...8..480M |last2=Zotter |last3=Kofler |last4=Ursin |last5=Jennewein |last6=Brukner |last7=Zeilinger |s2cid=119208488 }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal | last1 = Megidish | first1 = E. | last2 = Halevy | first2 = A. | last3 = Shacham | first3 = T. | last4 = Dvir | first4 = T. | last5 = Dovrat | first5 = L. | last6 = Eisenberg | first6 = H. S. | year = 2013 | title = Entanglement Swapping between Photons that have Never Coexisted | url = | journal = Physical Review Letters | volume = 110 | issue = 21| page = 210403| doi=10.1103/physrevlett.110.210403|arxiv = 1209.4191 |bibcode = 2013PhRvL.110u0403M | pmid=23745845| s2cid = 30063749 }}</ref> The authors claimed that this result was achieved by [[Quantum teleportation#Entanglement swapping|entanglement swapping]] between two pairs of entangled photons after measuring the polarization of one photon of the early pair, and that it proves that quantum non-locality applies not only to space but also to time.
153

个编辑

导航菜单